You are on page 1of 18

An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace

Author(s): Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siverson and Alastair
Smith
Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 93, No. 4 (Dec., 1999), pp. 791-807
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2586113
Accessed: 30-08-2016 13:53 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

Cambridge University Press, American Political Science Association are collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4 December 1999

An Institutional Explanation of the Democr


BRUCE BUENO DE MESQUITA Hoover Institution
JAMES D. MORROW Hoover Institution
RANDOLPH M. SIVERSON University of California, Davis
ALASTAIR SMITH Yale University
Wo He examine formally the link between domestic political institutions and policy choices in the
context of eight empirical regularities that constitute the democratic peace. We demonstrate that
democratic leaders, when faced with war, are more inclined to shift extra resources into the war
effort than are autocrats. This follows because the survival of political leaders with larger winning coalitions
hinges on successful policy. The extra effort made by democrats provides a military advantage over autocrats.
This makes democrats unattractive targets, since their institutional constraints cause them to mobilize
resources for the war effort. In addition to trying harder, democrats are more selective in their choice of
targets. Because defeat is more likely to lead to domestic replacement for democrats than for autocrats,
democrats only initiate wars they expect to win. These two factors lead to the interaction between polities that
is often referred to as the democratic peace.

T he study of international relations has produced wars they initiate, democracies pay fewer costs in terms
few widely accepted generalizations. One of of human life and fight shorter wars than nondemo-
these, sometimes even asserted to be an empir- cratic states (Bennett and Stam 1996; Siverson 1995).
ical law (Levy 1988), is that democracies do not fight (6) Transitional democracies appear more likely to
wars with one another. The empirical evidence for this fight than stable regimes (Mansfield and Snyder 1995;
claim is quite strong (Bremer 1992; Maoz and Abdolali Ward and Gleditsch 1998). (7) Larger democracies
1989; Oneal and Russett 1997; Ray 1995). Recent seem more constrained to avoid war than do smaller
efforts to cast this empirical observation in doubt democracies (Morgan and Campbell 1991).
notwithstanding (Farber and Gowa 1995; Layne 1994; Although these observations about democracy and
Schwartz and Skinner 1997; Spiro 1994), extensive, war are part of an important pattern, they lack a
rigorous statistical tests all show a significant propen- coherent explanation. Several possibilities have been
sity for democracies to be nearly immune from wars put forward, but none has gained broad acceptance.
with one another (Maoz 1998; Russett 1995). Associ- We propose a game-theoretic model that may help
ated with this so-called democratic peace are seven bring closure to the debate on the causal mechanism
additional empirical regularities related to war prone- governing the eight regularities mentioned above. The
ness and democracy, all based on empirical observa- model will be shown to account for the empirical
tions. (1) Democracies are not at all immune from record regarding the first six of the eight patterns. The
fighting wars with nondemocracies (Maoz and Abdolali regularities concerning transitional democracies
1989).1 (2) Democracies tend to win a disproportionate (Mansfield and Snyder 1995; Ward and Gleditsch
share of the wars they fight (Lake 1992; Reiter and 1998) and the constraints on great power democracies
Stam 1998b). (3) When disputes do emerge, demo- (Morgan and Campbell 1991) are stated in monadic
cratic dyads choose more peaceful processes of dispute form. These regularities cannot be evaluated in terms
settlement than do other pairings of states (Brecher of a model of strategic interaction without additional
and Wilkenfeld 1997; Dixon 1994; Mousseau 1998; information. Specifically, without data on the demo-
Raymond 1994). (4) Democracies are more likely to cratic state's adversary, we cannot evaluate the relevant
initiate wars against autocracies than are autocracies institutional and resource relationships. We will pro-
against democracies (Bennett and Stam 1998). (5) In vide an interpretation of our model that is consistent
with both monadic results, but we cannot undertake a
more rigorous assessment.
Bruce Bueno de Mesquita is Senior Fellow and James D. Morrow is
Senior Research Fellow, the Hoover Institution, Stanford University,
Stanford CA 94305-6010, Randolph Siverson is Professor of Political
Science, University of California, Davis, CA 95616, and Alastair
THE DEBATE
Smith is Assistant Professor of Political Science, Yale University,
New Haven, CT 06520-8301. The debate over the war behavior of democratic states,
The research reported here was supported by the National Science
and particularly the democratic peace, centers on
Foundation under grant SBR-9409225. We are greatly indebted to
Raymond E. Wolfinger for his facilitation of this research and to
whether a normative or an institutional explanation
David Austen-Smith, Fiona McGillivray, Will Moore, Bruce Russett, best accounts for the known facts (Thompson and
Kiron Skinner, Allan Stam, and several anonymous referees for their Tucker 1997). Normative accounts focus on several
helpful comments. different presumptions about democracies. One such
1 Some studies suggest that democracies are, on the whole, more
supposition is that they share a common value system,
pacific than autocracies (Benoit 1996; Ray 1995). Yet, such general
war avoidance cannot account for their relative propensity to fight including respect for individual liberties and competi-
with different regime types. tion. As stated by Dixon (1994, 17):

791

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

international disputes of democratic states are in the hands comes of conflict between democratic states. The in-
of individuals who have experienced the politics of com- ternational and domestic norms are induced from the
peting values and interests and who have consistently observed patterns of behavior in international conflicts
responded within the normative guidelines of bounded
that these arguments seek to explain. That democracies
competition. In situations where both parties to a dispute
are willing to abandon their normative commitment to
are democracies, not only do both sides subscribe to these
the peaceful resolution of disputes in the face of a
norms, but the leaders of both are also fully cognizant that
bounded competition is the norm, both for themselves and threat to their survival by another state that does not
their opponents. adhere to those norms is entirely plausible. In order to
qualify as an explanation of the observation, however,
A closely related argument is that citizens in democ- that assertion must be derived independently of the
racies abhor violence and so constrain their leaders observation, either from prior axioms or from unre-
from pursuing violent foreign policies. As succinctly lated empirical evidence. Otherwise, we cannot know
explained by Morgan and Campbell (1991, 189), "the what the argument predicts about seemingly contradic-
key feature of democracy is government by the people tory patterns of evidence. For instance, analyses by
and ... the people, who must bear the costs of war, are James and Mitchell (1995) and Forsythe (1992) of
usually unwilling to fight." Adherents of these perspec- covert operations suggest that, providing democratic
tives also argue, however, that democracies are willing leaders can escape public scrutiny, they often under-
to set aside their abhorrence of violence or their take violent acts against other democracies. Does such
respect for other points of view when they confront evidence contradict a norms-based arguments, or do
authoritarian states, because the latter do not share the norms apply only to interstate conflict at the level of
these common values. As stated by Maoz and Russett crises and war?
(1993, 625), "when a democratic state confronts a Second, a related difficulty is empirical. The histori-
nondemocratic one, it may be forced to adapt to the cal record is replete with democratic states that fol-
norms of international conflict of the latter lest it be lowed policies at variance with the norms argument.
exploited or eliminated by the nondemocratic state Many democratic states pursued imperialistic policies
that takes advantage of the inherent moderation of and, in building empires, engaged in wars that were
democracies." about subjugation rather than self-protection. It may
We believe that any explanation of the democratic be correct to argue that democratic states resort to
peace must satisfy two criteria. First, it must account realist strategies in the face of a powerful nondemo-
for the known regularities that are often grouped cratic opponent who threatens their existence, but too
together to define the democratic peace. An explana- many democratic wars have been against significantly
tion that accounts for all the regularities obviously is weaker states for this argument to be sustained as an
more comprehensive than those that account for only explanation for the democratic peace. It is difficult to
some. Furthermore, because the extant explanations reconcile such a pattern with democratic political cul-
are generally constructed in response to the observed ture. The explanation we propose, by contrast, explains
regularities, the more patterns that are explained, the the willingness of democracies to undertake imperial-
more credible the explanation, provided that it does istic or colonial conquest. This observation is the sort
not come at the expense of parsimony. Second, we of novel fact for which an explanation of the demo-
believe that a credible explanation also should suggest cratic peace should account, and we return later to our
novel hypotheses that do not form part of the corpus ofexplanation of imperial wars by democracies.
the democratic peace. Further credibility to the overall The institutional-constraints argument holds that
explanation is added if these novel hypotheses are democracies are more deliberate in their decision
borne out by the evidence. making than autocracies because their procedures pre-
The existing norms-based and institutional-con- clude unilateral action by leaders. This is thought to
straints arguments fail both tests. The model we pro- raise the costs of violence. Maoz and Russett (1993,
pose provides a direct explanation of six regularities 626) state: "Due to the complexity of the democratic
and an account consistent with the two nondyadic process and the requirement of securing a broad base
regularities mentioned earlier and suggests numerous of support for risky policies, democratic leaders are
novel hypotheses that are supported by evidence. reluctant to wage wars, except in cases wherein war
Later, for instance, we show that our theory implies seems a necessity or when the war aims are seen as
that democracies devote more resources to their war justifying the mobilization costs."2 This suggests, how-
efforts than do nondemocracies. We cite independently ever, that democracies should be unlikely to wage war
derived evidence. In addition, we have shown else- generally, not just against other democracies.
where that the institutional model we propose also The empirical record does not support such a con-
accounts for variation in economic growth across re- clusion.3 Rather, it shows that democracies do not fight
gimes and explains why leaders with failed public one another but do indeed engage in wars with author-
policies tend to last in office longer than leaders with
successful policies (Bueno de Mesquita et al. n.d.).
There are two difficulties with the norms-based 2 Without some specification of war aims and mobilization costs, the
last phrase of this statement allows anything with respect to demo-
arguments in the literature. First, the arguments ap-
cratic war behavior.
pear to be ad hoc. The presence and substance of 3 Benoit (1996) suggests that on average democracies are slightly less
norms are established solely by reference to the out- war prone than other systems.

792

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

itarian regimes.4 The argument based on the cheapness disenfranchised citizens with no say in the choice of
of expressing opposition seems stronger than the other leadership. All members of S have the right to partic-
putative institutional explanations, but it also has short- ipate in choosing the government. A subset of the
comings, one of which is its failure to account for the selectorate forms a winning coalition, which we denote
well-known rally-round-the-flag effect observed in de- as W. Members of the winning coalition are those
mocracies at the outset of crises and wars (Mueller people whose support is required to keep the incum-
1973; Norpoth 1987). This effect suggests that there is bent in office. If the incumbent cannot find W members
not an inherent abhorrence of violence in democracies. of the selectorate to support her, then she is removed
Most important from a theoretical position, none of from office.6 Since we assume that leaders are keen to
the institutional-constraints arguments has a suffi- stay in power, they are eager to satisfy members of the
ciently well-developed theory of how and why demo- winning coalition.
cratic institutions constrain leaders in the particular Typical categories of regimes can be related to the
way that produces the eight regularities observed, institutional variables on which we focus. In a democ-
whereas other institutional arrangements do not. racy with universal suffrage, for instance, S is approxi-
Rather, these arguments generally just assert that mately equal to N, and W is large, typically being a
democratic leaders are more constrained. majority of S. In monarchies and military juntas, W and
Bueno de Mesquita and Lalman's (1992) signaling S are typically small relative to N. In some authoritar-
explanation accounts for three of the eight observed ian states, S is quite large, and in others it is very small,
regularities, but it does not, for instance, explain why while W is always small in such systems. In a communist
democracies win a disproportionate share of their wars state, for instance, S has typically been a figure between
or why their costs are lower. Bueno. de Mesquita and just the members of the Communist Party (i.e., 57
Siverson's (1995) model accounts for these regularities million people in China) and all citizens, since univer-
but not for the democratic peace. Both those models sal suffrage (in largely meaningless elections) is com-
have in common the assumption that democracies are monplace for such systems. Authoritarian regimes are
more constrained than autocracies. For reasons of often characterized by rigged elections in which S is
theoretical parsimony, however, we prefer that this be large, but this has little effect on actual governance
a deductive result of a general model rather than an other than to raise the risks for members of W if they
assumption. That is, we wish to account for the several defect from the incumbent, as we explain below.
empirical regularities without assuming that one type Incumbent leaders (as individuals or as a governing
of political system is more constrained than another. coalition) select and implement public policies, which
Instead, we will demonstrate how institutional arrange- inevitably have a public goods component and a private
ments produce different levels of constraint in different goods component. Leaders have only limited resources
political systems and what effect those institutional to allocate to different policy goals and to help keep
arrangements have on behavioral incentives and the them in office. They can put everything into public
empirical generalizations of interest. policy that benefits everyone in the polity, everything
Our explanation shows that the behavioral incen- into private goods that are consumed only by members
tives-these could be called norms-are endogenous of the winning coalition, or any mix in between. If they
to certain political institutions and the interests that spend resources on, for instance, providing defense for
sustain them.5 We make no claims about the citizens' the citizenry, then they cannot use those same re-
abhorrence of violence or the ease with which they sources to provide special privileges to the members of
might protest government policies. In fact, we assume the winning coalition. If they buy the necessities of
that political leaders in all systems are motivated by the national defense only from cronies in the winning
same universal interest: They desire to remain in office. coalition, then the reduced competition to provide
We make no normative assumptions about differences defense results in an inefficient provision of that public
in the values or goals of democratic leaders or their good while cronies skim money off the top for their
followers as compared to authoritarian leaders or their personal gain. Thus, scarcity necessarily requires lead-
followers. ers to make choices over just how much to focus their
limited time and other resources on providing gener-
ally beneficial public policies and how much to focus on
POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS
just satisfying the wants of their core supporters.
All polities are characterized by institutional rules The main concerns here are to identify how re-
pertaining to the role of citizens in influencing the sources are allocated during an international dispute,
selection of government leaders. Let any polity consist given variations in institutional arrangements; to iden-
of N citizens. Let S be the subset of N that participates
in the selection of the political leadership. We call this
6 The theory we develop does not require that we assume minimal
subset the selectorate. Then N - S is the set of winning coalitions (Riker 1962). Indeed, the results generalize
straightforwardly to any defined magnitude for W. Yet, it makes
4 Although democracies do not fight wars with one another, they most sense to begin from a minimal winning context because that
often become engaged in militarized disputes (Oneal and Russett appears to be incentive compatible with the objective of leaders to
1997). See Senese (1997) for an alternative viewpoint. maximize their gains. A central question of interest to us here is how
5 Earlier work demonstrates the endogenous relationship of institu- W is selected, including the selection of W such that it deviates from
tions to foreign policy interests (Bueno de Mesquita and Siverson minimal winning. The comparative static analysis we undertake
1995; McGillivray 1997; Schultz 1996). focuses in part on that question.

793

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

tify whatever dependencies exist between regime type perforce cannot give a large amount of such benefits to
and war participation and outcomes; and to evaluate each member of their winning coalition.
the prospects that leaders are retained in office as a Democratic leaders are more likely to try hard to win
function of institutional arrangements. These issues their wars than are autocrats. If they do not expect to
influence whether leaders concentrate resources on the win, then they try to avoid fighting; This implies that
pursuit of national goals or on benefits to key constit- they pick and choose their conflicts carefully, which has
uents. In showing that this is true, we explain the several consequences. Democrats are more likely to
empirical regularities that constitute the democratic win wars than autocrats for two reasons. First, if they
peace. need to, democrats try hard, spending resources on the
Before turning to the formal representation, we war to advance their public policy goals (Reiter and
pause to describe the basic structure of our model and Stam 1998b). Second, fearing public policy failure,
outline the intuition that leads to the democratic peace democrats try to avoid contests they do not think they
result. We start by assuming that two nations, A and B, can win. Since two democrats in a dispute both try
are engaged in a dispute. National leaders must decide hard, both can anticipate that, if they go to war, each
whether to start a war in the hope of achieving their will spend lots of resources in a risky situation in which
objectives or rely instead on a negotiated settlement. If neither is disproportionately advantaged by greater
war occurs, then leaders must decide how much effort effort. Therefore, democrats are generally inclined to
to make to achieve military victory. By this we mean negotiate with one another rather than fight (Lake
what proportion of available resources a leader is 1992; Stam 1996, 176-8). By contrast, autocrats typi-
prepared to allocate to the war effort rather than to cally reserve their resources for domestic uses, as their
political survival depends on satisfying key constituents
other purposes. Obviously, leaders-who dedicate large
through the distribution of private goods. Autocrats do
quantities of resources to the war are more likely to
not have a great need to produce successful public
win, but at the cost of not having those resources
policies. Consequently, they try less hard than demo-
available to reward their supporters. The citizens re-
crats in war, and they sometimes fight wars in which
ceive payoffs based on the outcome of the crisis-be it
their chances are poor because defeat does not so
a war or a negotiated settlement-and the rewards that
greatly affect their prospects of political survival at
accrue from resources not consumed in the war effort.
home. Democrats, by their superior level of effort,
Given these payoffs, the winning coalition decides
often defeat autocratic foes and achieve successful
whether to retain or replace the current leader.
policy outcomes. This helps enhance their reselection.
A polity's institutional arrangements shape the se-
lection criteria that supporters use to determine
whether to retain the incumbent. Hence, political
institutions determine which outcomes allow a leader THE GAME
to keep her job and which do not. As we shall see, these
We assume that two nations, A and B, are engaged in
differences shape the policies that leaders choose.
a dispute. Our model examines the fundamental deci-
Citizens in general enjoy the benefits of public
sions that national leaders make under this contin-
policies, whether or not they belong to the winning
gency. In the game, leaders choose to fight or to
coalition. The advantage that members of W have is
negotiate a settlement. If the choice is to fight, then
that they also enjoy ashare of whatever private goods leaders decide how many of their available resources
are allocated by the leadership. On average, each they are prepared to commit to the war effort. In
member of W receives a share of private goods equal to reality, of course, either side in a dispute can resort to
RIW, where R is the available pool of resources and W war. We, however, consider the restricted game in
is the size of the winning coalition. which the leader in nation A chooses between the use
As the winning coalition increases, holding the bud- of force and a negotiated settlement. If she decides to
get constant, each member's share of private goods attack, then she also picks an effort level, by which we
decreases. This makes public policy benefits loom
mean she allocates some proportion, gA, of her avail-
larger in the overall utility assessment of members of able resources, RA, to the conduct of the war. Once
the winning coalition in more democratic polities as attacked, the leader in nation B also picks an effort
compared to autocracies. One consequence is that level, gB. If nation A decides not to attack, then the
democratic leaders, being just as eager to retain office dispute is settled peacefully through negotiations.
as their authoritarian counterparts, must be especially The war's outcome is a function of the relative effort
concerned about policy failure. Toreduce the risk of by each side. That is, who wins depends in part on how
policy failure and subsequent ..deposition, they make a leaders choose to allocate their limited resources.
larger effort to succeed in disputes. This means that When the dispute is settled, either through negotiation
they are willing to spend more resources on war effort or war, the domestic audiences in A and B then decide
and only engage in fights they anticipate winning. In whether to retain or to depose the incumbent (Fearon
contrast, leaders with small winning coalitions reserve 1994; Smith 1998). To make this decision, they evaluate
more resources for distribution to their supporters in their payoffs under each contingency and decide
the form of private goods. As long as they can provide whether they are better off remaining in the incum-
substantial private goods, they are at less risk of being bent's winning coalition or defecting to a prospective
deposed than are their democratic counterparts, who new leader.

794

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

Structure of the Game of modeling this process is to treatpA as the probability


that a random variable a, with distribution 4>(E), is less
1. The leader in nation A chooses between war and
negotiations. If she selects war, then she also than a function of the variables h (gA, gB, M), a
common example of which is the probit model, where
chooses how hard to fight, gA E [0, 1].
2. If war occurs, then the leader of B, having 4>(E) is the standard normal distribution, and h(gA, g9B
observed
A's effort level, chooses how hard to fight, M)
gB =E M[0,- + gAr - r.7
1].
3. Nature determines the outcome of the war.
4. In each nation, the members of the winning coali- Negotiations
tion, having observed the international outcome and
the level of private goods allocated to them, decide When nations enter negotiations, we assume they have
whether to retain their leader or defect to a domes- expectations about the likely outcome of the bargain-
tic political rival, thereby removing the current ing process. In particular we assume the expected
leader from office. rewards for A and B from a negotiated settlement are

We assume that only A can start a war. This assump- X and 1 - X, respectively. We might suppose this deal,
tion is benign. The question of whether B wants to X, reflects the relative military balance, M, but it need
initiate is answered by simply flipping the labels A and
not. Other factors can also be influential. As Fearon
B. Our central question is how political institutions (1995) points out in his bargaining model, the indivis-
affect crisis behavior. ibility of the policy space, the sustainability of deals in
the future, and the role of current negotiations in
altering the future military balance all influence which
Settling Crises by War deals can be achieved through negotiations.8
We model war as a costly lottery in which each player's The payoff to A from a negotiated settlement is X,
expected utility from the war depends on the probabil- which is enjoyed by all citizens in A. That is, this payoff
ity that its side will win or lose and the utilities is a public good. The citizens in B enjoy the benefit 1 -
associated with each possible outcome. In this section X from negotiation.
we develop our notions regarding the probability of
victory (and defeat) and the attendant utilities. UA(negotiations) = X; UB(negotiations) = 1 - X.
The values of victory and defeat are normalized to
one and zero, respectively. In addition, players pay a Table 1 summarizes the policy payoffs associated
per-capita cost, k, associated with the war's destruction with each possible outcome of the international dis-
and the risks of fighting. Therefore, the utility of victory
pute. We let z represent the generic outcome. Every-
equals 1 - k, and the utility for defeat is -k.
one in A receives the policy payoff VA(z) associated
Many factors shape the outcome of a war. Observ-
with the outcome z, and all members of polity B receive
able military capabilities certainly play an important
the payoff VB(z).
part, as do short-term shifts in government priorities by
putting more national resources behind a war effort
TABLE 1. The Policy Payoffs Associated with
(Kim and Morrow 1992; Organski and Kugler 1980;
International Outcomes
Powell 1996a, 1996b). ~The probability of victory is
presumed to increase as the total military advantage Outcome VA(Z) VB(Z)
dedicated to the war effort by one side grows relative to Negotiations X 1 - X
the other side. Therefore, the victor is likely to be the A wins the war 1 - k -k
nation with the most total military capabilities dedi- A loses the war -k 1 - k
cated to the war.
We consider two types of military capabilities: the
observable military balance, M, and the proportion of
7 Other common examples used in international relations include
additional national resources committed to the war
Bueno de Mesquita, Morrow, and Zorick (1997), who set
effort, gi. The subscript will refer to nation A or B, as
appropriate. The military balance, which takes values
?()={1 if :- 0
between 0 and 1, represents the ratio of observable
military assets of the two sides. Additional resources and h(M, mA, mB, gA, gB) = mA + 2(M - 1) - mB + gAr - gBr,
dedicated to the war by either country are drawn from where mA and mB are intangible military utilities, and the standard
ratio of forces model (see, e.g., Bueno de Mesquita 1981), which sets
the Ri resources each leader has at her disposal. By
choosing to devote the proportion gi of Ri to the war 0 if&OF i
?(? = if ?E C[0, 1]
effort, she generates an additional gir in military assets,
1 if,> 1
where r represents the exchange rate between re-
sources and military capability. and h(M, gA, gB) = (M + rgA)/(l + rgA
examines the implications of variation in these functions.
The probability that A wins in a war, denoted PA =
8 Nations' private information about their capability, which may take
PA (gA, gR, M), is increasing in military balance, M, and the form of intangible military assets of morale and leadership
A's effort, go, and is decreasing in B's effort, gB. The (Reiter and Stam 1998a, 1998b; see also Morrow 1989), also influ-
probability B wins is PB = 1 - PA. A general method ences negotiations.

795

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

Reselection resources, she is uncertain of the qualities of a prospec-


tive domestic rival. We represent the distribution of
Following the international dispute, the leaders in each
possible challengers with the cumulative density func-
nation face reselection. The members of the selector-
ate evaluate the payoff they received under the incum- tion FA(X), where FA(x) = Pr(CA ? x). For technical
convenience, we assume the distribution of challengers
bent. They compare this with what they expect to
is exponential: FA(x) = 1 - e-x
receive if they depose the incumbent and choose a
What can a challenger credibly offer the selectorate?
domestic challenger. Deposition is not simply a matter
He cannot make credible promises regarding how he
of concluding that the leader did a poor job during the
will perform during a dispute or on other policy
dispute. Rather, it is a question of whether the mem-
questions. Knowing this, the selectorate's members
bers of W believe they will be better off under alterna-
focus on the reservation value they expect if they
tive leadership.
choose a new leader. We assume that the reservation
Incumbents are deposed when they can no longer
value for picking the challenger is CA + RAISA.
convince W members of the selectorate to support
Incumbents can anticipate what they must give sup-
them. If the package of benefits an incumbent offers to
porters to defeat challengers. They simply must pro-
her supporters is better than the rewards any chal-
vide more utility for their coalition members than that
lenger can credibly offer, then the incumbent can find
offered by the challenger, or
W members of the selectorate who will retain her in
office. If, however, the incumbent fails to provide RA
benefits to the winning coalition in excess of what a (1 A) - + RA + VA (Z),
challenger can credibly promise to provide, then the
incumbent can no longer garner enough support to where Vi represents the performance of the le
form a winning coalition. At this point, supporters all policy dimensions other than the international
defect, and the incumbent is ousted. dispute. This utility term is quite intuitive. VA (z) is the
Defection is risky. There is no shortage of challeng- utility supporters derive from the outcome of the policy
ers and prospective defectors. Consequently, a member of the leader in the international dispute.10 (1 - gA) is
of the current winning coalition cannot be certain of the proportion of resources reserved for distribution as
being essential to the successor government. That is, by private goods to the winning coalition after spending
defecting, members of the winning coalition place their gA on the war effort. Of course, if there is no war, then
private goods benefits at risk. We characterize that risk gA = 0. The total pool of resources (RA) is diminished
as increasing as the pool of available members for a by whatever portion goes to the war effort, if any. What
winning coalition increases and as decreasing as the remains is distributed evenly to the members of the
necessary size of the winning coalition increases, so winning coalition so that each member receives (1 -
that the risk increases as S increases and decreases as gA) RAIWA. Of note is that members of the winning
W increases. For simplicity's sake, we treat the proba- coalition are assumed to be certain to receive their
bility of being a member of the successor winning share of private goods if they stay with the incumbent,
coalition in A as WAISA. Then, the expected utility but they only receive such goods probabilistically if
from private goods in a new coalition if one defects to they defect. In addition, neither the incumbent nor the
a challenger is simply (RAIWA) (WAISA) = RAISA. challenger can promise to distribute any resources that
Like the incumbent,Athe challenger proposes a mix of are destroyed or lost by the state during a war. This
public and private goods allocations. Of course, the proves important later in understanding why autocrats
selectorate does not know what the challenger can do not make the same allocation decision as demo-
actually deliver, whereas they have observed the per- cratic leaders.
formance of the incumbent. The selectorate must infer Leaders want to remain in office. At the time leaders
the ability of the challenger (Riker 1996). We denote choose their actions, including whether to wage war
the competence, strength, or ability of the challenger in and how to allocate resources, they cannot be certain
A as CA and use comparable notation for the challenger of the quality of prospective political rivals. Yet, given
in B.9 When the incumbent is making choices about the distribution of possible challengers, the incumbent
whether to fight or negotiate and how to allocate can assess how outcomes influence her prospects for
reselection. Leader A remains in office as long as she
9 In autocracies and other nondemocratic regimes, campaigns may offers her winning coalition at least as much as a
not be public but instead take such forms as secret discussions about potential challenger credibly promises. Hence, the
a coup, assassination, or other means to overthrow the incumbent.
probability the incumbent remains in office given out-
Success depends on attracting enough supporters to depose the
sitting government and replace it with one led by the challenger. comezandeffortgAisPr((l - gA)RAIWA + VA(z) +
Because of the risks (captured by our notion that the probability of
being essential to a successor government is equal to WIS), challeng-
ers in autocracies generally operate in secret. It would be a mistake 10 We assume here that all members of society benefit equally from
to believe that challengers do not always exist. Even in the most international outcomes. As earlier work shows (Bueno de Mesquita
autocratic regime there are always people eager to take over the role et al. 1997), however, foreign policy objectives are a function of
of leadership. One obvious indication is that following the sudden institutional arrangements. Countries with small winning coalitions
death of an incumbent there is always someone willing to step in and typically fight for resources that can be targeted as private goods to
assume leadership. Frequently, many people compete for the oppor- the regime's supporters. By contrast, countries with large winning
tunity, although the closest supporters of the leader are the obvious coalitions fight over policies that have larger public goods compo-
candidates. nents.

796

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

[WA 2 CA ? RAISA) = Pr((1 - gA) RAIWA- RAISA + The preceding discussion suggests the incentives of
VA(z) + I-A 2 CA) = F(VA(z) + (1 - gA) RAIWA - leaders. We now specify those formally by denoting the
RAISA + PAA) payoffs to leaders under each contingency they face. In
All else equal, leaders who perform well on other particular, if the outcome of the international dispute is
z and the leader's effort level is gA, and assuming the
issues (large Vi) and those with large selectorates (large
S) find it easiest to remain in office. When the selec- leader also gets the payoffs received by any other
torate is large, challengers can draw their political member of the winning coalition, then the leader's
backing from a large pool of potential supporters. This payoff is:
means supporters of the current incumbent cannot be
/ ~~~RA
certain of also being included in future coalitions.
UA(Z, gA) = VA(Z) + PFA
Hence, members of the current winning coalition only
probabilisitically receive private goods under future
leaders. By contrast, current members of the winning RA XRA
coalition receive private goods with certainty from the + L S ) + ( 1go)
incumbent. This forms the basis of the leader's incum-
bency advantage. where T is the leader's utility for remaining in office,
The size of the leader's incumbency advantage de- and the other terms refer to the payoff from member-
pends upon the configuration of the polity's political ship in the winning coalition.12 FA(), recall, is the
institutions. The smaller the selectorate, the greater distribution of challenger types; hence, FA (VA (z) +
are the private goods benefits members of the current (1 - gA) RAIWA + p. - RAISA) is the probability that
winning coalition can expect from any challenger and, the leader of A retains power given the international
therefore, the greater the private benefits the incum- outcome z and effort gA.
bent must provide in order to remain in power. Simi- During a dispute, the incumbent leader in A decides
larly, as the size of the required winning coalition whether to fight and, if so, how hard to try. If attacked,
decreases, the number of people with whom private the leader in B chooses an allocation of resources to
dedicate to the war effort. Following the end of the
benefits must be shared decreases, which makes the
value of the benefits to each member that much dispute, members of the winning coalition decide
greater. Therefore, as the winning coalition becomes whether to remain loyal or to defect, thereby retaining
larger, the incumbency advantage diminishes because or bringing down the incumbent leadership. This is the
the value of the private benefits to individual members sequence of play in the game. With the utilities all
of the winning coalition gets smaller. When the win- specified, we can now turn to solving the game.
ning coalition is small and the selectorate is large,
supporters of the incumbent jeopardize their welfare if SOLVING THE GAME
they defect to a political rival of the incumbent, since
they face a high risk of being cut off from private We solve the game by finding subgame perfect equilib-
benefits under the new leader. The risk of being ria, starting at the bottom of the game tree and working
excluded from the private payoffs of future coalitions sequentially backward through each decision. As such,
grows as the size of the selectorate increases and as the the analysis of each stage is done with the knowledge of
size of the winning coalition decreases, so that the risk actors' anticipated responses in subsequent decisions.
is greatest in autocracies and smallest in democracies. Having already examined reselection above, we move
The incumbent is advantaged in her ability to supply to the preceding decision: the level of resources dedi-
private goods because current members of the coalition cated to prosecuting the war.
are sure of receiving them. Given her advantage in If attacked, the leader of B chooses how many of his
private goods, the incumbent survives so long as she available resources, RB, to dedicate to the war effort:
does not do such a poor job on public policy that she is gB E [0, 1]. The advantage of spending more on the
judged grossly incompetent as compared to the chal- war is that he improves B's prospects of victory, but
trying hard also involves risks. By trying harder, B's
lenger. That is, as long as CA is not especially large or
p. strongly negative, the incumbent has the upper hand.leader reduces the amount of resources available to
What constitutes sufficient policy incompetence by the reward his supporters through private goods. Political
leader to warrant deposition, however, depends on the institutions influence the effort decision because they
structure of the polity. If the leader has a huge determine the relative importance for political reselec-
advantage over the challenger in her ability to supply tion of saving resources to use as private goods versus
private goods, then she can survive disastrous policy increasing the odds of military victory by spending
outcomes. Although leaders from systems with large those resources on the war effort. Let Y(gB) represent
winning coalitions, such as democracies, have some the expected payoff of B's leader from dedicating gB of
advantage in the supply of private goods, the magni- the available resources to the war, where PB(9B) is the
tude of this advantage is small, so these leaders cannot
tolerate policy failure as well as can autocrats or even 12 One might argue that the value of remaining in office, P, is a
monarchs."1 function of regime type. As Goemans (1995) points out, being ousted
is more often fatal for autocrats than democrats. Our assumption,
however, is that the primary goal of all leaders is to keep their job.
11 Bueno de Mesquita and Siverson (1995) and King, Tomz, and Given this, the principal, component in every leader's objective
Wittenberg (1998) find empirical support for these predictions. function is reselection.

797

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

probability that nation B wins given an effort level of ate, or part of the disenfranchised portion of society.
gB. This probability of victory also depends upon A'sYet, increased effort comes at the expense of having
effort and the military balance, but since we are fewer resources with which to provide private goods for
currently focusing on B's decision, we suppress this supporters.
notation. Similarly, we suppress all unnecessary sub- Resources not spent on the war effort go to the
scripting: winning coalition in the form of private goods. The
value of these private goods depends upon how many
R
people must be rewarded. Each supporter's share of
Y(gB) =pNW) -k + (1-gB) - the private goods is RIW. As the leader allocates
resources to the war effort, he reduces the private
goods rewards for his supporters. The rate at which
+ P(PB(gB)F VB + (1 - gv) increased effort diminishes supporters' benefits de-
pends upon W. When the winning coalition is small,
each member's share of the resources is high. Given
+ (1 -P(gB))F(lB+ (1-gB) these concentrated benefits, increased war effort dras-
tically reduces the utility of members of the winning
where VB = 1 - k - RBISB + PB and 'B = -k - coalition. In contrast, when W is large, each member
RB/SB + P1B receives only a small share of the private goods in the
The term PB(gB) - k refers to the expected value
firstof
place. Thus, when the winning coalition is large,
the war to the nation as a whole. (1 - gB) RIW the
is the
reduction in supporters' utility from having re-
leader's share of the private goods rewards. The final sources channeled into the war effort, instead of being
term, T(pB(gB)F(VB + (1 gB) RIW) ? (1 retained as private benefits, is small. It is incentive
P(gB))F(lB + (1 - gB) RIW)), is the product of the compatible with a leader's goal of remaining in office to
value of officeholding, P, and the expected probability maximize his supporters' utility. In terms of the sup-
of surviving in office. This expected probability is made porters' rewards, the cost of improving the probability
up of two components. The first,PB(gB)F(VB + (1 - of victory increases as the winning coalition gets
gB) RIW), is the probability of victory (PB(gB)), smaller. Thus, the marginal benefit of increased ef-
multiplied by the probability that B's leader survives in fort-the increase in the probability of victory-is
office given victory, F(VB + (1 - gB) RIW). The independent of political institutions but the cost of
second component, (1 - p(gB))F(lB + (1 - gB) increased effort is dependent on those institutions. To
make the institutional comparison as stark as possible,
RIW), is the probability of military defeat (1 - p(gB)),
multiplied by the probability that B's leader survivesconsiderin the following limiting case.
office given defeat, F(lB + (1 - gB) RIW). Suppose a leader chooses between making an all-out
Leaders choose the effort level that maximizes their effort that guarantees victory (gB = 1 andPB (1) = 1)
expected payoff. In general, the larger the winning and no additional effort at all, even though this makes
coalition, the greater is this optimal effort level. This defeat inevitable (gB = 0 and PB(O) = 0). The
leads to our substantive conclusion that democrats try expected payoff of a leader who makes the all-out effort
harder in wartime than do autocrats. Before we explain is YB(gB = 1) = 1 - k + TF(VB), where VB = 1 -
the origins of this result, it is important to add a k - RB/SB + P1B. Alternatively, by making no addi-
qualifier. In some cases, the outcome of the war may betional effort, the leader receives YB(gB = 0) = -k +
so important relative to private goods that all leaders, RIW + PF(lB + RIW), where 'B = -k - RB/SB +
whatever their domestic political institutions, try all out P1B. Each of these equations has terms relating to t
to win. At the other extreme, the salience of the war leader's direct rewards and terms relating to the pros-
may be sufficiently low that no political arrangements pects of reselection. We examine these components
induce additional effort. Between these extremes, how- separately.
ever, it is large winning coalitions that induce high In terms of direct rewards, an all-out effort gets the
effort levels and small coalitions that induce the hoard- leader a payoff of 1 - k as opposed to no additional
ing of resources for subsequent distribution as private effort, which generates a direct payoff of -k + RIW.
rewards to the winning coalition. Therefore, if the winning coalition is larger than R,
The game reveals that large winning coalitions en- then the leader makes an all-out effort (W > R).
courage leaders to dedicate additional resources to the Although the direct benefits are illustrative of why
war effort. As for all the technical results, the formal leaders with large W try hard, we think of our argument
proof is in the Appendix. The key insight concerns how as predominately reselection driven. The reselection
coalition size influences the importance of private related rewards associated, respectively, with an all-out
goods as a means of rewarding supporters. As leaders effort and no additional effort are TF(VB) and
increase their level of effort during a war, they increase TF(lB + RIW). Since VB = 1 - k - RB/SB + pi and
the probability of victory. A military victory benefits 'B = -k - RBISB + p, and since F(.) is an increasing
everyone in nation B, including members of the win- function, the all-out effort term is greater than the
ning coalition. The marginal benefit of increased effort no-effort term when 1 > R/W. Again, in this limiting
is independent of political institutions, since everyone case, leaders make an all-out effort to win only when
benefits from the policy success, whether leader, mem- W > R. Otherwise, leaders hoard their resources for
ber of the winning coalition, member of the selector- private goods provision and make no additional effort,

798

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

even though military defeat is inevitable. Such leaders in war differ as a function of their institutional settings.
could improve their chances of victory by trying harder, All else being equal, institutional arrangements pro-
but this is not incentive compatible with their desire to vide democratic leaders with greater incentives to try
stay in office. hard relative to autocrats. To show how this influences
Thus far we have shown how political institutions the empirical regularities associated with the demo-
affect the amount of resources dedicated to the war cratic peace, we now assess the incentives to negotiate
effort for B. Similar logic applies for A. Although A's rather than fight.
leader's decision calculus is slightly more complicated,
because she must anticipate B's effort level, the same
THE DECISION TO FIGHT OR TO
motivations persist. Again, the larger A's winning
NEGOTIATE
coalition, the less important private goods become
relative to foreign policy success. Therefore, all else Because leaders in states with large winning coalitions
being equal, the larger the winning coalition, the more cannot easily compensate for policy failure by doling
resources A dedicates to the war effort.13 out private good, they need to succeed in foreign and
The game shows that democratic leaders, because domestic policy. Leaders in systems with small winning
they require large winning coalitions, try harder in war coalitions can more readily compensate for policy
than do autocrats, who only need support from a small failure by providing private benefits to their few key
coalition to stay in office. One might think that auto- backers. Therefore, they do not try as hard in wars as
crats have an interest in fighting hard to protect the do democrats. One consequence is that democracies
pool of resources they need to distribute as private are less attractive targets than autocracies. By the same
goods, but to stay in office they must only provide more token, democracies are reluctant to pursue wars they
than their challenger can credibly promise. The chal- do not expect to win. Their leaders are at great risk of
lenger cannot promise to distribute any resources that political defeat at home due to failed policies. Auto-
have been lost as a consequence of defeat in the war. cratic leaders are not.
Therefore, the incumbent autocrat's comparative ad- It follows that democratic leaders generally attack
vantage in distributing private goods and in reserving only if they anticipate victory. They are highly selective;
resources for that purpose remains unaltered following they prefer to negotiate when they do not anticipate
military defeat. military success. This does not mean they are unwilling
The deduction from our model that democratic to fight. Democracies, because of their propensity to
leaders try harder in wars than do autocrats is, we try hard, can often overwhelm their foe. This carries an
believe, a novel theoretical result. It is interesting to important implication for the type of foe they can fight
note, therefore, empirical evidence that fits our deduc- and defeat. Because autocrats do not try as hard in war,
tion. Bates et al. (1998, 7) report that Rosenthal they make attractive targets for democracies. In con-
trast, two democracies are reluctant to fight each other.
finds a "selection effect:" parliamentary governments, for
example, fight fewer wars [than monarchies or autocra- Since both try hard, each minimizes to the extent
cies]. They are only willing to fight wars that are profitable, possible, given its resource endowments, the chance
and they are more willing to adequately finance, and that the other will win. Since democrats need to be
therefore more likely to win, the wars they choose to overwhelmingly confident of victory, it is difficult to
sponsor. His conclusion is reinforced by the argument of satisfy the conditions necessary for democracies to fight
Levi, which explores thd impact of increased democratiza- one another.
tion and industrialization upon military mobilization. Autocrats do not depend upon military victory to
Faced by an increase in both variables, she argues, gov-
keep their job. Of course, they prefer winning to losing,
ernments have to invest more in convincing their popula-
but their political (and personal) survival is primarily a
tions of the importance of the war and in winning their
function of satisfying their small band of supporters
consent to fight.
rather than providing their citizens with successful
That is, democratic leaders invest their effort and policies. They are more willing to gamble on war than
resources in mobilizing their societies to produce the are democrats because the latter's political survival is
public good of victory in war, as predicted. Lamborn on the line; the former's is not. Thus, it is straightfor-
(1991) presents additional direct evidence for the ward to see that democracies and autocracies can fight
deduction that democracies try harder in war. He wars against each other and that autocracies can afford
shows that, before World War I, Germany devoted a to fight one another.
larger percentage of its gross national product to the Stated formally, we characterized optimal effort de-
military than did Britain or France.-Nevertheless, the cisions for leaders in A and B once war occurs as gA
latter mobilized greater resources once the war began and gB, respectively. All else being equal, the larger is
because they were better able than the Germans to Wi, the harder nation i tries. If A's leader initiates
increase revenue extraction for the war effort. conflict with B, then A's payoff is its chance of winning
We have demonstrated that the incentives of leaders multiplied by its utility for winning, plus the chance it
loses multiplied by its utility for losing, plus the value of
13 In general, the interaction between the effort levels of A and B the private goods retained after choosing a level of war
depends upon the precise function mapping effort into probability of
victory,p(gA, ge). For the special case in whichp(gA, gB) is the force
effort: U,(WAR~gA, gB) = PA - k + (1 - gz*)
ratio model, however, increased effort by one side elicits increased RA/WA + P(PAFA(VA + (1 -gA) RA/WA) + (1-
effort from the other. PA)FAQIA + (1I gA) RA/WA)), where PA is the

799

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

probability that A wins given effort levels g and g B. If secondary consideration that is not driven by an auto-
A's leader chooses negotiation rather than conflict, crat's primary objective-to stay in office. As such,
then her expected payoff is UA (nego) = X + conflict initiation depends upon an assessment of the
PFA(nA + RAIWA) + RA/WA, where nA = X +expected WA value of war relative to negotiations. As we
RAISA. saw, autocrats find it easier to retain office than do
A's leader only initiates conflict when the benefit of their democratic counterparts. Autocrats have an ad-
doing so exceeds what she expects from a negotiated vantage over challengers in their ability to provide
settlement: UA(WARlg*, g*) 2 UA(nego).14 The private goods. Since private goods figure predomi-
more likely A is to win, the more likely it is that this nantly in the rewards given to supporters in autocratic
condition is met. Given their political institutions, A systems, supporters risk much if they desert the incum-
and B exert effort levels g and g , respectively. These bent. This incumbency advantage in the supply of
effort levels influence the probability of A being victo- private goods means that as long as autocratic leaders
rious, PA. In addition to structuring how hard A and B retain resources to provide private goods for their
try, political institutions also influence whether leaders supporters, they survive. Hence, as shown above, even
want to initiate conflict, given knowledge of the effort if she makes little additional effort, A's leader survives
levels that will follow in any subsequent war. We define in office.
P as the probability of victory that makes A indifferent Knowing that the leader in A makes no additional
between negotiations and war: effort and typically survives whatever the outcome of
conflict, her expected value of fighting approximately
P =
reduces to PA - k + RA/WA + P, where PA is the
probability of victory given no additional effort by A's

W+ A +FA nA + j-PFA + (1 WRAleader. Negotiated settlements leave A's resources


untouched and available for distribution as private
RA ) Fl+RA
(1 + kF(V + (1Ao WA ) WA FA + (1 - A WA)) goods. Again, having the incumbency advantage of
guaranteed private goods provision, the typical auto-
crat also retains office via negotiations. An autocrat's
A only initiates conflict if PA 2 P. Although this expected value for negotiations reduces to approxi-
expression is mathematically precise, it provides little mately X + RA/WA + P. Therefore, an autocrat's
substantive interpretation of the incentives that leaders decision resembles that of a standard unitary actor
face. Yet, political institutions shape this expression in model. An autocratic leader typically initiates fighting
a systematic manner. We present examples for both when PA > X + k: The expected benefits of conflict
autocrats and democrats to illustrate how political outweigh the expected value of negotiations.15
institutions structure the conditions under which lead-
ers choose war rather than negotiations. These stan-
The Decision for Democrats
dard cases show how autocrats and democrats differ in
their decisions to initiate conflict. Generally, survival Unlike autocrats, leaders with large winning coalitions
for an autocrat depends upon her ability to distribute have only a small incumbency advantage in the supply
private goods. Providing she does not expend resources of private goods. As already shown, this makes their
on the war effort, she typically survives whether she survival in office harder and more contingent upon
wins, loses, or negotiates. Since her survival is not their public policy performance. Knowing that the
strongly influenced by the war outcome, an autocrat's survival of democrats depends upon their public policy
initiation decision resembles a standard realist calcula- performance, we construct an example to show how
tion of benefits and losses. For a democrat the situation institutions structure the conflict decision of leaders in
is different. Given the large number of supporters she large winning coalition systems. Having examined this
must appease, she cannot buy political loyalty with archetypal case, we analyze the limiting mathematical
private goods alone but must rely instead on public case. Although we believe the stereotypical case is
policy success. For her, military defeat equates with generally appropriate, there are plausible conditions
political defeat; so, where possible, she avoids fighting under which the results we generate from this example
when defeat is a significant possibility. break down. These conditions are important because
they predict the domestic political circumstance when
democrats become belligerent and when war between
The Decision for Autocrats
democracies is most likely. Rather than interrupt the
Autocrats initiate conflict when the~expected gains flowof
of our general argument by continually referring
conflict exceed what they expect to obtain through to these exceptional circumstances, which resemble
negotiations. Yet, the decision to fight is largely a those of gambling for resurrection under the diversion-
ary war hypothesis (Downs and Rocke 1994; Goemans
14 If X < - k, then war is inevitable, since A would prefer losing to
a negotiated settlement. At the other extreme, if A's expected deal
through negotiations is greater than the best possible outcome from 15 The limiting case shows this clearly. As the winning coalition
war, A always negotiates: X 2 1 - k. Since we are primarily thinking contracts, W -O 0, the private goods that each supporter receives
of X as a division between 0 and 1, the first extreme is generally become extremely large, RIW -- o; hence, leaders make no effort,
impossible. To restrict ourselves to substantively interesting cases, we and the decision to fight resembles the unitary actor solution: limwb0
assume -k ' X ' 1 - k. P = X + k.

800

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

1995; Levy 1989; Richards et al. 1993; Smith 1996; they attack than is true for their autocratic counter-
Werner 1996), we consider them separately. parts.
As we have already demonstrated, in systems with The implications of the above theoretical result
large winning coalitions, leaders have only a small about the willingness of democratic leaders to use
incumbency advantage in the provision of private violence as the means to advance their objectives is
goods. Instead, leaders survive on the basis oftheir noteworthy. Autocracies may engage in imperialist
public goods performance. With their sensitivity to expansion, for instance, out of a quest for additional
public policy provision in mind, we construct our private goods. Democracies can also be expected to
stylized case by assuming that defeat means almost participate in imperialist expansion according to our
certain removal and victory means almost certain re- model, provided that doing so enhances the survivabil-
tention. Therefore, the expected payoff for a demo- ity of incumbents. The targets during wars of colonial
cratic leader from initiating conflict is approximately and imperial expansion typically are very weak states or
PA(l - k + T) + (1 - PA)(-k) = -k + PA(1 + peoples who can easily be defeated. The norms-based
P), where PA is the probability of victory for A given argument that democracies use violence to protect
the effort each side makes. If instead of fighting A's their survival against nondemocratic foes who do not
leader negotiates a settlement, then her expected pay- share the abhorrence of violence may account for some
off is UA(nego) = X + TFA(nA + RA/WA) + RAIWA, democratic-autocratic wars, but it seems to be contra-
where nA = X + WA - RAISA. Although we shall dicted by wars of colonial or imperial expansion by
subsequently discuss relaxing this assumption, for cur- democracies. Certainly, the weak foes in such wars did
rent purposes suppose that this is approximately equal not threaten the survival of the democratic belligerent.
to X + T + RA/WA. We know that democratic leaders Yet, our model shows that extremely weak opponents
are sensitive to policy failure and' that supporters' readily fulfill the requirements to be targets of demo-
rewards from negotiations are generally closer to those cratic initiations of violence. Democracies, according
of success than failure, since conflict is inefficient. An to our model, initiate fighting when their prospects of
additional, although small, benefit from negotiation is victory are almost certain, so they, like autocracies, are
that leaders can allocate private goods. So, as an initial not immune from the temptations of expansionism.
working supposition, we assume that negotiations also Near certainty of victory, not normative commitment
give leaders a significant probability of retaining office. to peaceful resolution of disputes, describes when
Democrats initiate conflict when -k + PA(l + democracies go to war.
i) > X + T + RAIWA, which can be alternatively The democratic propensity to try hard makes it
expressed as PA> (X + T + k)/(l + T) + RA/((l + difficult for either side of a democratic dyad to over-
P)WA). Given the large winning coalition size of a whelm the other. Being unable to guarantee victory,
democracy, the latter term, RAI((l + P)WA), is small. both sides seek to avoid what is likely to be a bloody
The magnitude of the former term, (X + T + k)/(l + and protracted conflict. The exception arises when one
P), depends upon the value of holding office. As party in the dyad is much weaker than the other. In that
holding office becomes important (large 4), this term case, large democracies are not immune from attacking
becomes close to one. This indicates that democratic small ones, but small democracies are expected to sue
leaders who value holding office need to be almost for peace rather than fight back. This follows in the
certain of victory before risking war. model because democracies need a high probability of
In constructing this stylized example we made sup- victory in order to fight. Therefore, large democracies
positions about the probability of reselection associ- are prepared to fight weak adversaries, including de-
ated with each outcome. Later we explore the robust- mocracies, but the weak democrats, having a low
ness of our results in light of variation in these probability of victory, are unwilling to fight back. This
conditions. By looking at the limiting case of an results in cases of low-level, one-sided attacks by large
extremely large winning coalition we see justification democracies against small ones (e.g., the United States
for this working assumption. As the winning coalition attacked the Dominican Republic in 1965), a phenom-
expands, W --> o, each supporter's private goods enon widely observed in the historical record. This also
allocation becomes vanishingly small, RIW -> 0. Under explains why democracies can be imperialist powers.
this contingency, private goods have no value to lead- Democrats need to be more certain of victory than
ers, either in terms of personal or reselection benefits. do autocrats before they attack, but this is not to say
Hence, leaders allocate all available resources to extra that democratic states are necessarily more dovish than
war effort, g* = 1. Under this condition A only attacks autocratic regimes. Although democrats must be con-
ifpA ' limWooP = (X + k + TF(n) - TF(l))/(1 + fident of victory before initiating conflict, their in-
T(F(v) - F(l))). Of course, if leaders care nothing creased effort means that often they can overwhelm
about reselection (T = 0), then this again reduces to other states. In the Appendix we formally show that the
the unitary actor solution. If, as we believe, the rese-size of a negotiated settlement, X, sufficient to buy off A
lection motive is primary (large 4), however, then and prevent A from attacking is not a simple monotone
concavity in F(.) is sufficient to ensure that (X + k + in the size of the winning coalition. Simply because
TF(n) - TF(l))/(1 + T(F(v) - F(l))) > X + k. democrats are more selective in their conflicts does not
Given our assumption that challenger types are expo- always make them less aggressive. Rather, whether
nentially distributed, this means that leaders in systems large or small winning coalition systems are more
with large W must be more certain of winning before aggressive is a function of the specific conditions.

801

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

Under some circumstances autocrats may be more only if B is substantially weaker than A, taking both the
dovish, under other conditions they may be more prewar military balance and effort levels into account.
hawkish. Our institutional explanation has two oppo- Since B will try hard, A must have a great prewar
site components. First, leaders with large winning military advantage or a great advantage in overall
coalitions typically try hard during conflict, dedicating resource endowments that can be put to use in the war
additional resources to the war effort, which allows effort. Aside from such asymmetric conflicts as charac-
them to overwhelm other states. Second, democratic terize imperialism and wars of colonial expansion, wars
leaders with large winning coalitions need to be more between democracies are unlikely.
certain of victory than their autocratic counterparts We have now established that autocracies fight each
before initiating conflict. Given these two competing other provided either one believes it has a consequen-
influences, we cannot say whether in general democrats tial advantage; autocracies are more reluctant to initi-
are more hawkish or dovish than autocrats, but the ate wars against democracies because of the difference
combination of these two effects leads to the implica- in levels of effort, although they are not precluded from
tion that democratic nations generally do not fight one doing so when the conditions in the model are right;
another. and democracies target autocratic states just under
those circumstances when the democracy expects to
The Interaction of Polities win, although this occurs more often than we might
suppose because of the effort advantage induced by
Thus far, we have shown that political institutions help democratic institutions. The latter two results suggest
shape war-fighting incentives. We found that a large an explanation for Benoit's (1996) finding that democ-
winning coalition has two effects: It makes states try racies are overall more pacific than other systems. They
harder if there is a war, and it makes leaders more
also explain Bennett and Stam's (1998) finding that
selective about the disputes they are prepared to
democracies are more likely to initiate war against
escalate to warfare. We now explore how these effects
autocracies than vice versa. We now move to the heart
shape the possibility of conflict between different com-
of the democratic peace and explain why pairs of
binations of polities.
democracies have such a low propensity to fight.
Case 1: A is autocratic and so is B. Neither tries hard
The institutional arrangements within democracies
if there is a war. The leader of A attacks if she believes
mean that the leader's survival depends more upon
that on average she can get more from conflict than
policy success than upon the provision of private goods
negotiations. She may believe, for instance, that the
to supporters. Once engaged in a war, democratic
expected settlement through negotiations underesti-
leaders typically make every effort to win. A war
mates A's relative war-fighting ability. B's leader, pre-
between two democracies is likely to be bloody and
sumably, does not share this belief. If she did, then the
hard fought, with both sides using every available
negotiated settlement proffered by B would reflect that
resource. Democratic leaders are reluctant to engage
fact. As the war's outcome is not critical to A's (or B's)
in a war unless they are extremely confident of winning.
political survival, the decision to fight is more easily
Against an autocrat, victory often is almost assured
influenced by secondary factors not assessed in our
because of the democrat's willingness to try hard. A
model.
democratic opponent, however, is also prepared to go
Case 2: A is autocratic, but B is democratic. Despite
the extra mile for policy success. Victory has to be a
the fact that A's institutions place few constraints on
the decision to fight, A's leader is generally reluctant to
near certainty in order for a democracy to fight rather
attack a democracy because democracies try hard. than negotiate, and it is unlikely that either democracy
Therefore, she knows that her state is likely to lose the will have a sufficiently large advantage to prefer war to
war. This reduces the expected utility from fighting as negotiation. Consequently, democracies are more
compared to the expected utility from negotiations, likely to negotiate a resolution of their mutual disputes
which makes war initiated by an autocrat against a rather than fight. Only democratic leaders who do not
democrat less likely, all else being equal, than war highly value retaining office are willing to fight when
initiated by an autocrat against another autocracy. the perceived odds of victory are not extremely high.
Case 3: A is democratic, but B is an autocrat. The Our model supports the claim that democracies tend
political institutions of A make its leader reluctant to not to fight one another but do tend to initiate wars
attack B unless military victory is highly likely. Yet, the against autocracies, provided the democrat has a sub-
incumbent in A is prepared to put more effort into the stantial probability of victory. The model also indicates
war (if there is one) than will the autocratic B. Hence, that autocracies can readily fight one another and are
A is more likely to win the conflict than, for instance, less inclined to negotiate than are democrats. We
the prewar military balance atone suggests. Thus, de- began with eight observed empirical regularities of
mocracies are willing to fight autocrats so long as the interest, and we have shown how institutional arrange-
prewar military balance plus the democracy's addi- ments explain the first five. Although the other three
tional effort give A a substantial probability of victory. have not been explicitly discussed thus far, the model
Autocrats are willing to fight back under these condi- can readily address these patterns, too.
tions because victory is not essential for their political It is commonly assumed, and has been demonstrated
survival. empirically, that the costs a nation endures in war and
Case 4: A is democratic and so is B. A will attack B the length of time it takes to win are inversely related

802

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

to its military dominance (Bennett and Stam 1996; DIVERSIONARY WAR AND COMPROMISE
Bueno de Mesquita 1983). If this is so, then nations AGREEMENTS
that overwhelm their opponents are likely to win
Although we present a general model of war, for clarity
quickly and suffer fewer causalities in the process. As
of exposition we have focused on particular cases.
we have shown, democracies tend to make the greater
These stylized cases suggest that democracies are only
effort. Therefore, on average, we should expect them to
aggressive if they are nearly certain of victory. When
win quickly and to have lower casualties than autocra-
the outcome of the war is less certain, democracies
cies. Although the relationship between costs and prefer negotiated settlements. Since this conclusion
relative military dominance is outside the formal drives the democratic peace predictions, its robustness
framework of our model, it reinforces our findings. is worth exploring to identify the conditions under
Democracies find it hard to overwhelm other democ- which it breaks down.
racies because both sides are prepared to make an For mathematical convenience we assumed the dis-
all-out war effort. Hence, a war between democracies is tribution of challenger types was exponential. With
likely to be long and costly. Since the survival of respect to effort level, our intuition focuses on the
democratic leaders depends upon public policy success, arguments of F(.), rather than the specific shape of the
they typically want to avoid long and costly wars. exponential distribution. That is, our arguments about
Mansfield and Snyder (1995) suggest that transi- effort levels are grounded upon how political institu-
tional democracies are not bound by the democratic tions shape the rewards supporters receive and not
peace. Instead, they are more war prone than older specifically on the marginal effect of these benefits. So,
democracies or autocracies. Our model may shed some with respect to effort level, our assumption that chal-
light on the regularity they have advanced. Elsewhere lenger types are distributed exponentially is benign.
we report on the endogenous selection of institutions With respect to the decision to fight, however, our
(Bueno de Mesquita et al. 1998) using a variation of assumption is less innocent. For example, in examining
the model discussed here. We found a larger set of the limiting case (W -> oc), we used the concavity of
conditions under which there are incentives to expand the exponential distribution. It certainly seems reason-
the size of the selectorate rather than the size of the able to assume there are diminishing marginal returns
winning coalition. If states in transition to democracy from additional rewards for supporters when a leader is
expand their selectorate faster than they expand their already likely to remain in office, but such an assump-
winning coalition, then the latter falls below its optimal tion is less tenable when a leader's initial prospect of
size. In that case, the model suggests the existing survival is low. We may, for example, prefer to assume
government is highly susceptible to overthrow by for- challengers are distributed normally, which makes the
eign or domestic rivals, which makes it highly unstable. reselection decision appear as a probit model. Of
This seems compatible with the view advanced by course, providing a leader has reasonable prospects of
survival, the logic behind our stylized case holds. For
Mansfield and Snyder (1995) and reinforced by Ward
leaders who have little hope of remaining in office,
and Gleditsch (1998), who maintain that not all tran-
however, the rationale for our stylized case diminishes
sitional democracies are war prone; those undergoing
and may be reversed. This implies that democratic
reversal in the democratization process are most apt to
leaders with failed domestic policies (low ii) may be
fight. That is an avenue 4of research we will continue to
extremely belligerent.
pursue, mindful that current results are consistent with
Given her institutional incentives, a democratic
but inconclusive at this stage regarding the hypothesis
leader with failed public policies is unlikely to retain
about transitional democracies.
office unless she has an astonishing change in perfor-
As stated at the outset, we cannot systematically
mance. If we think of reselection as modeled in a probit
evaluate Morgan and Campbell's (1991) monadic ob-
setting, then this is to say the leader starts deep in the
servation that large democracies appear particularly
left-hand tail. Given the increasing marginal returns on
constrained, but we can indicate how it might be
additional rewards when starting from such a low base,
consistent with our theory. We bear in mind that they a leader with failed policies has an incentive to gamble
do not address the resources or institutional con- everything on the outcome of conflict. It is perhaps
straints of the adversary in war. Major power democ- only through a successful war that she has any signifi-
racies typically have a significant advantage over their cant chance of remaining in office. If a leader is in a
opponents in terms of the military balance, which position of accepting a negotiated settlement that
enhances their bargaining position relative to the bar- leaves her with little chance of domestic survival, then,
gaining position of smaller, less powerful democracies. counter to our earlier argument, she faces no disad-
Since an advantageous bargaining position allows lead- vantage from fighting. If she loses, she will be deposed,
ers to obtain nearly everything they want anyway, even but she would have been removed anyway. Yet, victory
if certain of victory, the small additional gains made holds the prospects (although not necessarily high,
through military victory are likely to be offset by the significantly greater than with negotiations) of remain-
costs of fighting. Therefore, powerful democracies ing in office. Hence, a democratic leader with failed
should strongly manifest the expected behavior of policies is potentially bellicose. This, of course, is the
democracies in a manner consistent with the Morgan gambling for resurrection idea inherent in the diver-
and Campbell monadic results. sionary war theory literature (Downs and Rocke 1994;

803

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

Goemans 1995; Levy 1989; Richards et al. 1993; Smith leaders belligerent, autocrats find it less important to
1996; Werner 1996). keep negotiating than do democrats. Two democratic
These diversionary hypotheses may appear to under- leaders are destined to fight only when neither is able
mine our earlier conclusions, but this is not so. Indeed, to make additional concessions, a circumstance that
quite to the contrary, these diversionary results are arises only if both have failed domestic policies. The
satisfying on several dimensions. Our theory does not same motivations exist for autocrats, but the incentives
simply state that democracies are either more cautious are weaker, since autocrats are surer of reselection
or more bellicose; it states the conditions under which whatever the international outcome.
each of these eventualities occurs. This distinction is
important. Our theory does not state that a war
CONCLUSION
between democracies is impossible. Rather, we show
that the conditions under which a democrat will attack In our simple model, leaders are assumed to be moti-
another democrat are more restrictive than the condi- vated by a desire to keep their job. They allocate
tions under which a democrat will attack an autocrat. resources toward the pursuit of public policies that
This constraint, which occurs because democrats are benefit all citizens and toward private goods that
less attractive targets due to their high war effort, holds benefit only their key supporters. When a member of
even in diversionary circumstances. Autocrats always the winning coalition defects from the incumbent lead-
are the more attractive targets, but when two demo- ership, the defector puts her access to private goods at
cratic leaders have unsuccessful domestic policies, war risk. That risk is assumed to increase as the selectorate
between democracies is most likely. increases in size and to decrease as the winning coali-
In terms of theory building, the diversionary hypoth- tion increases in size.
eses are pleasing. A new theoretical model is convinc- The institutional arrangements of political systems
ing when it accounts for the predictions of extant influence the incentives of leaders to provide different
models. Hence, the fact that our model simultaneously kinds of policies. We examined the link between insti-
accounts for findings in both the diversionary war and tutions and policy choices in the context of interna-
democratic peace literatures strengthens our argu- tional disputes. We demonstrated that democratic
ments. Indeed, we believe the most attractive feature leaders, when faced with a war, are more inclined to
of our institutional model, and more generally the shift extra resources into the war effort than are
larger project of which it is a part, is its ability to autocratic leaders. This follows because, as the winning
encompass results from disparate and distinct litera- coalition grows, the prospects of political survival in-
tures (Bueno de Mesquita et al. 1997, 1998, 1999, n.d.). creasingly hinge on successful policy performance. The
Negotiations are complex, and for convenience we extra effort made by democrats gives them a military
have not modeled their details. The objectives of advantage over autocrats in war. In addition, demo-
leaders during negotiations differ depending on their cratic leaders only choose to fight when they are
institutional arrangements. Since autocrats typically confident of military victory. Otherwise, they prefer to
survive whatever the policy outcome, providing they do negotiate.
not squander their resources, they simply seek to Democrats make relatively unattractive targets be-
maximize their gains from the process. Democratic cause domestic reselection pressures cause leaders to
leaders face different pressures. It is harder for them to mobilize resources for the war effort. This makes it
keep their job if they perform poorly on policy. They harder for other states to target them for aggression. In
would like to get a good deal for their nation through addition to trying harder than autocrats, democrats are
negotiations, but they only need a deal good enough for more selective in their choice of targets. Defeat typi-
them to be reselected. If the negotiations break down, cally leads to domestic replacement for democrats, so
then the democrat must be militarily successful to they only initiate war when they expect to win. These
satisfy domestic policy wants and to survive politically. two factors lead to the interaction between polities that
Hence, a democratic leader may be prepared to accept is often termed the democratic peace. Autocrats need
a more modest settlement rather than allow negotia- a slight expected advantage over other autocratic ad-
tions to break down and risk being removed by failure versaries to initiate conflict, but they need more over-
during war. This is particularly true if the democrat whelming odds against democratic foes. This is because
faces a democratic opponent who will try hard in any democrats compensate for any initial military disadvan-
war. Again, we see that democrats are unlikely to fight tage by devoting additional resources to the war effort.
one another; they are likely to seek ways to succeed In order to initiate war, democrats need overwhelming
through negotiations even if one side must make odds of victory, but that does not mean they are
additional concessions to avoid a breakdown. passive. Because democrats use their resources for the
For autocrats the story is different. They survive war effort rather than reserve them to reward backers,
domestically by providing private goods. Unless the they are generally able, given their selection criteria for
international outcome is horrendous, it is unlikely to fighting, to overwhelm autocracies, which results in
influence their reselection prospects. Because they do short and relatively less costly wars. Yet, democracies
not have a great incentive to avoid the breakdown of find it hard to overwhelm other democracies because
negotiations, they have a smaller incentive than dem- they also try hard. In general, democracies make
ocrats to make additional concessions to avoid a war. unattractive targets, particularly for other democracies.
Whereas domestic policy failures make democratic Hence, democratic states rarely attack one another.

804

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

One objection to the democratic peace concept is where v = 1 - k + A - RIS, 1 = -k + pA - RIS, and F(.)
that it lacks a comprehensive explanation. Frameworks represents the distribution of challengers, which we assume is
based on norms or on constraints account for some but exponential F(x) = 1 - e
Let g* = g*(W) be the effort level that maximizes B's
not all patterns observed Our model appears to be
expected payoff given a winning coalition of size W: g*(W) =
fairly comprehensive. Two novel hypotheses are that
arg maxge[O.l] Y(g, W). For what follows, we assume that
democracies try harder and that political incentives in
this optimal effort is unique.16
democracies do not make them immune from wars of There are two cases to consider: B's optimal effort lies on
imperial expansion. Evidence from other studies sup- a boundary (i.e., g* = 0 or g* = 1) and B's optimal effort is
ports the former; the latter is a well-known fact but interior (g* E (0, 1)). In the former case, B strictly prefers
seems to contradict core parts of the norm-based to spend either nothing (g* = 0) or all available resources
explanations of the democratic peace. Our model (g* = 1) on the war. Straightforwardly, under these contin-
explains these diverse phenomena without attributing gencies an infinitesimal change in W has no effect on B's
superior motives or greater civic mindedness to one optimal effort: dg*(W)/dW = O.. Hence, we focus on the
latter case. When B's optimal effort decision is interior, the
kind of leader over another. The explanation is driven
first- and second-order conditions imply aY(g, W)/&g = 0
purely by self-interested leaders who seek to retain
and &2Y(g, W/ag2 < 0.
office and face alternative institutional arrangements.
The first-order condition implies that H(W) = aY(g,
W)Iag = (p'(g)W - R + 4JWp'(g)(F(x) - F(y)) -
TR(p(g)F'(x) + (1 - p(g))F'(y)))/W= 0, wherex = v +
APPENDIX (1 - g) R/W, y = 1 + (1 - g) R/W, p'(g) = dp(g)/dg and
F'(x) = dF(x)/dx. Defining the numerator of H(W) as
In this appendix we examine the properties of the subgame
perfect equilibria of the game to show mathematically how
G(W), aH/aW = (W(aG/aW) - G(aW/&aW)/W2, which,
given the first-order condition G(W) = 0, reduces to
political institutions affect the effort level that nations make
once engaged in a war and how political institutions influence
aH/8aW = (G/aJ/)/W. By the implicit differentiation ru
the conditions under which nations initiate violence. Sub-
dg*(W)/dW = -(&H/&/aW)/H/&g). Since, by the second-
order condition, aH/&g < 0, aG/&W > 0 implies dg*/dW >
game perfect equilibria are strategy profiles that are Nash
0.17
equilibria in every proper subgame of the game. Given the
Evaluating aG/&W yields aG/&W = p'(g) + Tp'(g)(F(x) -
boundedness, continuity, and differentiability of the functions
in our setup, the existence of such equilibria is guaranteed by F(y)) - RIW 4p'(g)(1 - g)(F'(x) - F'(y)) + R2/W2
( - g)(p(g)F"(x) + (1 - p(g))F"(y)). Given that
standard results.
F(x) = 1 - e-x/, F'(x) = i/o e-x/, and F"(x) = _1/(Y2
We consider the aspects of equilibria required to support
e-x/, aG/&W > 0. Hence, dg*(W)/dW > 0, so optimal
our conclusions. First, we examine B's effort decision. Sec-
effort levels increase as the winning coalition grows. Q.E.D.
ond, we analyze A's effort decision. For both A and B, the
The analysis of A's effort decision is analogous to that for
greater the size of a nation's winning coalition, the greater is
B. Hence, we omit a proof.
the wartime effort made. Third, we examine the propensity of
different systems to initiate conflict by characterizing how the PROPOSITION 2. A's effort level, g*, is weakly increasing in the
size of the winning coalition affects the value of conflict size of WA.
relative to the value of negotiations. Fourth, we build upon
this result to show that the size of the negotiated settlement
that makes A indifferent between fighting and negotiations is The Decision to Fight or Negotiate
not a monotone of the size of the winning coalition.
We examine how, in addition to affecting effort levels,
political institutions affect the conditions under which A
initiates conflict. In the text we discussed this in terms of a
Effort Level stereotypical case and analyzed the limiting cases as W
Once engaged in conflict, leaders decide how hard to try. This becomes extremely large or extremely small (W -> oo and
effort increases with the size of the winning coalition. We W -> 0). Here, we provide additional results. First, we
start with B's effort decision. B, having observed A's effort, characterize how W affects Z, the payoff difference between
gA, decides what proportion of available resources to dedi- conflict and negotiation. Second, we use this result to show
cate to the war. Suppressing all subscripts, B's effort level, g, that the size of the negotiated settlement that makes A
influences the probability that it wins the war, p(g) = PB(gA, indifferent between fighting and negotiations is not a mono-
tone of W. Hence, whether large or small winning coalition
gB) -
systems require the larger payoff to avert war depends upon
PROPOSITION 1. B's optimal effort level, g*, is weakly increasing specific conditions.
in the size of WB-
16 Given the nonlinearity of these equations, flat spots or identical
Proof Y(g, W) is B's expected payoff from the war given maxima are unlikely, but deterrence offers a straightforward equilib-
effort level g. rium selection refinement if there are any. The higher B's effort level,
the less attractive a target B becomes. Since higher effort levels deter
R A, and such effort levels are credible, we use the refinement that B
Y(g, W) = p(g) - k + (1 - g) w picks the larger effort level.
17 Evaluating the second-order condition at the turning point,
aG/ag = W aHiag = p"(g)W + WTp"(g)(F(x) - F(y)) + 2/p(g)
/ / ~R\
p'(g)(R - W) - 2/p(g)Wp'2gT(F(x) - F(y)) + 2/p(g)
+ Tjp(g)F v + p'(g)RT(F'(y)
(1 -g) W
- p(g)F'(x)) + R2/WT(p(g)F"(x) + (1 -
p(g))F"()). The sign of the first two terms depends uponp"(g), and
the sign of the third term is determined by (R - IW). Everything els
? (1 -p(g))Ftl ? (1
is negative. -g) W

805

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
An Institutional Explanation of the Democratic Peace December 1999

The Effect of Regime on the Decision to Fight. A only initiates relative to conflict, aN/&nc < 0. Using the implicit differen-
conflict if the value of doing so exceeds the value of a tiation rule, we have dnc/dW = -(aNlaW)l(aNlanc).
negotiated settlement: Z(fV) = UA(WARkA(9V, gB(V)) -
Hence, whether an increase in W results in a larger or small
UA(nego) 2 0. negotiated settlement being just sufficient to buy off A
Writing the utility from conflict in terms of W only, depends upon the size of aN/&W, which is equivalent to
dZ/dW.
Hence, in general we cannot unambiguously determine
UA(WARIW) =p -k + (1 -g) R
whether an increase in W will increase or decrease the deal
sufficiently to buy off A. Substantively, this implies that
increasing W may increase or decrease the prospects for a
+ I(pF( v + (1 -g) v
negotiated settlement depending upon the precise condi-
tions. Democrats need not be more dovish than autocrats.

+ (1 - p)F(l + (1 -g) W
where p is the probability that A wins given optimal effort REFERENCES
levelsg andv = 1 - k + p. - RIS, andl = -k + 1i - RIS. Bates, Robert H., Avner Greif, Margaret Levi, Jean-Laurent
If A chooses negotiation rather than a conflict, then her Rosenthal, and Barry R. Weingast. 1998. Analytic Narratives.
expected payoff is UA(nego) = X + NF(n + RIW) + RIW, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
where n = X + [- RIS. Bennett, Scott D., and Allan C. Stam III. 1996. "The Duration of
Therefore, Z(W) = p - k + (1 - g) RIW + NV(pF(v + Interstate Wars: 1812-1985." American Political Science Review 90
(June): 239-57.
(1 - g) RIW) + (1 - p)F(l + (1 - g) RIW)) - (X +
Bennett, Scott D., and Allan C. Stam III. 1998. "The Declining
NVF(n + RIW) + RIW). This expression is the payoff
Advantages of Democracy: A Combined Model of War Outcomes
difference between conflict and negotiation. Next, we exam-
and Duration." Journal of Conflict Resolution 42 (June): 344-66.
ine how institutional features affect Z by differentiating it
Benoit, Kenneth. 1996. "Democracies Really Are More Pacific (in
with respect to W: dZ/dW = dp/dg dg/dW(l + T(F(x? - General)." Journal of Conflict Resolution 40 (December): 636-57.
F(y))) + Q + TQ(pF'(x) + (1 - p)F'(y)) + RIW2 + Brecher, Michael, and Jonathan Wilkenfeld. 1997. A Study of Crisis.
R/JW2 TF'(n + RIW), where Q = -dg/dWR/W - (1 - g) Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
R/W2, x = v + (1 - g) R/W and y = 1 + (1 - g) R/W. Bremer, Stuart. 1992. "Dangerous Dyads: Conditions Affecting the
Substituting the first-order condition from the effort decision Likelihood of Interstate War, 1816-1965." Journal of Conflict
Resolution 26 (June): 309-41.
((1 + 4(F(x) - F(y))) = RIW ((1 + pF'(x) + (1 -
Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce. 1981. The War Trap. New Haven, CT:
p)F'(y)))/(dp/dg)), this can alternatively be written as:
Yale University Press.
dZ R R Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce. 1983. "The Costs of War: A Rational
Expectations Approach." American Political Science Review 77
dW= W2g (1 g)T pFFv + ( -g)-W (June): 347-57.
Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and David Lalman. 1992. War and
Reason: Domestic and International Imperatives. New Haven, CT:
+ (1-p)F' (I+ (1-g)-W + VF' (n W)
Yale University Press.
Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siver-
The sign of this expression determines whether an increase son, and Alastair Smith. 1997. "Inside Out." Hoover Institution.
in the size of W makes A more or less aggressive. A positive Typescript.
sign means increases in W make A more likely to use force. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siver-
This expression cannot be unambiguously signed, and son, and Alastair Smith. 1998. "Endogenous Political Institutions
whether an increase in W makes war more or less likely and the Survival of Leaders." Hoover Institution. Typescript.

depends upon the precise conditions. To get an idea of Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siver-
son, and Alastair Smith. 1999. "Policy Failure and Political Sur-
factors that influence the sign of this expression, however,
vival: The Contribution of Political Institutions." Journal of Con-
suppose that bargaining strength approximately correlates
flict Resolution 43 (April): 131-45.
with military strength (i.e., n p). Under such circum- Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, Randolph M. Siver-
stances, concavity in F(.) suggests F'(n + RIW) < son, and Alastair Smith. N.d. "Political Institutions, Political
(pF'(x) + (1 - p)F'(y)). Although events depend on Survival and Policy Success." In GoverningforProsperity, ed. Bruce
precise conditions, this suggests that when effort levels are Bueno de Mesquita and Hilton Root. New Haven, CT: Yale
already high (g close to one), an increase in W makes A more University Press. Forthcoming.
aggressive (dZ/dW > 0) Alternatively, when g is low, Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James D. Morrow, and Ethan Zorick.
dZ/dW < 0. 1997. "Capabilities, Perception and Escalation."American Political
Science Review 91 (March): 15-27.
Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and Randolph Siverson. 1995. "War and
What Value of Negotiations Makes Leaders Forgo War. Next the Survival of Political Leaders: A Comparative Study of Regime
we show that the size of the negotiated settlement that is just Types and Political Accountability." American Political Science
sufficient to avoid war is not a monotonic function of Review 89 (December): 841-55.
coalition size. Rather, whether the size of a deal is sufficient Dixon, William. 1994. "Democracy and the Peaceful Settlement of
to buy off an autocrat or a democrat depends upon the International Conflict." American Political Science Review 88
particular conditions and not just the size of the winning (March): 14-32.
Downs, George W., and David M. Rocke. 1994. "Conflict, Agency,
coalition. Suppose n, is the value of a negotiation that makes
and Gambling for Resurrection: The Principal-Agent Problem
A indifferent between negotiation and conflict (i.e., if X = n,
Goes to War." American Journal of Political Science 38 (May):
then Z = 0).
362-80.
Dropping all nonessential terms and subscripts, we let
Farber, Henry S., and Joanne Gowa. 1995. "Polities and Peace."
N(nc, W) define the identity of A being indifferent between International Security 20 (Fall): 123-46.
conflict and negotiation: N(n- , W) = UA(attack| W) Fearon, James. 1994. "Domestic Political Audiences and the Esca-
UA(nego~nc, W) = 0. lation of International Disputes." American Political Science Re-
Since increasing nc increases the value of negotiations view 88 (September): 577-92.

806

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 93, No. 4

Fearon, James. 1995. "Rationalist Explanations for War." Interna- Were Right: Democracy, Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950-
tional Organization 39 (Summer): 379-414. 1985." International Studies Quarterly 41 (June): 267-93.
Forsythe, David P. 1992. "Democracy, War, and Covert Action." Organski, A. F. K., and Jacek Kugler. 1980. The War Ledger. Chicago:
Journal of Peace Research 29 (November): 385-95. University of Chicago Press.
Goemans, Hein. 1995. "The Causes of War Termination: Domestic Powell, Robert. 1996a. "Stability and the Distribution of Power."
Politics and War Aims." Ph.D. diss. Department of Political World Politics 48 (January): 239-67.
Science, University of Chicago. Powell, Robert. 1996b. "Uncertainty, Shifting Power, and Appease-
Hirshleifer, Jack. 1989. "Conflict and Rent-seeking Success Func- ment." American Political Science Review 90 (December): 749-64.
tions: Ratio vs. Difference Models of Relative Success." Public Ray, James Lee. 1995. Democracies in International Conflict. Colum-
Choice 63 (2): 101-12. bia: University of South Carolina Press.
James, Patrick, and Glenn E. Mitchell II. 1995. "Targets of Covert Raymond, Gregory A. 1994. "Democracies, Disputes, and Third-
Pressure: The Hidden Victims of the Democratic Peace." Interna- Party Intermediaries." Journal of Conflict Resolution 38 (March):
tional Interactions 21 (1): 85-107. 24-42.
Kim, Woosang, and James D. Morrow. 1992. "When Do Shifts in Reiter, Dan, and Allan Stam III. 1998a. "Democracy and Battlefield
Power Lead to War?" American Journal of Political Science 36
Military Effectiveness." Journal of Conflict Resolution 42 (June):
(November): 896-922. 259-77.
King, Gary, Michael Tomz, and Jason Wittenberg. 1998. "Making Reiter, Dan, and Allan Stam III. 1998b. "Democracy, War Initiation
the Most of Statistical Analyses: Improving Interpretation and and Victory."American Political Science Review 92 (June): 377-89.
Presentation." Paper presented at the annual meeting of the
Richards, Diana, T. C. Morgan, R. K. Wilson, V. L. Schwebach, and
American Political Science Association, Boston, MA.
G. D. Young. 1993. "Good Times, Bad Times, and the Diversion-
Lake, David A. 1992. "Powerful Pacifists: Democratic States and
ary Use of Force." Journal of Conflict Resolution 37 (September):
War." American Political Science Review 86 (March): 24-37.
504-35.
Layne, Christopher. 1994. "Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Demo-
Riker, William. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven,
cratic Peace." International Security 19 (Fall): 5-49.
CT: Yale University Press.
Lamborn, Alan. 1991. The Price of Power. London: Unwin Hyman.
Riker, William. 1996. The Strategy of Rhetoric. New Haven, CT: Yale
Levy, Jack S. 1988. "Domestic Politics and War." Journal of Interdis-
University Press.
ciplinary History 18 (Spring): 653-73.
Russett, Bruce M. 1995. Grasping the Democratic Peace. Princeton,
Levy, Jack S. 1989. "The Diversionary Theory of War: A Critique."
NJ: Princeton University Press.
In Handbook of War Studies, ed. Manus I. Midlarsky. Ann Arbor:
Schultz, Kenneth. 1996. "Domestic Competition and Bargaining in
University of Michigan Press.
International Crises." Ph.D. diss. Department of Political Science,
Mansfield, Edward D., and Jack Snyder. 1995. "Democratization and
Stanford University.
War." Foreign Affairs 74 (May/June): 79-97.
Schwartz, Thomas, and Kiron Skinner. 1997. "Democracy and the
Maoz, Zeev. 1998. "Realist and Cultural Critiques of the Democratic
Paradox of Perpetual Peace." Paper presented at the annual
Peace: A Theoretical and Empirical Re-assessment." International
meeting of the American Political Science Association, Washing-
Interactions 24 (1): 3-89.
ton, D.C.
Maoz, Zeev, and Nazrin Abdolali. 1989. "Regime Types and Inter-
Senese, Paul D. 1997. "Between Dispute and War: The Effect of
national Conflict, 1816-1976." Journal of Conflict Resolution 33
Joint Democracy on Interstate Conflict Escalation." Journal of
(March): 3-36.
Politics 59 (February): 1-27.
Maoz, Zeev, and Bruce M. Russett. 1993. "Normative and Structural
Causes of the Democratic Peace." American Political Science Siverson, Randolph M. 1995. "Democracies and War Participation:
Review 87 (September): 624-38. In Defense of the Institutional Constraints Argument." European

McGillivray, Fiona. 1997. "Party Discipline as a Determinant of the Journal of International Relations 1 (December): 481-90.
Endogenous Formation of Tariffs." American Journal of Political Smith, Alastair. 1996. "Diversionary Foreign Policy in Democratic
Science 41 (April): 584-607. Systems." International Studies Quarterly 40 (March): 133-53.
Morgan, T. Clifton, and Sally Howard Campbell. 1991. "Domestic Smith, Alastair. 1998. "International Crises and Domestic Politics."
Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democ- American Political Science Review 92 (September): 623-38.
racies Fight?" Journal of Conflict Resolution 35 (June): 187-211. Spiro, David. 1994. "The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace."
Morrow, James D. 1989. "Capabilities, Uncertainty and Resolve." International Security 19 (Fall): 50-86.
American Journal of Political Science 33 (November): 941-72. Stam, Allan C., 1996. Win, Lose or Draw: Domestic Politics and the
Mousseau, Michael. 1998. "Democracy and Compromise in Milita- Crucible of War. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Thompson, William R., and Richard Tucker. 1997. "A Tale of Two
rized Interstate Conflicts, 1816-1992." Journal of Conflict Resolu-
tion 42 (April): 210-30. Democratic Peace Critiques." Journal of Conflict Resolution 41
Mueller, John D. 1973. War, Presidents and Public Opinion. New (June): 428-54.
York: Wiley. Ward, Michael D., and Kristian S. Gleditsch. 1998. "Democratizing
Norpoth, Helmut. 1987. "Guns and Butter and Governmental Pop- for Peace." American Political Science Review 92 (March): 51-62.
ularity in Britain." American Political Science Review 81 Septem- Werner, Suzanne. 1996. "Absolute and Limited War: The Possibili-
ber): 949-59. ties of Foreign Imposed Regime Change." International Interac-
Oneal, John R., and Bruce M. Russett. 1997. "The Classical Liberals tions 22 (July): 67-88.

807

This content downloaded from 200.3.192.226 on Tue, 30 Aug 2016 13:53:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like