You are on page 1of 10

Teleological Notions in Biology

First published Wed Mar 20, 1996; substantive revision Wed Feb 26, 2020
The manifest appearance of function and purpose in living systems is responsible for
the prevalence of apparently teleological explanations of organismic structure and
behavior in biology. Although the attribution of function and purpose to living systems
is an ancient practice, teleological notions are largely considered ineliminable from
modern biological sciences, such as evolutionary biology, genetics, medicine, ethology,
and psychiatry, because they play an important explanatory role.
Historical and recent examples of teleological claims include the following:
The chief function of the heart is the transmission and pumping of the blood through the
arteries to the extremities of the body. (Harvey 1616 [1928: 49])
The Predator Detection hypothesis remains the strongest candidate for the function of
stotting [by gazelles]. (Caro 1986: 663)
The geographic range of human malaria is much wider than the range of the sickle-cell
gene. As it happens, other antimalarial genes take over the protective function of the
sickle-cell gene in … other warm parts. (Diamond 1994: 83)
Despite the substantial amount of data we now have on theropod dinosaurs, more
information is necessary in order to determine the likelihood that early feathers served
an adaptive function in visual display as opposed to other proposed adaptive functions
such as thermoregulation. (Dimond et al. 2011: 62)
The ubiquity of claims such as these raises the question: how should apparently
teleological notions in biology be understood?
Most post-Darwinian approaches attempt to naturalize teleology in biology, in
opposition to nineteenth-century viewpoints which grounded it theologically.
Nevertheless, biologists and philosophers have continued to question the legitimacy of
teleological notions in biology. For instance, Ernst Mayr (1988), identified four reasons
why teleological notions remain controversial in biology, namely that they are:

1. vitalistic (positing some special ‘life-force’);


2. requiring backwards causation (because goal-directed explanations seem to use
future outcomes to explain present traits);
3. incompatible with mechanistic explanation (because of 1 and 2);
4. mentalistic (attributing the action of mind where there is none).
A fifth complaint is that they are not empirically testable (Allen & Bekoff 1995). The
current philosophical literature offers both Darwinian and non-Darwinian accounts of
teleology in biology that aim to avoid these concerns. In this article, we hope to bring
some clarity to the contemporary debates over the role of teleological notions in biology
by sketching a taxonomy of the various accounts of biological function on offer (see
Allen & Bekoff 1995 for a more comprehensive taxonomy that forms the basis of this
presentation). We primarily focus on naturalistic accounts of biological function, since
this is where we see the most lively and productive current debates (see, e.g., Garson
2016 for an extended survey). We also briefly discuss the notion of goal-directedness in
section 2.

• 1. Framing the Debate


• 2. Explanatory Teleonaturalism
• 3. Assimilation to Non-Biological Explanations
• 4. Natural Selection Accounts
o 4.1 Indirect
o 4.2 Direct Natural Selection Approaches
• 5. Unification and Pluralism
• Bibliography
o Anthologies
• Academic Tools
• Other Internet Resources
• Related Entries

1. Framing the Debate


The discussion about biological teleology has ancient origins. It is particularly
prominent in Plato’s depiction of the divine Craftsman or ‘Demiurge’ in
the Timaeus and Aristotle’s discussion of final causes in the Physics (see the section on
teleology in the entry on Aristotle). However, Plato’s and Aristotle’s understanding of
teleology, as well as their arguments for teleology in the natural world, are distinct
(Lennox 1992; Ariew 2002; Johnson 2005). Whereas Plato’s teleology is
anthropocentric and creationist, Aristotle’s is naturalistic and functional. On the
Platonic view, the Demiurge is the source of all motion in both the heavens and on
earth, and the universe and all living beings within it are artifacts modeled on the Forms
(see the relevant sections of the entries on Plato and Plato’s metaphysics). The goal
toward which all things, including living beings, are directed is the external and eternal
good of the Forms. In contrast, on the Aristotelian view, the teleology that directs the
behavior of living beings is immanent. For instance, in organismal development, the
impetus for this goal-directed process is a principle of change within the organism, and
the telos, or goal, of the development is also an inherent property. Although often
conflated, the views of Plato and Aristotle on teleology have been influential in
historical debates on biological teleology, and one can still find Platonic and
Aristotelian ideas in the current debate on biological functions.
In addition to its role within ancient philosophy and cosmology, teleology has long been
an important topic within physiology and medicine. Galen’s On the Use of the
Parts (De usu partium) is an early example of teleological reasoning applied to
physiology (see the section on teleology in the entry on Galen). In this text, Galen
presents a functional analysis of the various parts of living organisms, in which
“existence, structure, and attributes of all the parts must be explained by reference to
their functions in promoting the activities of the whole organism” (Schiefsky 2007:
371). For Galen, a teleological account of parts is superior to a purely causal-
mechanical one, since the function or purpose of the part plays an ineliminable role in
the explanation of the part and its activities. This Galenic view of anatomy, with its
explicitly Aristotelian reliance on final causes, largely dominated medical thought until
the seventeenth century. William Harvey’s On the Motion of the Heart and Blood (De
motu cordis) was seen by many of his contemporaries (e.g., Hobbes, Descartes) as a
turning point away from the Galenic or Aristotelian approaches to anatomy, with their
appeal to final causes, toward the new mechanistic and experimental science of the
seventeenth century (French 1994). His attempt to empirically establish the structure
and motion of the heart without ever claiming to have identified the final cause of
circulation, as well as his use of mechanical analogies, such as the analogy from the
expansion of the arteries to the inflation of a glove, provide some support for this
assessment. Robert Boyle, however, offered a different interpretation of Harvey’s work.
Boyle saw it as amenable to his ‘compatibilist’ approach that attempted to show that
“mechanical and teleological explanations of biological phenomena are compatible”
(Lennox 1983: 38). Recent commentators have also suggested Harvey was strongly
influenced by Aristotelian teleological thinking, and thus is a liminal figure in the
transition from vitalist to purely mechanistic explanation in physiology and medicine
(Distelzweig 2014, 2016; Lennox 2017), although Lennox notes that “Harvey appears
to be pressing the analogy between art and nature in ways that are not Aristotelian but
more Platonic in spirit” (Lennox 2017: 191).
Immanuel Kant’s analysis of teleology in the Critique of Judgment (Kant 1790 [2000])
also played an influential role in biology. According to Kant, humans inevitably
understand living things as if they are teleological systems (Zammito 2006). However,
on Kant’s view, the teleology we see in the natural world is only apparent; it is the
product of our limited cognitive faculties (see section 3 of the entry on Kant’s
aesthetics). But in addition, according to Kant, there is a certain non-machine-like
character of organisms, evident in their ability to grow and reproduce, that leads to a
type of mechanical inexplicability. Hannah Ginsborg (2004) argues that for Kant this
impossibility of explaining organisms in solely mechanistic terms does not itself
distinguish them from complex artifacts; but, she argues, Kant thought that the
regenerative and reproductive aspects of organisms lead us to attribute a kind of natural
purposiveness that is absent in artifacts, paralleling Aristotle’s justification for natural,
immanent teleology. Kantian analysis of this sort shows up in early nineteenth century
research in what would come to be called organic chemistry. Scientists at that time
sought to determine whether living systems were nothing more than complex chemical
systems, fully analyzable in terms of physical and chemical processes. Those
researchers adopting a Kantian approach advocated a teleo-mechanist strategy to make
sense of the goal-directed nature of living systems, which sought to treat the organism
as both a means and an end and thus incorporated elements of both teleological and
mechanistic explanation (Lenoir 1982).
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the status of teleology in biology was also
contested as part of the vitalist-mechanist debate in physiology and medicine (for an
overview, see the first section of the entry on life). Whereas mechanists sought to
describe all living things in purely mechanical terms, vitalists argued that physical
properties alone could not explain the goal-directed organization of living things. They
claimed that ‘vital forces’ were also necessary to explain the difference between
physical and living systems. Although they fell out of favor, some vitalist accounts
persisted through the twentieth-century, for instance, in philosopher Henri Bergson’s
‘élan vital’ (see the section creative evolution in the entry on Bergson) and in biologist-
cum-philosopher Hans Driesch’s concept of ‘entelechy’ (Driesch 1908).
Much debate over the role of teleology in biology in the twentieth century, especially
amongst the architects of the ‘modern synthesis’, traces back to Charles Darwin’s
theory of evolution by natural selection. Biologist and philosopher Michael Ghiselin,
expressing a common interpretation of Darwin’s role in this debate, claims in his
preface to Darwin’s work on orchids that Darwin’s theory succeeded in “getting rid of
teleology and replacing it with a new way of thinking about adaptation” (Darwin
1862/1877 [1984: xiii] cited in Lennox 1993: 409). On this view, the theory of natural
selection explains how species “have been modified so as to acquire that perfection of
structure and co-adaptation” without any appeal to a benevolent Creator (Darwin 1859:
3). Prior to Darwin, the best explanation for biological adaptation was the argument
from design, most influentially presented in William Paley’s Natural Theology (Paley
1802): living things have the structure and behaviors that they do because they were
designed for certain purposes by a benevolent Creator (see the entry on natural theology
and natural religion). Darwin’s theory provides biology with the resources to resist this
argument, offering a fully naturalized explanation for adaptation. Although most agree
that Darwin’s theory does indeed purge evolutionary biology of any illicit appeal to
external, Platonic teleology, there is disagreement as to whether or not Darwin’s
evolutionary explanations are teleological (see the relevant section of the entry
on Darwinism). Even Darwin’s contemporaries disagreed as to whether or not the
theory of natural selection purged teleological explanations from biology or revived
them (Lennox 2010). In any case, it is clear that Darwin used the language of ‘final
causes’ to describe the function of biological parts in his Species Notebooks and
throughout his life; he also reflected frequently about the relationship between natural
selection and teleology (Lennox 1993).

2. Explanatory Teleonaturalism
Philosophical naturalism denotes a broad range of attitudes towards ontological
questions. We use “teleonaturalism” to denote a similarly broad range of naturalistic
accounts of teleology in biology that are united in rejecting any dependence on mental
or intentional notions in explicating the use of the teleological terms in biological
contexts. Thus, those who reject teleomentalism typically seek truth conditions for
teleological claims in biology that are grounded in non-mental facts about organisms
and their traits.
Some teleonaturalists analyze teleological language as primarily descriptive rather than
explanatory, maintaining that teleology in biology is appropriate for biological systems
which show purposive, goal-directed patterns of behavior (for which Pittendrigh (1958)
coined the term “teleonomic”). For such views, the primary scientific challenge is to
explain teleonomy, not to use teleonomy as explanans (see Thompson 1987). While
cybernetics lost its appeal in the latter part of the twentieth century, more recent
approaches to living systems that treat them as self-organizing or “autopoietic”
(Maturana & Varela 1980) bear certain affinities to the descriptive attitude towards
teleonaturalism—although most proponents claim that the concepts developed within
these approaches are explanatory.
Hence, most teleonaturalists favor accounts of biological function which make the
explanatory role of this notion a desideratum. Naturalistic accounts typically aim to
satisfy two additional desiderata. They should distinguish genuine biological functions
from accidental utility (such as noses supporting glasses), and they should capture the
normative dimension of function in order to preserve a function-malfunction
distinction. Although these three desiderata are neither universally accepted nor are they
adequacy conditions in the strict sense, they have nevertheless achieved canonical status
within the contemporary debate over biological functions.
In the subsequent sections we divide various ways in which different teleonaturalist
accounts of function can be distinguished. Our first distinction is between (a) views
which assimilate functional explanations in biology to patterns of explanation in the
non-biological sciences, and (b) views treat functional explanation as distinctively
biological.

3. Assimilation to Non-Biological Explanations


Ernest Nagel (1961) and Carl Hempel (1965) provide early attempts by philosophers of
science to directly assimilate functional explanation in biology to more general patterns
of explanation. In particular, they both consider functional explanation within the
framework of the Deductive-Nomological account of scientific explanation. They
consider the functional claims to be related to explanations of the presence of a trait in
an organism. Their accounts differ primarily on whether to say that a trait T has
function F in organism O when T is sufficient to produce F in O(Hempel’s version) or
when T is necessary to produce F in O (Nagel’s version).
Larry Wright (1973, 1976) also offers an explanatory account targeted on the presence
of the trait, but he criticizes the prior accounts for failing to capture the apparent goal-
directedness of functional traits. His so-called “etiological” analysis holds that the
function of X is Z means (a) Xis there because it does Z, and (b) Z is a consequence (or
result) of X’s being there. Because of the intended breadth of Wright’s analysis, it has
been attacked on conceptual grounds (e.g., Boorse 1976), but the general thrust of the
etiological account survives in accounts of function based on natural selection,
discussed in section 4.
Cummins (1975) criticized both Hempel and Nagel on the grounds that the proper
target of explanation of biological function claims is not the presence of a trait, but the
capacities of biological organs and organisms. Sophisticated capacities can be analyzed
in terms of the contributions that their components make to those capacities. For
example, the heart of a bilaterian animal pumps blood, which in this way contributes to
the capacity of the organism to deliver oxygen and nutrients to its tissues. The heart
itself can be further decomposed into parts (chambers, valves, etc.) which each play
different functional roles in contributing to that organ’s capacity to pump blood. Among
philosophers, this approach to functional analysis is most associated with Cummins
(1975), although biologists have advanced similar ideas, sometimes independently
(Hinde 1975; Lauder 1982), and indeed the approach can be traced much further back,
as the quotation from William Harvey in the introduction suggests. Cummins’ ideas
about functional analysis have been incorporated in recent discussion on mechanisms in
the biological sciences (see the entry on mechanisms in science). For instance, Craver
(2007) explicitly draws on Cummins (1975) in his account and is important for moving
teleological descriptions down to the molecular level (see also, Craver 2001, 2013).
According to Cummins, although biological systems certainly have capacities that are
uniquely biological, there is nothing specifically biological about the pattern of
explanation offered by functional analysis; it applies equally well, for example to the
contributions made by the components of artifacts (Lewens 2004), for example the
contributions of the engine’s pistons in the capacity of an automobile to transport
people. Because of the generality of the framework, it is also possible to give a
functional analysis of how some part of a biological system contributes to outcomes
usually treated as negative, such as disease or death. Some commentators regard this as
a virtue of the approach, while others regard it as too detached from standard biological
practice. Relatedly, the functional analysis approach fails to live up to the commonly-
held desideratum that an adequate account should provide an analysis of malfunction—
a desideratum that Cummins explicitly rejects (see also Wouters 1999 and Davies
2001). A heart with a hole in its septum may not circulate blood at a level sufficient to
sustain life, but it thereby simply lacks that function.
4. Natural Selection Accounts
Many philosophers of biology believe that functional explanation is uniquely
appropriate to biology, turning to Darwin’s theory of descent with modification to
ground the practice of attributing functions. Like Wright, Hempel, and Nagel, natural-
selection teleonaturalists take the primary target of explanation to be the presence of
various traits in organisms.
Here we distinguish between two ways of using natural selection to ground biological
teleology.

• Indirect approaches treat the adaptive, self-organizing nature of living cells and
organisms as the natural basis for teleological properties of their traits, but give
background credit to the power of natural selection to produce such self-
organizational complexity as is found in living systems.
• Direct approaches invoke natural selection explicitly when explicating
functional claims, either in an etiological sense based on the history of selection
or in a dispositional sense based on the fitness of organisms possessing the
traits.

4.1 Indirect
The primary motivation for the earliest indirect, cybernetic accounts of biological
teleology were to explain the apparent purposiveness of biological organisms, for
instance, the maintenance of constant body temperature in endotherms. These accounts
aimed to provide a naturalized explanation for the goal-directed behavior of biological
systems through reference to their organization. In an influential early paper, Norbert
Wiener and colleagues sought to explain the goal-directed behavior of biological
organisms and machines as arising from their utilization of negative feedback
mechanisms (Rosenblueth et al. 1943; for further development see also Braithwaite
(1953), Sommerhoff (1950) and Nagel (1953)). Attributions of teleological, or goal-
directed, behavior to animals or machines, they argued, meant nothing more than
“purpose controlled by feed-back” (Rosenblueth et al. 1943, 23).
This cybernetic account of teleology inspired biologist Colin Pittendrigh to introduce
the term ‘teleonomy’ into the literature (Pittendrigh 1958). With this neologism,
Pittendrigh hoped to purge biology of any vestiges of Aristotelian final causes whilst
providing biology with an acceptable term to describe adapted, goal-directed systems.
This term was taken up in the 1960s by evolutionary biologists such as Ernst Mayr
(1974) and George Williams (1966), as well as by scientists studying cell metabolism
and regulation, who were just beginning to elucidate the structural and molecular basis
for cellular feedback mechanisms (Monod & Jacob 1961; Davis 1961). According to
proponents, adopting a cybernetic account of goal-directed behavior in biological
systems splits the explanatory problem in two. On the one hand, teleological activity in
the biological world could be explained by the presence of teleonomic systems with
negative feedback mechanisms, whereas the very presence of those teleonomic systems
in living organisms, on the other hand, could be explained by the action of natural
selection (Monod 1970 [1971]).
Although explicit cybernetic accounts of biological teleology have fallen out of favor,
other organizational approaches to biological function have had a recent resurgence in
the function literature. These organizational, or systems-theoretic, approaches often
build upon early cybernetic accounts or aim to extend Maturana and Varela’s (1980)
influential notion of autopoiesis, which refers to the self-organizing, self-maintaining
characteristic of living systems (see the entry on Embodied Cognition for further
description). These accounts identify the function of a biological trait through an
analysis of the role the trait plays within an organized system in contributing to both its
own persistence and the persistence of the system as a whole (Schlosser 1998;
McLaughlin 2001; Mossio et al. 2009; Saborido et al. 2011; Moreno & Mossio 2015).
Although they differ in their details, organizational approaches to biological function
generally agree that a trait token T has a function F when the performance
of F by T contributes to the maintenance of the complex organization of the system,
which in turn results in T’s continued existence. For example, the heart has the function
to pump blood, according to these accounts, because it contributes to the maintenance
of the entire organism by causing the blood to circulate, which facilitates the circulation
of oxygen and nutrients. At the same time, this circulation is also responsible in part for
the persistence of the heart itself, since the heart also benefits directly from this function
(i.e., the cardiac cells receive the oxygen and nutrients necessary for their survival).
Similar to direct natural selection accounts, organizational accounts can be forward or
backward-looking: the function of a trait may identify its dispositional contribution to
the complex organization of the system which results in its own persistence or
reproduction in the future (forward-looking; Schlosser 1998), or a functional attribution
may identify a trait’s past contribution (etiological, or backward-looking; McLaughlin
2001). Alvaro Moreno’s group adopts a third position. They claim their organizational
account of function unifies these two perspectives (Mossio et al 2009; cf. Artiga &
Martinez 2016). All these organizational accounts differ from direct natural selection
accounts, however, in that they make no appeal to the selection history of the trait.
Instead, the function of a trait can be inferred from the present or past role of the trait in
maintaining itself within the complex, organized system without further holding that the
trait was selected for that role. On this view, functional attributions in biology are
explanatory not because of selection, but rather because of the causal role traits play in
contributing to the maintenance of the organization of a system, which in turn enables
the traits themselves to persist.

4.2 Direct Natural Selection Approaches


Accounts of biological function which refer to natural selection typically have the form
that a trait's functions causally explain the existence or maintenance of that trait in a
given population via the mechanism of natural selection. William Wimsatt (1972), Ruth
Millikan (1984), and Karen Neander (1991a), all treat the past history of natural
selection as the selection process that legitimizes the notion of a biological function.
Within such approaches there is a dispute about the exact role of natural selection,
whether as a source of variation (sometimes referred to as the “creative” role of natural
selection, e.g., Neander 1988; see also Ayala 1970, 1977), or only as a filter on
variations that arise independently (Sober 1984).
Positions which ground functional claims in natural selection have much in common
with Wright’s etiological account. However, because the grounding is specific to
biology, they may avoid the kinds of counterexamples to Wright’s account introduced
by critics such as Christopher Boorse, predicated on the idea that Wright’s account is
intended to provide a more general conceptual analysis. A related challenge stems from
the claim that pre-Darwinian thinkers such as Harvey correctly identified functional
properties of biological organs, and that natural selection cannot therefore be a
requirement for the proper conceptual analysis of function. Defenders of direct natural
selection accounts of function have responded in different ways. One way, exemplified
by Millikan (1989), is to argue that conceptual analysis has no role to play in
articulating what is essentially a theoretical term within modern evolutionary biology.
Another way, exemplified by Neander (1991b), is to say that the task of conceptual
analysis is appropriate but restricted to the concepts of the relevant scientific
community.
Paul Davies (2001) and Arno Wouters (2005) argue that both Millikan and Neander are
incorrect to treat malfunction as an important theoretical or conceptual aspect of the
practice of attributing functions by biologists. Wouters declares the wish that the study
of biological function should be liberated “from the yoke of the philosophy of mind”
(2005: 148). However, Ema Sullivan-Bissett (2017) argues that while the task of
explicating biological practice by philosophers of biology is usefully distinguished from
the broader goals of philosophers pursuing naturalistic accounts of mind and language
(see the entry on teleological theories of mental content), the latter serves legitimate
goals. She regards an account of malfunction to be integral to the latter project even if
not to the former. Davies (2001) argues that the natural selection accounts are unable to
provide an account of malfunction insofar as they individuate traits functionally,
entailing that a putatively malfunctioning trait is not an instance of the functionally-
defined kind. Sullivan-Bissett addresses Davies’ objection by incorporating a structural
condition on the individuation of traits. (See also Garson 2016: 48–49, for additional
discussion and critique of Davies’ view.)
Returning to the kinds of traits studied by biologists, some theorists make a distinction
between the initial spread of a new phenotypic trait in a population and the more recent
maintenance of traits in populations. Take a trait such as feathers, arising in a
population by whatever means. Initially this trait may have spread because of a role in
mating displays. Later, feathers may have contributed to improved thermoregulation.
And still later, the trait may have become more widely distributed because feathers
make good flight control surfaces. If display or thermoregulatory functions of feathers
become less important in some niches, the trait may nonetheless be maintained in a
population due to selection for its flight-control function. The shifting functional profile
may also be correlated with differentiation in form, such as between downy feathers and
flight feathers.

You might also like