You are on page 1of 7

04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem.

Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

You have 2 free member-only stories left this month. Sign up for Medium and get an extra one

The Four-Color Theorem


Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical Challenge To Re-Define The Modern Theorem

Jesus Najera Follow


Oct 22, 2019 · 12 min read

Few mathematical theorems are ever covered & publicized to the greater mainstream
(aka non-academic) crowd. Sometimes, because, well, math is boring to sane people,
but mainly because many of these theorems are brutally convoluted & unnecessarily
hard to grasp. The sweet spot between simplicity & significance is rarely found in the
general textbook of unsolved math problems; however, the topic of this piece, is one of
the rare few exceptions that very much does strike that balance.

The Four Color Theorem, or the Four Color Map Theorem, in its simplest form, states
that no more than four colors are required to color the regions of any map so that no two
adjacent regions have the same color. As promised, that’s a theorem any elementary-
level student can grasp. A second, more math-y form of the theorem states that: given
any separation of a plane into contiguous regions producing a figure called a map, no
more than four colors are required to color the regions of the map so that no two
adjacent regions have the same color. A bit more complicated, but confidently graspable
at an undergraduate-level. A third & final way of stating the theorem, that’s vastly more
practical but exponentially more complex, requires the language of graph theory. In
graph-theoretic language, the four color theorem claims that the vertices of every planar
graph can be colored with at most four colors without two adjacent vertices receiving
https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 1/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

the same color, or, in other words: every planar graph is four colorable. Don’t worry if
this last description flew over your head, the point is to simply introduce it & preview
the connection to graph theory— we’ll take the time to define & digest it later on.

In addition to its inviting simplicity, the Four Color Theorem is famous for its inflection
point in the history of math: it was the very first major theorem “proved” through
brute-forcing scenarios with a computer. In today’s day-&-age that’s a rather
historically-significant breakthrough. As we’ll see shortly, despite a massive entry of
theorems since 1852, the Four-Color theorem had outright resisted any attempts at a
general conjecture for decades. And even when a likely conjecture reared its head in
1976, the Four-Color Theorem refused to yield to any general map. Which, in turn,
forced the latest entrants to turn to this questionable method of provability (computing
all scenarios). The implications of accepting this method as a general proof rightly raised
questions about what it means to prove a theorem. Indeed, thanks to the Four-Color
Theorem, people are still debating the role of computers in mathematical proof & the
future of mathematics as a human endeavor.

Before continuing, pause now & take a moment to imagine a complex map that you
believe requires more than four colors. Go ahead & quickly sketch it out — then try
coloring it in (or filling it in with integers 1–4). Myself included, I’ve yet to come across
someone who intuitively believes this theorem at first sight; it just seems false. And yet,
throughout its history, not a single counterexample has been discovered. We’ll eventually
walk-through the logic of the latest accepted conjecture, however, to satisfy our curiosity
for a deeper understanding, we’ll first start at the very origin of the problem.

Origin
The Four Color Theorem burst into the scene as nothing more than a curious
observation. First pondered upon by one Francis Guthrie in early 1852, the proposal
occurred while trying to color the map of England, when he noticed that only four
different colors were needed. Shortly thereafter graduating from the University of
London, he went on to study law; by this time, however, his younger brother Frederick
Guthrie had become a student of the famed mathematician August De Morgan. Francis
shared his original observation as well as his fruitless attempts with Frederick to ask &
enroll De Morgan on the quest to bring forth a conjecture.

De Morgan was unable to give an answer, however, as history shows he was instantly
hooked. On 23 October 1852, he wrote the following to William Hamilton, a famous
Irish mathematician & astronomer:

A student of mine asked me today to give him a reason for a fact which I did not know was a
fact — and do not yet. He says that if a figure be anyhow divided and the compartments
differently coloured so that figures with any portion of common boundary line are
differently coloured — four colours may be wanted, but not more — the following is the case
in which four colours are wanted. Query cannot a necessity for five or more be invented.
…… If you retort with some very simple case which makes me out a stupid animal, I think I
must do as the Sphynx did….

https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 2/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

De Morgan’s self-deprecating humor towards the end of the letter underlines a stunning
bemusement that’s consistent with first impressions of the Four Color Theory.
Regardless, with the problem now in the hands of one of the most prominent
mathematicians of his generation, it quickly spread like wild-fire; thus, officially
sparking the race for a generalized conjecture.

Historical Attempts
After approximately three decades since the observation was first proposed, assistance
arrived from one Arthur Cayley. Flustered by the unsolved nature of this seeming-
simple problem, Cayley officially enlisted while attending a meeting of the London
Mathematical Society; half-way through the meeting, he asked everyone in attendance
whether anyone had found a solution. With no one volunteering an attempt let alone a
solution, he headed home to face the challenge head-on.

Less than a year later, 1879, Cayley returned with a publication submitted to the Royal
Geographical Society (On The Colouring Of Maps). Lacking a proper solution, he
nevertheless drastically pushed forth the stagnant search by explaining his shortcomings
& attempts at reframing the problem. One of these productive shifts in perspective
stemmed from his question: “what if a particular map is already successfully colored
with four colors, & we add another area, can we still keep the same coloring?”
Essentially an inverse inquiry, it helped start another path towards a general theorem.

Next in the chronicles of the Four-Color Theorem arrived Alfred Bray Kempe. Another
London barrister (lawyer) who studied mathematics under Cayley at Cambrige, Kempe
attempted his hand at the impossible proof to surprisingly fruitful results. In early July of
1879, Alfred Bray Kempe announced in Nature that he had a proof of the Four Colour
Conjecture.

The core of Kempe’s theorem relied on a proven theorem, a now-common graph theory
operation, & a completely original method. The crux of Kempe’s theorem revolved
around the proven fact that every planar graph must have a vertex with degree less
than six. From this postulate, Kempe’s proof consisted of scrubbing, or patching, sub-
graphs of maps by removing vertices with four vertices or less. Why patch out sub-
https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 3/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

graphs of four vertices or less? Because with four vertices or less, these sub-graphs were
undeniably four-colorable. Once all minor (less than four vertices) vertices were patched
out, Kempe’s proof consisted of coloring in & uncovering sub-graphs until the original
graph remained. The big trick in his proof, his greatest contribution to the effort, was his
inventive method of coloring the remaining sub-graphs. Instead of using all four colors,
Kempe observed that many, though not all, many adjacent graphs only needed two colors .

The core method of Kemp’s theorem relied on an inventive method of his aptly named
Kempe chains. A Kempe chain is a “chain” of vertices that are colored with two
alternating colors. Though possible to explain orally, a visual example explains the
concept in a much more succinct way. For example, let’s pretend the map of the United
States below represents a graph. A Kempe chain is an adjacent, alternating coloring of N
units. Below, in our map (graph), we can see adjacent states alternating in colors: New
York (Blue), Pennsylvania (Red), Ohio (Blue), Indiana (Red), & Illinois (Blue):

Shoutout Mark Walters: http://historyofmathematics.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/09/2004-Walters.pdf

The example above is a clear Blue-Red Kempe chain. It conveys which vertices are
colorable with alternating colors; perhaps even more importantly, however, it provides
information about which vertices (states) cannot join the current chain, for example,
California or Florida (since neither is adjacent to the current chain). These chains served
as the backbone of Kempe’s proof of the four-color theorem, by patching out small sub-
graphs, then coloring in the remaining maps with Kempe chains. For the longer part of
at least a decade, it was believed that Kempe successfully cracked it. Receiving
tremendous acclaim, he was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society, served as its treasurer
& was shortly knighted.

False Positive
Unfortunately, despite the premature celebrations, as history shows, Kempe’s proof was
indeed wrong. The Four Colour Theorem returned to being the Four Colour Conjecture in
1890 with a publication submitted by a lecturer at Durnham, England by the name of

https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 4/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

Percy John Heawood. He showed that Kempe’s proof was wrong, however, he couldn’t
correct the mistake himself:

The aim here is rather destructive than constructive, for it will be shown that there is a
defect in the now apparently recognized proof.

The theorem flaw hid in plain sight for over a decade before rearing it’s head,
nevertheless, Heawood rekindled the race to prove the four-color theorem.

The next waves of advancement came from across the pond. First, George David
Birkhoff, one of America’s first prominent mathematicians, contributed by constraining
Kempe’s theorem through finding certain large reducible configurations. From there,
Philip Franklin, an MIT mathematician, expanded upon Birkhoff’s work to prove that
Four-Color Theorem holds true for all graphs with 25 or fewer vertices. What followed
from the 1910s to the 1950s was a flurry of collaborate effort to prove the theorem for
graphs with higher & higher vertices; thereby inching slightly closer to a general proof.

By 1968, any counter-example to the Four-Color Theorem must have at least 41 vertices.
In addition to large reducible configurations, another focus of those on the hunt was a
little something called unavoidable sets. The best known method for finding
unavoidable sets at the time an approach called discharging, invented by a Heinrich
Heesch. Seeing the need for an equilibrium between reducible configurations &
unavoidable sets, Heesch was likely the first mathematician who publicly stated a belief
that the Four-Color Conjecture could be proved by finding an unavoidable set of
reducible configurations. Last, & equally important, Heesch observed that the set
necessary could contain up to ten-thousand configurations. Proving ten-thousand
scenarios, by hand, unfortunately, required a Herculean physical task. Fortunately, the
timing couldn’t have been more perfect as the tide was turning on a previously-niche
technology: the burgeoning field of computer science. High-speed computers made such
a proof possible.

The Age of Computers


Computers turned out to be exactly the tool our pioneers required to properly test the
configurations for reducibility. The complexity of a vertex or map configuration, known
as a ring-size, is calculated by the number of vertices “surrounding” or “encapsulating”
it. In the early 60s, however, computers were only powerful enough to test figures with
ring-size less than 12, — which was insufficient for the proof. Not a programmer
himself, Heesh was unaware of this limitation & moved to partner up with a high school
teacher by the name of Karl Durre. On November 23, 1965, almost an entire century
since it’s inception, the first reducibility test was run on a CDC 1604 — a computer at the
Institute of Technology in Hannover, Germany. It was surprisingly successful. After a
month of back-testing, the pair tested the program for the first time with a configuration
of ring-size nine whose reducibility had been previously unknown. It worked, however,
Durre had already noticed that computing resources in Germany would not suffice. So
the pair made several trips to the United States to much more powerful computers — yet
the problem still remained unsolved. Heesch, frustrated & flustered, finally returned

https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 5/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

home to Hannover, vowing to finish the proof of the Four-Color Theorem on his own.
History responded with a hard nien, however, as due to disagreements with the German
research community, he failed to acquire additional funding & resources.

Heesch did, however, manage to metaphorically pass on the torch to a curious student of
his. One Wolfgang Haken, an attendee of Heesh’s lectures on the Four Color Theory,
gained a lifelong interest in the problem & reached out to Heesch to re-motivate him. It
worked. Another two years into their quest, & once again funding became an issue.
Heesch, now aging & burnt out, finally threw the towel in. Still enthusiastic but lost
without his mentor, Haken declared “Right now I’m quitting. I consider this to be the
point beyond which one cannot go.”

It was at this point that, for the final time, that one wearied soldier’s pessimism was
outweighed by another soldier’s optimism. Upon hearing about Haken’s resignation,
another zealous academic, this time Kenneth Appel, a mathematician & computer
programmer professor at the University of Illinois, insisted that he & Haken could finish
this journey. Haken, revived by this enthusiasm pressed onward. In the summer of 1976,
after several hundred pages of scrutinizing details & over 1200 hours of output on a
powerful computer, the four-color conquest finally came to a halt. Appel celebrated the
success by etching the statement ‘Modulo careful checking, it appears that four colors
suffice’ onto the department’s blackboard. Appel & Haken presented their proof to a
group of mathematicians at a meeting in Toronto. Shortly after this presentation, they
polished and published the proof, which is lengthy but boils down to checking 1,936
cases for reducibility.

The End?
Fun fact, each of the 1,936 cases required a computer crunch up to 500k logical
operations. The controversy of the Four Color Theorem persists: the validity of the proof
still remains in question to this day. And for good reason. Mathematicians, & the
community as a whole, are now left between a rock & a hard place: come to a consensus
in our acceptance of a new, computer-aided type of proof or re-attempt to prove the Four
Color Theorem manually.

Regardless of all the skepticism, it was indeed commemorated as a valid proof. The
University of Illinois mathematics department adopting the slogan “Four Colors Suffice.”
Predictably though, this did not completely end research on the four-color theorem; as a
whole, the community is reluctant to cede to the proof as it stands. So, as expected,
progress has slowed but never fully stopped. The most recent effort came in 1996, when
Neil Robertson, Daniel Sanders, Paul Seymour,& Robin Thomas made a giant leap in
reducing the cases of the unavoidable set to only 633 configurations. Though again, this
method strongly resembles that of Appel & Haken in which it requires computational
checking, it cannot be verified by hand. As David Burton, an associate professor & math
historian states:

It cannot be ruled out that a short and convincing proof of the conjecture may yet be found,
but it is just as conceivable that the only valid proofs will involve massive computations

https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 6/7
04/02/2021 The Four-Color Theorem. Its Surreal Simplicity & Critical… | by Jesus Najera | Cantor’s Paradise | Medium

requiring computer assistance. If this is the case, we must acknowledge that a new and
interesting type of theorem has emerged, one having no verification by traditionally
accepted methods. Admitting these theorems will mean that the secure notion of a
mathematical proof is open to revision.

Perhaps the largest irony in the near-two century-long search for an answer to the Four
Color Theory stems from the overall lack of urgency in solving it. Originally stumbled
upon by a curious barrister coloring in a map, one would expect that the theorem would
be relevant & applicable to cartography: it isn’t so. Cartography has evolved quite
smoothly with very little care for the Four Color Theory. Yet, from the many advances in
graph theory & the overall push to re-define theorems in modern times, it’s clear that
the journey has had measurable outcomes. The ultimate jigsaw puzzle — simple to
understand, yet impossible to solve, the Four Color Theorem holds a special place in the
history of both math & computer science. Perhaps we may never find an elegant proof to
the four-color theorem & it really is an inflection point in the history of theorems. Alas,
as always, only time will tell.

This essay is part of a series of stories on math-related topics, published in Cantor’s


Paradise, a weekly Medium publication. Thank you for reading!

Mathematics History Education Data Science Math

About Help Legal

Get the Medium app

https://medium.com/cantors-paradise/the-four-color-theorem-8eece6ab6b12 7/7

You might also like