You are on page 1of 15

The Two-Party System and Duverger's Law: An Essay on the History of Political Science

Author(s): William H. Riker


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 76, No. 4 (Dec., 1982), pp. 753-766
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1962968 .
Accessed: 05/09/2013 04:36

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
The Two-party System and Duverger's Law:
An Essay on the History of Political Science
WILLIAM H. RIKER
University of Rochester

Science involves the accumulation of knowledge, which means not only the formulation of new
sentences about discoveries but also the reformulation of empirically falsified or theoretically dis-
credited old sentences. Science has therefore a history that is mainly a chronicle and interpretation of
a series of reformulations. It is often asserted that political science has no history. Although this asser-
tion is perhaps motivated by a desire to identify politics with belles lettres, it may also have a
reasonable foundation, in that political institutions may change faster than knowledge can be ac-
cumulated. To investigate whether propositions about evanescent institutions can be scientifically
falsified and reformulated, I examine in this essay the history of the recent and not wholly accepted
revisions of the propositions collectively called Duverger's law: that the plurality rule for selecting the
winner of elections favors the two-party system. The body of the essay presents the discovery, revi-
sion, testing, and reformulation of sentences in this series in order to demonstrate that in at least one
instance in political science, knowledge has been accumulated and a history exists.

One defining characteristic of science as distinct the phrase "accumulation of knowledge" we


from belles lettres, criticism, and philosophic mean not only that the corpus of propositions is
speculation is the accumulation of knowledge in growing, but also that each one of the series of
the form of more or less verifiable propositions revisions is more general or more precise than its
about the natural world. In the conventional view predecessor.
of science, propositions are verified deductively In this view, every branch of science has a his-
when they are inferred indisputably from an tory which is a chronicle of the marginal revisions
axiom system and verified empirically when they of propositions leading up to the currently ac-
have survived repeated attempts at falsification cepted ones. This is what Thomas Kuhn (1970)
(Popper 1963). In practice, however, scientific calls "normal science." Political science, which is
propositions are typically neither so theoretically my concern in this essay, has, however, often
indisputable nor so empirically unfalsifiable as the been said to have no history, which is of course
conventional view suggests. Rather, most re- merely a way of saying that it contains no ac-
ported tests of propositions involve either dis- cumulation of knowledge and that it is therefore
crediting a theory or successful falsification. The not a branch of science. Many political scientists
triumphant scientist then replaces the proposition have been persuaded to believe this assertion, so
he or she has falsified with a revised one, which that in despair they are inclined to abandon the
passes the test that the initial proposition failed. search for scientific generalizations. (This despair
When I speak of a more or less verified proposi- is, I believe, the root of the movement toward
tion, therefore, I mean the one that is the current phenomenology and hermeneutics and other ef-
end point of a series of revisions and that is, at forts to turn political science into a belles-lettristic
least provisionally, accepted by the relevant por- study.)
tion of the scientific community (Riker 1977). By The rationale for the assertion that political
science lacks a history is that political institutions,
the main topic of generalizations in the field, are
themselves so evanescent that the subject and
This historywas writtenlargelyat the instigationof predicate classes of scientific propositions change
studentsin my courseon the scope of politicalscience, more swiftly than the propositions can be per-
whereI haveusedthis historyto illustratewhatI believe fected. It is indeed true that in comparison with
Thomas Kuhn (1970) meant by "normal science." I the physical and biological sciences, which deal
have, of course,benefittedgreatlyfrom theircomments with the unchanging
as well as from the commentsof my colleague,Harold properties of matter, and
Stanley.This paperwas presentedin an earlierform to even in comparison with psychological sciences,
the AmericanAssociationfor the Advancementof Sci- which deal with the relatively more plastic proper-
ence, Washington,D.C., 1982,on a panelassembledby ties of the human psyche, the habits and institu-
StevenBramsand to the InternationalPoliticalScience tions studied in the social sciences are swiftly
Association,Rio de Janeiro,1982,on a panelassembled changing. But generalizations are neither so hard
by David Apter. to come by nor so hard to perfect as this criticism
753

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
754 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
implies. Many of the propositions of social sci- observation of their relationship with the number
ence involve an interplay between permanent of political parties:
psychological characteristics of humans and in- (1) Plurality voting-rather misleadingly called
stitutional structures. This feature implies some the simple-majority, single-ballot system by
degree of permanence for the subject and predi- Duverger-in which the unique winner is the can-
cate classes of generalizations in social science. didate with the most votes. With two or fewer
For example, the law of demand in economics candidates, the winner has a simple majority of
that, with appropriate qualifications, demand the votes cast; with three or more candidates, the
curves do not slope upward-is mainly psycho- winner may have only a plurality.
logical in character and is indeed a better formu- (2) Run-off majority voting among three or
lated and more thoroughly verified law of more candidates with two ballots, in which at the
behavior than any to be found in the science of first ballot the winners are the two candidates with
psychology itself. Even when the psychological the largest and second largest number of votes,
component is smaller and the institutional compo- and, at the second ballot between exactly these
nent is larger than in the law of demand, as is two, the winner is the candidate with a simple
typical in political science, lasting generalization is majority. Coupled with the two-ballot system are
still possible because many institutions (e.g., various alternative vote methods in which count-
voting and decisions by forming coalitions) are, ing, rather than voting, occurs twice, using the
when abstractly described, at least as old as writ- same definition of winning as in the two-ballot
ten history. system.
It should be the case, therefore, that political (3) Proportional representation, in which the
science, like any other science, has a history, even winners are those candidates who obtain some
if it has not heretofore been chronicled. My inten- quota of votes, usually v/(s + 1) or (v/(s + 1)) + 1,
tion in this essay is to demonstrate that a history where v is the number of votes cast and s is the
does exist, and my vehicle is a particular series of number of winners to be selected. Since s>1,
reformulations called Duverger's law. I am not some winners must have less than a plurality.
undertaking this demonstration out of chauvin- Although it is easy to clarify Duverger's ter-
ism, merely to claim for students of politics the minology, it is not at all easy to straighten out the
name and privilege of scientists, but rather to ambiguity in his statement of the relationship be-
show that the accumulation of knowledge is pos- tween electoral systems and the number of parties.
sible even when dealing with such fragile and tran- Is plurality voting a necessary condition of the
sitory phenomena as political institutions (Riker two-party system? or a sufficient condition? or
1977). This is also why I deal with Duverger's law, both? or neither? The claim that the relation is "a
a not very well accepted proposition dealing with sociological law" suggests causality or a necessary
institutions of only the last two hundred years. If and sufficient condition, whereas the use of
it is demonstrated that knowledge has accumu- "favors" suggests the relationship is at best prob-
lated, even in this not yet satisfactorily formulated abilistic, not deterministic. I suspect the formula-
"law" about an ephemeral institution, then I will tion was deliberately ambiguous because the
have demonstrated at least the possibility of the author was not himself entirely certain of what he
accumulation of knowledge about politics. wanted to claim. Just what the claim ought to be
is not immediately obvious, so I will settle the
I question as I survey the present state of knowl-
edge about Duverger's law.
Duverger's law proposes that "the simple-
majority single-ballot system favors the two-party II
system." Duverger described this sentence by say-
ing: "Of all the hypotheses . .. in this book, this Duverger's sentences appeared in print in 1951,
approaches most nearly perhaps to a true socio- but as is' usually the case with scientific laws,
logical law" (Duverger 1963, p. 217). Related to similar propositions had already been widely dis-
this sentence is another, which Duverger did not cussed and reformulated with some increasing
elevate to the status of law: "the simple-majority degree of sophistication.' Indeed, related propo-
system with second ballot and proportional repre- sitions appeared in popular discussion almost as
sentation favors multi-partyism" (Duverger 1963, soon as methods other than plurality voting were
p. 239). I will refer to the first proposition as the
law and to the second proposition as the hypothe-
'It is customaryto call the law by Duverger'sname,
sis. These propositions distinguish among three not becausehe had much to do with developingit but
kinds of electoral systems, which, although far ratherbecausehe was the first to dareto claimit was a
from a complete list of the systems in current use, law. The memorialhonors, therefore,a traitof charac-
are the only ones used widely enough to admit the ter as muchas a scientificbreakthrough.

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-party System and Duverger's Law 755
proposed or adopted for legislative elections in were met in Europe in the latter half of the nine-
which large numbers of people were expected to teenth century, but general public discussion on
vote. By "large numbers" I mean an electorate of the subject did not appear until the 1850s. In 1856
approximately 5 percent of the population, which Denmark, which then had a small electorate,
in an era of primitive medicine and poor diet was adopted a form of proportional representation for
perhaps 25 to 33 percent of the adult males. Such over half the members of its unicameral legisla-
electorates were constituted in America in the ture, and at about the same time, Lord John
eighteenth century and in Western Europe in the Russell's unsuccessful reform bills provided for
late nineteenth century. Once these large elec- what the British called "three-cornered" consti-
torates existed, there also existed a motive for tuencies, a rudimentary form of representation of
politicians to attempt to devise appropriate minorities in which each voter has two votes in a
methods to manipulate outcomes in elections, and three-member constituency. In 1859 Thomas Hare
hence methods other than plurality voting were in The Election of Representatives set forth an
discussed and adopted. Naturally proponents and elaborate method of proportional representation,
opponents of alternative methods also thought the single transferable vote, and in 1861 John
deeply about the consequences of alternative Stuart Mill popularized it in Considerations on
methods and thus began to discuss propositions Representative Government, which contained a
related to Duverger's law. philosophical justification of Hare's method. Mill
These propositions were to be expected, and it believed Parliament should contain "not just the
is quite likely that there is indeed some demon- two great parties alone," but representatives of
strable relation between electoral forms and the ''every minority . . . consisting of a sufficiently
structure of the party system. Whatever their large number," which number he defined pre-
other ideological or programmatic functions, cisely as the number of voters divided by the
political parties serve to organize elections. (For a number of seats (Mill 1910, p. 263). Mill argued
recent elaboration, see Katz 1980.) Politicians and that the Hare method would bring about this
candidates with some common interests-perhaps result, so from the very beginning of the discus-
only a common desire to win or perhaps also a sion, there was some dim appreciation of
common ideology or a common identification Duverger's hypothesis, although not necessarily
with a group-appeal to voters under a common of Duverger's law. The appreciation was quite
banner, and thereby generate political parties. dim, however, because in the parliamentary
Since one motive for the common appeal is the debate on cumulative voting in 1867, Mill ex-
desire to win, it is not surprising that the constitu- pressed himself in a way that clearly indicated that
tional definitions of winning have an effect on the he thought proportional representation would not
parties thereby generated. If winning is defined as upset the two great parties:
the most votes, that is, as a plurality, then one
The right honorablegentlemansaid one thing
might reasonably expect a two-party system owing that perfectlyamazedme. He said that ... it was
to the necessity under this definition of maximiz- wrongthat the representationof any community
ing votes. Since the best way, in the long run, to shouldrepresentit only in a singleaspect,should
get the most votes is to get more than half, each of representonly one interest-only its Tory or
two parties might be expected to structure a coali- Liberalopinion; and he added that, at present,
tion in the hope, before the election, of getting a this was not the case, but that such a state of
majority. Alternatively, if winning is defined as thingswouldbe producedby the adoptionof this
more than half the votes at a runoff election, can- proposal.I apprehendthat then, even morethan
didates do not necessarily have to maximize votes now, each party would desireto be represented
... by those men who wouldbe most acceptable
at the initial election-the second most votes in- to the generalbody of the constituenciesfully as
itially may be enough to win in the end. And if much, if not more, than they do now (Hansard
winning is defined as the achievement of some 1867, 3rd series, vol. 188, pp. 1103-04).
number of votes less than half (as is necessarily
the case under proportional representation), then Clearly Mill expected the proposed system would
the necessity of maximizing disappears entirely. In produce Tory free traders and Tory corn law sup-
short, when the definition of winning forces can- porters without upsetting the two-party system.2
didates to maximize votes in order to win (as in About the same degree of appreciation was
plurality systems), they have strong motives to
create a two-party system; but when the definition
'Leys (1959) has said that Mill understood Duverger's
of winning does not require them to maximize law, although what Leys and I have discussed relates to
votes (as in runoff and proportional systems), the effect of proportional representation (Duverger's
then this motive for two parties is absent. hypothesis), not to the effect of plurality voting
The twin conditions of a large electorate and (Duverger's law). In any event, Leys's remark is highly
proposals for methods other than plurality voting anachronistic. To say that Mill understood Duverger's

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
756 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
shared by the opponents of change. Disraeli, for have been formed and are kept together by major-
example, when speaking in the same debate ity voting" [emphasis added; Droop means, of
against cumulative voting (which was, however, course, plurality voting.
adopted in the form of the "limited vote" or two This is the earliest explicit statement of Duver-
votes per voter in three-member constituencies) ger's law that I have seen. By 1901 it was a com-
said: monplace. In the controversy over proportional
representation for the new Australian constitu-
I havealwaysbeen of the opinionwith respectto tion, in their preface to Proportional Representa-
this cumulativevotingand otherschemeshaving
for theirobject to representminorities,that they tion Applied to Party Government: A New Elec-
are admirableschemes for bringing crochetty toral System, Ashworth and Ashworth (1901, pp.
men into this House-an inconveniencewhich vii-viii) set up their problem thus:
we have hitherto avoided, although it appears
that we now have some few exceptions to the The claim that everysection of the people is en-
generalstate of things; IN.B.: John StuartMill titledto representationappears. .. so just that it
then sat on the otherside of the Housel but I do seems intolerable that a method should have
not think we ought to legislate to increasethe been used ... which excludesthe minority....
numberof specimens(Hansard1867, 3rd series, But in view of the adage that it is the excellence
vol. 188, p. 1112). of old institutionswhich preservesthem, it is
surelya rash conclusionthat the presentmethod
Quite recently Duff Spafford sent me what he of election has no compensating merit. We
and I believe is the earliest known explicit state- believe there is such a merit-namely, that the
ment of the law. Henry Droop, an English bar- present method of election has developed the
rister, advocate of proportional representation party system [emphasisin original; the party
systemreferredto is, of course, dual. Once this
and inventor of the Droop quota, wrote in 1869 truthis grasped,it is quite evidentthat the Hare
about plurality voting: system would be absolutelydestructiveto party
Each elector has practicallyonly a choice be- government.... The object of this book is to
tween two candidatesor sets of candidates.As suggesta reform,whichpossessesthe advantages
successdependsupon obtaininga majorityof the of both methods and the disadvantages of
aggregatevotes of all the electors,an electionis neither.
usually reduced to a contest between the two
most popular candidatesor sets of candidates. Needless to say, the Ashworths failed to achieve
Even if othercandidatesgo to the poll, the elec- this goal, but they do deserve credit for their clear
tors usually find out that their votes will be
thrown away, unless given in favour of one or enunciation of both Duverger's law and Duver-
other of the partiesbetweenwhom the election ger's hypothesis.
reallylies.
III
Droop was apparently influenced by an observa- In the previous section I reported a gradual
tion in an address by Ernest Naville, president of development culminating in a clear and unam-
the Geneva Association for Reform, which Droop biguous statement of both Duverger's proposi-
translated as follows: "When the majority alone tions twenty years after Hare and seventy years
[i.e., Naville meant "by the plurality rule"] before Duverger. In the succeeding half century
chooses the representatives of all, the electors in- scholarly support became quite general, so that it
evitably group themselves into two camps be- was indeed reasonable for Duverger to call one of
cause, to arrive at representation, it is necessary to them a law. The general theme of this develop-
obtain the majority." Naville did not apparently ment is that of an initial skepticism followed by
believe that this force was sufficient for the two- increasing acquiescence.
party system, and Droop's position in 1869 is am- A. Lawrence Lowell, whose books on compara-
biguous. But by 1881 he was prepared to argue tive politics dominated the field at the turn of the
"these phenomena [i.e., two-party systems] I can- century, thought that the two-party system was
not explain by any theory of a natural division essential for effective parliamentary government.
between opposing tendencies of thought, and the He attributed this system in Great Britain to the
only explanation which seems to me to account historical experience of the English people, but he
for them is that the two opposing parties into also thought that the absence of it in France was
which we find politicians divided in each of these owing to the majority system and the second
countries [United Kingdom, United States, etc.] ballot (Lowell 1896). Thus, in effect, he accepted
Duverger's hypothesis but not Duverger's law.
Other prominent scholars of that period were less
law is about like saying that the child with burnt fingers clear. Ostrogorski, for example, was so eager to
understands the chemical principles of combustion. do away with political parties by his own pet

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-partySystem and Duverger'sLaw 757
reforms that he never quite diagnosed the causes nent studentof comparativepolitics. In the initial
of structural features of parties (Ostrogorski edition(1924),he criticizedproportionalrepresen-
1908, vol. 2, p. 705). Practical publicists, excited tation in much the same way as had MacDonald
by the controversy over proportional representa- fifteen yearsearlier,that is, as a systemthat con-
tion, which was considered or adopted in most fused responsibility.In the second edition (1935),
European countries between 1900 and 1925, however, he added a postscript in which he
tended to favor proportional representation if blamed proportionalrepresentationin Italy and
they belonged to parties without a majority and to Germanyfor increasingthe numberof political
oppose it if they belonged to parties with the ma- parties.Then he attributedthe weaknessof execu-
jority or close to it. Implicitly, therefore, they tives and the instability of governmentsto the
behaved as if they agreed with Duverger's law. multiplicityof parties,and he explainedthe riseof
One author who explicitly stated this belief was J. Mussolini and Hitler as a reaction: "people
Ramsay MacDonald, later a Labour prime become so distractedby fumblinggovernments,
minister, who wrote frequently against propor- that they will acquiescein any sort of dictator-
tional representation and clearly explained the ship. . ." (Finer 1935, p. 16). Hermens's Democ-
forces involved in Duverger's law (MacDonald racyor Anarchy:A Studyof ProportionalRepre-
1909, p. 137). As a socialist he thought the plural- sentation(1941)constitutesthe most elaboratein-
ity system was a good discipline for new socialist dictmentof this electoralsystemfor its encourage-
parties like the Labour party, and furthermore, ment of National Socialism, and although not
when his party won, he wanted it to win the whole publisheduntil 1941,its evidencehad beenwidely
thing-His Majesty's Government-not just a circulatedfor severalyearsbefore that. Although
chance at a coalition. On the other hand, most manynow recognizethat Finerand Hermenshad
minority publicists were not so frank; when they made too facile an attributionand inference,still
favored proportional representation, they typi- they werefrequentlyquoted, and the collectionof
cally denied Duverger's hypothesis (on the effect evidenceon this subject by Hermensand others
of proportional representation) and pointed out (e.g., Mellen 1943) had, I believe, a significant
that countries without proportional representa- persuasive effect in support of Duverger's
tion often did not have two-party systems. (For an hypothesis.
example, I quote J. Fischer Williams, "In France, The scholarly study of the two-party system
Italy, and Germany, there are more parties than tended to increasethe evidencefor and scholarly
with us [Great Britain]. . . . But this is not the certainty about Duverger's law. Arthur Hol-
result of proportional representation" (Williams combe, a prominentAmericanpolitical scientist
1918, p. 68). Conversely, those opposed to pro- in the first half of the century, affirmed
portional representation were not quite sure. The Duverger'slaw as early as 1910: "the tendency
authors of the Report of the Royal Commission underthe systemof pluralityelectionstowardthe
on Electoral Systems remarked in puzzlement: "It establishmentof the two-party system is . . .
is asserted by some that small parties would spring almost irresistible"(Holcombe 1910). Although
up like mushrooms when the repressive influence in a populartextbookpublishedas lateas 1919W.
of the majority [Note: they meant plurality] B. Monro attributedthe two-partysystemto the
method was removed; by others that the two- "practical capacity of the Anglo-Saxon race"
party system would survive any change of mecha- (Monro 1919, p. 329), and although authors of
nism whatever" (Royal Commission on Electoral other populartextbooksof the next decade, e.g.,
Systems 1918, p. 31). CharlesMerriam,E. M. Sait, and FredericOgg,
Two strands of intellectual development re- avoided the subject entirely, by 1933 the notion
moved the doubts. One was the spread of dissatis- was well establishedthat pluralityvoting for exec-
faction in the 1930s with proportional representa- utives generatedthe Americantwo-partysystem.
tion; the other was an increased scholarly exam- Arthur MacMahon argued: ". . . centrifugal ten-
ination of the origins of the two-party system that dencies[i.e., for many factions]have been offset
characterized the successful American polity. by the fact that in the face of the necessity of
Since the dissatisfaction with proportional repre- choosinga singlecandidate,the alternativesopen
sentation relates to Duverger's hypothesis (that to electorateshavebeen sharplynarrowed"(Mac-
proportional representation caused multiple par- Mahon 1933). This example of presidentialand
ties, the lesser of Duverger's two propositions), I gubernatorial elections proved extraordinarily
will skip over most of that debate, which was convincing,and withina decadethe moregeneral
especially aimed at identifying the reasons for the form of Duverger'slaw was enshrinedin popular
initial successes of the German National Socialist American textbooks. Thus Carl Friedrich ob-
Party. An excellent example of the effect of that served that the "single member district with
experience is observable in the two editions of a plurality elections . . . forces the electorate to
Fabian Society tract by Herman Finer, a promi- make up its mind betweentwo clear-cutalterna-

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
758 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76

tives" (Friedrich 1937, p. 290), and E. E. Schatt- party systemscaused proportionalrepresentation


schneider wrote that the "single-member-district- (Grumm 1958). His evidence was that five con-
system-plus-plurality-elections . . . discriminates tinental governmentsthat adopted proportional
moderately [emphasis in original] against the representationhad more than two parties when
second party, but against the third, fourth, and they did so. Presumablythey actedto preservethe
fifth parties the force of this tendency is multi- balanceamongexistingparties.But at the time of
plied to the point of extinguishing their chances of adoption,all thosegovernmentshad eithermajor-
winning seats altogether," a force that thereby ity systems (i.e., second ballot) or a history of
guarantees exactly two parties (Schattschneider earlierproportionalrepresentationor no experi-
1942, p. 75). V. 0. Key, Jr. (1949) even applied ence with democracy.Since Duvergercoupledthe
the idea of the law to the superficially one-party majoritysystemwith proportionalrepresentation
system of the states of the old Confederacy, as a cause of multiple parties (as, indeed, had
observing that where primary elections in the one Lowell(1896)and Holcombe(1910)),it is entirely
main party were conducted with the plurality rule, to be expected from the hypothesis that multi-
there was bifactionalism, and where conducted party systems occur in the five countriesat the
with the runoff majority rule, there was multi- time they actually occurred,that is, before pro-
factionalism. However, Key was uncertain about portional representation.So Grumm's evidence
the effect because he thought also that the main supportsratherthan refutesthe hypothesis.
force for bifactionalism probably was the exis- (Incidentally,the few Europeancountriesthat
tence of a serious Republican opposition. changedfrom pluralityto proportionalrepresen-
Scholarly acceptance of both Duverger's law tation also changedfrom a two-partysystemto a
and Duverger's hypothesis was therefore quite multiple-partysystem(Polyzoides 1927).)
general by the time he formulated them. Entirelyapart from Grumm'serror, however,
Duverger's own contribution was twofold: First, there are numerous counterexamplesto Duver-
he distinguished sharply between the law and the ger's hypothesis. For a long time Australia has
hypothesis, which previously had often been mis- had the alternativevote, whichcan be interpreted
takenly interpreted as duals of each other. (Since either as a rudimentaryform of the Hare system
plurality and proportional systems are only two or a version of the majority system. Its parties
out of many, the absence of one does imply the have indeed increased from two to three, and
presence of the other.) Second, he collected and therethe numberhas stabilized.If the hypothesis
systematically arranged a large amount of histori- were true, however,the numbershould continue
cal evidence in support of both sentences so that to increase.It has not, and indeed the thirdparty
their full significance was apparent. is effectivelyan appendageof one of the two main
parties.Austriahas maintainedboth proportional
IV representationand a two-partysystem since the
end of the Second World War. There is no ap-
Of course, acceptance and utterance do not parent feature of the electoral system that ac-
make statements true. The history of these sen- counts for this fact, so it seems a true counter-
tences in the next thirty years consists mainly in example.Despitepartialproportionalrepresenta-
collecting evidence for and against their truth and tion, since 1945Germanyhas developeda system
revising their formulation and adjusting the ra- with two major parties and a third small party
tional choice model within which they fit. Since it alliedcontinuallywith the samemajorparty.This
is just exactly this activity that constitutes the is not a good counterexample,however, because
daily life of science, the fact of a substantial the proportional system also has a plurality
amount of testing out and reformulating of feature intended by its authors to minimize the
Duverger's hypothesis and law is evidence of the number of parties in excess of two. Finally,
accumulation of knowledge I am trying to Ireland provides a devastatingcounterexample.
describe. Despite the use of the Hare system, its parties
I start with Duverger's hypothesis (that propor- have decreasedsharply in number since a high
tional representation and majority systems favor point in 1927, when therewere seven partiesplus
multiparty systems). Clearly Duverger himself was fourteen independents.In 1969 there were three
uneasy about the hypothesis, did not call it a law, parties,one of them very small and one indepen-
and asserted it only as a probabilistic association, dent. This resultwas substantiallyreproducedin
not a deterministic one. 1973and in 1977,whenone partyobtainedan ab-
The earliest attack on the hypothesis was, how- solute majority of the votes. Not unreasonably,
ever, entirely misdirected. Grumm asserted that one studentof Irishelectionswho initiallyseemed
the causal direction in the hypothesis was re- to accept Duverger'shypothesis(O'Leary 1961),
versed, that proportional representation did not has now specificallyrejectedit (O'Leary1979,pp.
cause multiparty systems but rather that multi- 112-13). Katz (1980, p. 40) tried to discount the

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-party System and Duverger's Law 759

force of this counterexample by calling the Hare Furthermore, the percentage of the primary vote
system a modified form of the plurality rule for the top candidate (and for the top two can-
(because voting is for individual candidates, not didates) was much greater in the plurality states
parties), and by predicting then (p. 61), from than in the runoff states, which is exactly what
Duverger's hypothesis, that the number of parties one would expect if the two-ballot system en-
in Ireland should be more than the number in courages multifactionalism. Still, longitudinal
Britain (with the unmodified plurality rule) and averages cover up significant deviations. Canon
fewer than the number in Italy (with the party-list also noted that Alabama, a runoff state, has in the
system of proportional representation). This is, last decade developed something close to bifac-
however, too easy a way out. The Hare system is tionalism, whereas West Virginia, a plurality
indubitably proportional, and it lacks entirely the state, still had fairly evident multifactionalism in
main feature of the plurality rule, namely the the earlier part of this period. Since these two ex-
force encouraging parties to maximize votes. ceptions are not fully explained at present, the
Since there appears to be nothing in common case is strengthened that Duverger's hypothesis is
among these four counterexamples, it seems im- no more than a probabilistic association.
possible to save the hypothesis by modifying it, This is, I believe, what a theoretical interpreta-
and that is the lesson to be learned from Rae's tion, in terms of rational choices by politicians,
more general analysis of the cases (Rae 1971). He would suggest. The rational choice theory, stand-
has shown very neatly that for the development of ing implicitly behind the hypothesis, is that pro-
a successful new party, proportional representa- portional representation and the second ballot
tion is neither a necessary condition (see, for runoff both offer politicians an incentive for the
example, the British Labour party in a plurality formation of new parties and do not give them
system) nor a sufficient condition (see the absence any disincentive. The incentive is that, given par-
of successful third parties in Austria). Instead, ticular configurations of potential coalitions,
Rae offered a list of seven variables, one of which these systems sometimes permit new parties (and
is the presence of proportional representation, heretofore-excluded politicians) to get a bit of
that may be associated with successful new parties political influence with relatively few votes. That
(pp. 151-58). Altogether Rae made an extremely is, in these systems a new party does not have to
strong case that the hypothesis, at least as it get the most votes to win, merely some indefinite
related to proportional representation, cannot be number less than the most. Under proportional
more than a probabilistic association. representation, the candidate or list with the
The empirical evidence is not so conclusive in second most votes can always win seats and some-
the case of the two-ballot majority. No one, aside times so can candidates with the third or fourth
from Duverger, has devoted much attention to most votes. Indeed the purpose of the system is to
party systems associated with this rule. Most con- encourage this result. In the runoff majority
tinental governments used it before they adopted system a candidate who initially has the second
proportional representation, and, as has already most votes can ultimately win, provided the sup-
been remarked, Lowell (1896) and later some ad- porters of eliminated candidates vote for her or
vocates of proportional representation (e.g., Wil- him at the second ballot. Hence, if a group of
liams 1918) believed that the multiparty system politicians can see a chance to come in second or
developed as politicians' rational response to this third, it is often worthwhile to form a new party.
rule. Canon (1978) conducted the most impressive In the plurality system, on the other hand, this
test of the relationship. He was inspired mainly by positive incentive is turned into a disincentive
Key's (1949) uncertainty about the application of because it is rare for the prospective builders of a
the hypothesis to the multifactionalism in new party to see a chance to come in first past the
southern states. Canon used as data the presence post. This system, then, constitutes a real
of bifactionalism from 1932 to 1977 in the Demo- disincentive because the leaders of the new party
cratic gubernatorial primaries in sixteen southern are likely to be regarded as politically irrelevant.
and border states. Ten of these states use the run- This disincentive is absent from proportional
off primary with a majority required for nomina- representation and runoff systems, however,
tion at either the first or second ballot. The other because even leaders of failed parties are welcome
six use the plurality method with just one primary. in expanded coalitions of continuing parties.
Although factionalism is not easy to measure, a Neither feature of this incentive system is strong
reasonable index of it showed in fairly close ap- enough to permit one to say for certain that these
proximation of Duverger's hypothesis that fac- electoral systems favor multiple parties. The in-
tionalism in all but one of the plurality primary centive is weak because it operates only when peo-
states was lower-often much lower-than in all ple want to form new parties for other reasons.
the runoff primary states. For the one anomaly, However, there are surely many configurations of
West Virginia, the index was only slightly higher. potential coalitions, configurations lasting

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
760 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
through many elections, that do not render it like- tion. After noting the Canadian exception, Rae
ly that new parties will come in second (probably said, "insofar as the electoral law exerts a con-
the case in Austria) or even third (probably the trolling pressure, the single-member district is
case in Ireland). Similarly the absence of a dis- likely to press the system toward two-party com-
incentive for new parties within the system of pro- petition" (Rae 1971, p. 143), which is almost
portional representation itself is not very impor- exactly Duverger's sentence, with the verb struc-
tant. Although the existence of proportional ture "likely to press the system toward" rather
representation prohibits the direct use of the dis- than "favors."
incentive inherent in plurality voting, there are The reason Rae fell into this logical trap of both
other kinds of efficacious disincentives that can be denying and then affirming Duverger's law is that
combined with proportional representation, as like Duverger himself, he could not decide
has been done in Germany and perhaps Austria. whether the law was deterministic or probabilistic.
So the incentive is not sufficient and the dis- So Rae's restatement of it is deterministic, but his
incentive is not necessary. Hence the hypothesis actual use of it is probabilistic. I suspect the
cannot be deterministically valid, although doubt- reason for his ambivalence is his belief that the
less there is a fairly strong probabilistic associa- revised deterministic law was less dramatic and
tion between proportional representation or less useful, but attaching conditions to a law is, to
runoff elections on one hand and the multiparty my mind, unexceptionable. The elementary form
system on the other. of the law of demand is "demand curves do not
slope positively," but to state this law accurately,
V one must say: "holding other prices, income, and
tastes constant, demand curves do not slope
We can therefore abandon Duverger's hypothe- positively," perhaps less dramatic-if drama is
sis in its deterministic form (although it is still what one wants from science-but certainly more
useful for practical life) and proceed to the more useful because it is more accurate. Similarly Rae's
interesting question of Duverger's law, relating revision involves greater accuracy and greater
plurality elections and two-party systems. The dif- utility.
ficulties with the law are less formidable. There The Indian counterexample is more difficult to
are indeed counterexamples, but not, I believe, deal with. India began plurality elections about
definitive ones, so that the law may possibly sur- the same time Duverger formulated his law, and
vive with appropriate revisions. If we can also fit only once has something approaching a two-party
it to an adequate theory, it may even be per- election been held. Congress, the party of Nehru
suasive. and his daughter, Indira Gandhi, has been domi-
The two most pressing counterexamples to nant during most of the thirty years since 1951,
Duverger's law are in Canada and India, where even though Congress candidates have never ob-
despite plurality elections there are distinctly more tained as much as 50 percent of the vote. Because
than two parties. In Rae's study of 121 elections in of the large number of candidates in many consti-
20 countries, 30 elections were conducted under tuencies under this genuine multiparty system,
plurality rules and seven of these-all in Canada Congress has usually translated an electoral
-resulted in more than 10 percent of the votes for minority into a majority of legislative seats. It is
a third party. Rae attributed the Canadian devia- an interesting puzzle why the numerous minor
tion to the fact that, geographically, local parties parties do not disappear or consolidate; they have
survive as the main parties in some provinces decreased in number since 1951, but there are still
while they are third parties nationally. Doubtless at least four or five significant parties. One
this situation derives from the extreme decentrali- wonders why it is taking so long for Duverger's
zation of Canadian government, wherein the law to work.
chance of provincial control is of itself enough to Two explanations have been offered for the
motivate political action. delay. Weiner (1957, pp. 223, 262-64) argued that
On the basis of the Canadian exception, Rae the minor parties were social groups providing
reformulated Duverger's law from "the simple- emotional satisfaction to activists, entirely apart
majority, single-ballot system favors the two- from the goal of winning elections. Since activists
party system" to "plurality formulae are always presumably maximize the pleasures of member-
associated with two-party competition except ship rather than the rewards of office, in Weiner's
where strong local minority parties exist" (Rae theory it is not to be expected that they reduce the
1971, p. 95). Rae commented that his revision number of political parties other than acciden-
produced a "much less dramatic proposition" tally. Although I think that Weiner was on the
(Rae 1971, p. 96), although when he came to write right track in looking at the motivation of politi-
about the long-range effects of plurality formulas, cians rather than of voters, it was a serious mis-
he concluded by reaffirming Duverger's proposi- take to lump all politicians together. Certainly the

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-party System and Duverger's Law 761
leaders of the main parties besides Congress one of two parties locally, and (2) one party
behave as if they are intensely motivated by the among several is almost always the Condorcet
chance of office. To attribute to them a group winner in elections.
loyalty that prevents them from doing what is Note that this formulation is deterministic-an at-
necessary to win is to describe them as truly irra- tempt to avoid the ambiguity of Duverger and
tional. I suspect, however, that they are just as ra- Rae. The law asserts that, with the exceptions
tional as western politicians, and so I reject noted, the plurality rule is a sufficient condition
Weiner's explanation, except as it applies to very for a two-party system. It is not, however, an
small and politically irrelevant parties. assertion of a causal relation, inasmuch as the
On another occasion (Riker 1976), I have of- plurality rule clearly is not a necessary condition
fered a different kind of explanation. I believe (vide, Austria).
that because Congress, the largest party in India,
includes the median of the voters arranged on an VI
ideological spectrum, Congress has most of the
time been the second choice of many voters on The revised law is entirely consistent with our
both its right and its left. Hence, the party has knowledge of the empirical world, accounting
probably been a Condorcet winner most of the both for the long history of two-party competi-
time, although it has never obtained an absolute tion in Anglo-American countries with plurality
majority.3 Congress has been clearly defeated only voting and for the apparent exceptions like Social
when the opposition has been so consumed with Credit in Canada, the Irish in Britain in the nine-
intense popular hatred of Mrs. Gandhi or with in- teenth century, the multiparty grouping around
tense elite lust for ministerial office that politi- Congress in India, and the few third parties in the
cians and voters alike could put aside their United States that have survived more than one
ideological tastes and act as if they ordered their election. But the law itself is entirely empirical,
preferences with Congress at the bottom of the the record of observations. It explains nothing
list. When they have done so, they have defeated and tells us nothing about why it works. It is the
Congress in both state and national elections. task of science to explain the law by incorporating
Then, typically, coalitions of each end against the it as a necessary inference inside a theory. Thus it
middle (like Janata in 1977-79) have dissolved and is appropriate to look at the theory that subsumes
Congress has won again, presumably as the Con- the law.
dorcet choice. With these thoughts in mind, I con- Duverger offered two theoretical explanations
structed a model in which, with rational partici- for why the plurality rule destroys third parties:
pants who wished to maximize political satisfac- (1) a "mechanical effect" of underrepresenting
tion, i.e., for office and ideological tastes, a losing parties and (2) a "psychological factor" in
multiparty equilibrium was consistent with plural- that voters do not want to waste their votes on
ity elections. The essence of this model was that losers. Both these reasons derive (implicitly) from
some party in the multiparty system was regularly a view of both politicians and voters as rational
a Condorcet winner. Utilizing this feature, it is actors, i.e., expected utility maximizers. The
possible to revise Duverger's law further, incor- mechanical effect gives politicians an incentive to
porating Rae's revision, to account for both of abandon parties that win even less than they might
the apparent exceptions, Canada and India. be expected to; the psychological factor gives
voters, observing wasted votes and even votes
In my revision the law reads: that, being wasted, indirectly contribute to the
Pluralityelection rulesbringabout and main- victory of least-liked parties, an incentive to vote
tain two-partycompetitionexcept in countries for their second choices. If both these proposi-
where(1) thirdpartiesnationallyare continually tions are correct, they can be combined, as they
were by Duverger, into a theoretical explanation
3ACondorcetwinneris a candidatewho can beat any of the operation of the law.
other in a pairwisecontest. Such a winner, even with The existence of the mechanical effect was dis-
only a plurality,is surelyin a strongerposition than a puted by Grumm on the basis of a modest bit of
pluralitywinnerwho would be beaten in pairwisecon- evidence (Grumm 1958). But Rae showed defini-
tests becausesupportersof second, third, fourth, etc. tively by an empirical comparison that plurality
candidateswouldcombineto defeat him. In the Indian rules gave a greater relative advantage to large
example,Congresshas probablybeena Condorcetwin- parties over small ones than did proportional
ner; that is, it probablywould have been able to defeat
rightistsin a pairwisecontestbecauseleftistswouldvote representation rules (Rae 1971, pp. 88-92).
for Congressratherthanrightists,and similarlyit would Sprague (1980) carried Rae's analysis quite a bit
have been able to defeat leftists in a pairwisecontest further by calculating precisely how much plural-
becauserightistswould vote for Congressratherthan ity systems are biased against third parties. An un-
leftists. biased system is, of course, one in which a party

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
762 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76

gets the same proportion of seats in a legislature supporters of the weakest party (i.e., one of the
as it gets proportion of votes, regardless of the two larger parties nationally) strengthens the third
size of the party's vote. In nearly all systems par- party. This latter effect is probably what has kept
ties with a small proportion of votes get an even alive the Liberal party in Britain and some
smaller proportion of seats (a negative bias), and Canadian third parties. Because third parties re-
parties with a large proportion of votes get an main third parties, however, the main force of
even larger proportion of seats (a positive bias). sophisticated voting must work against third par-
Building on Tufte (1973), Sprague defined an ex- ties.
actly unbiased threshold point, B, of the propor- Given the significance of sophisticated voting in
tion of the vote, through which a party would the explanation of why Duverger's law works, one
pass, as its vote increased, from suffering a nega- very important question is: Does sophisticated
tive bias to enjoying a positive bias. Using Rae's voting occur? That is, are ordinary voters clever
data, Sprague calculated B for plurality systems to and bold enough to vote against their true
be 0.32 and for proportional systems to be 0.12; tastes?
that is, third parties in proportional systems get a Shively (1970) made the first attempt to dis-
fair or positively biased proportion of seats if they cover sophisticated voting. He interpreted Duver-
get one-eighth or more of the vote, whereas in ger's law (rather too broadly, I think) as the
plurality systems they get a fair share only if they sentence: "Where the likelihood that a party can
get one-third or more of the vote. This compari- win . . . is low, voters are less likely to continue
son demonstrates quite vividly how severely voting for it, or . .. to begin voting for it." For a
Duverger's mechanical effect discourages the for- test, he created an index of the likelihood of win-
mation of third parties in plurality systems. ning and regressed the change of a party's propor-
The main dispute is about the validity of the tion of the vote in two consecutive elections on
psychological factor, which Downs bluntly de- this index. He expected a positive association, i.e.,
scribed thus: low likelihood linked with decline in share of
votes, but he got a negative one. This result led
A rational voter first decides what party he
believes will benefit him most; then he tries to him to further statistical manipulation and a re-
estimate whether this party has any chance of interpretation which he believed supported the
winning.He does this becausehis vote shouldbe law, though only weakly. Hence he concluded
expendedas partof a selectionprocess,not as an that the psychological factor had "a trivial impact
expression of preference. Hence even if he on election outcomes."
preferspartyA, he is "wasting"his vote on A if Given the empirical strength of Duverger's law
it has no chance of winning, becausevery few at the institutional level, these results from elec-
other voters prefer it to B or C. The relevant toral data were, to say the least, perplexing. Since
choice in this case is betweenB and C. Since a Shively's form of the hypothesis and his method
vote for A is not useful in the actual processof
selection,castingit is irrational(Downs 1957, p. were far too gross to study the truly relevant
48). behavior, however, other scientists have looked
more precisely at voters' desertion from third par-
What Downs describes has come to be called ties. These investigators have found a relatively
"sophisticated" voting, by which is meant that large amount of sophisticated voting in Britain,
the voter takes account of anticipated votes by Canada, Germany, and the United States, as de-
others and then votes so as to bring about the best scribed below.
realizable outcome for himself, regardless of Britain. Spafford (1972) observed that Shively's
whether or not his vote is sincere, i.e., for his pre- hypothesis involved no discrimination between
ferred alternative. situations in which sophisticated voting would or
In the election of single executives, if sophisti- would not be efficient, but in fact one would ex-
cated voting occurs, it always works against third pect more sophisticated voting as the chance in-
parties. (Indeed, early statements of Duverger's creases to affect the outcome between one's sec-
law in the United States, e.g., by MacMahon ond and third preferences. That is, if the race is
(1933), emphasized the special importance of the close between the major parties, then third-party
elected executive in bringing the psychological supporters are more likely to desert their party at
factor into play.) In the election of members of a the polls. Spafford tested this for 104 constituen-
legislature, however, which of the several parties cies with Liberal candidates in both the 1964 and
is weakened by sophisticated voting depends on 1966 elections and found a highly significant,
conditions in the constituency. If the third party positive association between the Liberal share of
nationally is the weakest locally, then sophisti- the vote in 1966 and the share of the vote of the
cated voting by its supporters weakens it. How- winning party in 1964. For example, lower Liberal
ever, if the third party nationally is one of the two shares went with lower shares for the winning par-
larger parties locally, then sophisticated voting by ty in the previous election, which means that, with

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-party System and Duverger's Law 763
a greater chance to influence the outcome, more sophisticated (second choice) vote on expected
Liberals deserted. Clearly sophisticated voting oc- utility, degree of political participation, and inten-
curred in this instance. sity of first preference. He found that the coeffi-
Lemieux (1977) elaborated on this analysis by cient for expected utility was in the right direction
comparing the effect of the Liberal vote in all con- for both categories of voters and statistically
stituencies with its effect in marginal constituen- significant for sophisticated voters, that is, sincere
cies (i.e., those in which the margin between Con- voters had PI U1 > P2 U2, whereas sophisticated
servative and Labour was less than 15 percent) for voters had the reverse. Furthermore, the closer
all seats that Liberals contested and for each pair that sophisticated voters judged their first and sec-
of elections from 1959 to 1970. Categorizing con- ond choices to be, the more likely they were to
stituencies according to the Liberal strategy (to vote sophisticatedly, which supports the inference
contest in both elections, or the second only, or that the voters were in fact consciously sophisti-
the first only), Lemieux found that the Liberals cated (Cain 1978, pp. 650-51).
had a significant effect on the Conservative share Germany. In elections for the Bundestag,
of the vote in five of the nine possible cases when voters cast two ballots simultaneously, one for a
considering all the constituencies in the category. candidate to be chosen by the plurality rule in
Considering just the marginal constituencies for single-member districts (Erststimme), and the
these five cases, the Liberals' effect was also other for a party list to be awarded seats by pro-
significant but of the opposite sign and just about portional representation in a statewide multi-
the same absolute size, which means that, for the member district (Zweitstimme). Each party then
marginal seats, the incentive for the Liberals to gets its plurality-won seats plus the number of
desert their party is extremely great. Lemieux seats won by the proportional rule less the number
remarked, and I agree, that these results indicate a of plurality-won seats. If sophisticated voting oc-
large amount of sophisticated voting (Lemieux curs, one would expect that the two major parties
1977, p. 177). would get more Erststimmen (votes in plurality
In a study of third-party voters in Britain, Cain elections where voting for small parties is "waste-
(1978) examined the matter with the use of elec- ful") than Zweitstimmen (votes in proportional
tion results and then survey responses, both from elections, where every vote for a small party can
1970. Since the results from the latter confirm count) and vice versa for small parties. Fisher
results from the former, we have yet another con- (1974) found this to be exactly and universally the
firmation of the existence and significance of case: In every state in every election from 1961
sophisticated voting. First, Cain regressed third- through 1972, Christian Democrats and Social
party vote shares in constituencies on Closeness Democrats had fewer Zweitstimmen than Erst-
(i.e., the difference between major-party shares) stimmen, whereas every minor party had more.
and on Abstention, a new variable in these discus- The typical shift was 1 to 2 percent for the large
sions. His hypotheses were: (1) a positive associa- parties and in 1972 up to 5 percent for the Free
tion between Closeness and third-party share, i.e., Democrats, then the only surviving minor party.
as the race between the major parties becomes in- More to the point, one would expect the shift to
determinate-that is, as the difference between be especially large for minor parties, and this was
the major parties decreases-the third-party vote exactly what Fisher found. In 1961, 1965, and
would also decrease, and (2) a negative associa- 1969, the Free Democrats lost between 13 and 38
tion between Abstention and third-party share, percent of its Zweitstimmen when their voters cast
i.e., as the proportion of nonvoters increases, the the Erststimmen, whereas the major parties never
proportion of third-party votes decreases. The lost as much as 7 percent (Fisher 1974). This infor-
theory was strongly confirmed: both coefficients mation enables us to estimate the sophisticated
were the right sign and highly significant (Cain voting for supporters of Free Democrats at be-
1978, p. 645). tween one-tenth and two-fifths.
Given this promising discovery in macro- Canada. Black (1978, 1980) also used survey
analysis, Cain then turned to survey responses for data to study individual decisions. Using prefer-
microanalysis. Relative to individual decisions, ence orders from survey data and probabilities of
expected utility theory holds that the choice of the affecting outcomes from actual outcomes in con-
individual is a function of the utility, U, of the stituencies, for one test he categorized voters into
several outcomes, i, where outcome i is a victory (1) those for whom it would be advantageous to
for party i, i = 1,2,3, times the probability, Pi, vote sophisticatedly, and (2) those for whom it
that the voter can bring about these outcomes. would not be. For data from elections in 1968 and
Cain estimated the probabilities from data about 1972, approximately 37 and 62 percent of the
actual outcomes in respondents' constituencies former (advantaged) and only 10 percent of the
and the utilities from survey responses. Then he latter (not advantaged) actually did so. For
regressed the sincere (first choice) votes and the another test, he categorized voters into marginal

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
764 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76

(i.e., small preference for first over second choice) Ordeshook and I have elaborated (Riker and
and nonmarginal (large preference). The marginal Ordeshook 1968), it may be impossible for an in-
voters were found to be much more likely to vote dividual to influence the selection process. One in-
sophisticatedly than the nonmarginal, and for terpretation of influence is the chance to make a
those marginals for whom sophisticated voting tie or to break a tie that occurs in the absence of
was advantageous, actual voting for the second the individual's vote. This chance is, of course,
choice ranged between 50 and 100 percent. These extremely tiny in most elections in the modern
two tests were repeated and confirmed in elab- state. Under this definition, it is objectively the
orate regression equations. Altogether they in- case that one cannot expect to contribute much to
dicate a remarkable amount of sophisticated the decision process. If so, the rational action may
voting. be simply to express a preference.
United States. The 1968 presidential election Ferejohn and Fiorina (1974, 1975) have sug-
with a third-party candidate and national survey gested that individuals do not calculate their
data about preference orders allowed Bensel and chance of influence but merely their satisfaction,
Sanders (1979) to estimate the proportion of minimizing thereby the maximum regret they
sophisticated voting in that election. Comparing would feel if an undesired candidate won. The
those for whom sophisticated voting was advan- debate over the relative merits of minimax regret
tageous (mostly Wallace supporters) with those and expected utility is extensive (Beck 1975;
for whom it was not, they found that the 12 per- Mayer and Good 1975). Although the bulk of the
cent of the advantaged voted sophisticatedly, evidence about the way people behave now seems
whereas only 4 percent of the not advantaged did. to favor expected utility (Black 1978; Cain 1978;
Since the electoral college breaks up the national Aldrich 1976), still the fact that the minimax
electorate into fifty parts with different informa- regret interpretation can be put forward plausibly
tion about probable outcomes in each one, this suggests that some people may be interested mere-
allowed them to compare voters' calculations. If ly in utility, not expected utility.
voting is sophisticated, it should be the case that If the chance to influence is negligible, then
where Wallace was strong (i.e., had more chance energy spent on a calculus and sophisticated
to carry the state), his supporters would be more voting is wasted and irrational, whereas voting
likely to vote sincerely than where he was weak. merely to express a preference may be entirely
The effect was striking: in strong Wallace states rational. Meehl (1977) has faced this problem
only 4 percent voted sophisticatedly as opposed to squarely and has insisted that the "wasted vote"
17 percent in states where Wallace was weak. argument is at best meaningless and at worst a
fraud. Voters' motivation is rational, he argued,
VII only in terms of their sense of moral obligation.
This obligation cannot involve a means-end calcu-
The evidence renders it undeniable that a large lation-for that is meaningless when votes are not
amount of sophisticated voting occurs-mostly to influential-but must instead respond to a moral
the disadvantage of the third parties nation- imperative. He acknowledged that moral impera-
ally-so that the force of Duverger's psycho- tives might also lack meaning, in which case all
logical factor must be considerable. It seems in- justifications of voting are irrational. But if only
itially appropriate and attractive, therefore, to the morally motivated vote is rational, then it is
construct a theory to explain Duverger's law out impossible to waste a vote (or to behave
of the theory of rational choice. Nevertheless, we irrationally) by voting simply for one's first
cannot do so blithely. In the first place, not every- preference.
one votes sophisticatedly, although the evidence Granting some persuasiveness to Meehl's argu-
collected here suggests that most people who ment, the theoretical underpinning of Duverger's
"should" do so by reason of the expected utility law is surely weak if behavior in accord with the
calculus probably do so in fact. It is difficult, psychological factor of individual voters' calcula-
however, to build a theory on behavior that is not tion of expected utility is itself irrational. It seems
certainly universal, and even if it is universal, necessary, therefore, to find some new, or at least
there remains a serious and unresolved paradox in additional, theoretical explanation of why
the argument, which is that the expected utility Duverger's law works.
calculus of voting may itself be irrational. The direction one must go, I believe, is to turn
In Downs's statement of the theory, which I attention away from the expected utility calculus
cited previously, the rational voter should expend of the individual voter and to the expected utility
his vote "as part of the selection process," not as calculus of the politician and other more substan-
"an expression of preference." Yet this statement tial participants in the system. The groups and in-
may be indefensible because, as Downs himself dividuals who buy access and the politicians who
pointed out (1957, pp. 36-50, 260-76) and as buy a future have substantial interests, and it is

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1982 The Two-partySystem and Duverger'sLaw 765
their actions to maximize expected utility that * empirically: Counterexamples have been ana-
have the effect of maintaining the two-party sys- lyzed and the law revised to subsume them.
tem under plurality voting. * theoretically: A theory of the behavioral forces
One especially interesting feature of politics involved has been enunciated and revised.
under plurality rules is that minor parties regularly From the first enunciation by Droop, the law
appear. The reason, I believe, is that quite rea- has been implicitly embedded in a rational
sonably not all voters vote sophisticatedly. In- choice theory about the behavior of politicians
stead they are willing, like Meehl himself, to sup- and voters. This theory has been rendered
port a program that appeals to their ideological more and more explicit, especially in the last
taste. Potential politicians are in turn often willing two decades, so that recent empirical work
to experiment with and invest in new programs consciously invokes the rational choice model.
and platforms to form a possible winning venture.
Since some of these win locally, they can remain * and as a source of hypotheses: Propositions in-
in the system for a long time. In the United States ferred from it have been tested as, for example,
there is the additional attraction to politicians in the inquiry about sophisticated voting was
that we have a two-ballot majority system (rather undertaken because, if the law is valid and if
than a plurality system) at the electoral college the theory is appropriate, something like
level, which encourages third parties because their sophisticated voting must occur.
leaders may convince themselves that they have a Of course, there is much yet to be done. If the
chance to throw the election into the House of theory is revised along the lines I have suggested,
Representatives (Bensel and Sanders 1979). conditions to cover the counterexamples will
Coupling the interest of potential leaders with the doubtless be clarified and simplified. And there
sincere behavior of many voters, one understands are more polities to examine. Recently Nigeria has
why there is an almost constant supply of third adopted plurality voting, and its future experience
parties. with or without a two-party system will be another
The interesting question about such parties is test of the law.
not why they begin, but why they fail. I believe Although we are only part way along in this his-
the answer is that donors and leaders disappear. A tory, it still seems to me that the law is much more
donor buys future influence and access, and many defensible than when Droop uttered it a century
donors are willing to buy from any party that has ago. Many-perhaps most-political scientists
a chance to win. (In the United States, at least, who specialize in the study of political parties now
many donors give to both parties.) But as rational accept the law (e.g., Katz 1980, who, however,
purchasers they are not likely to donate to a party thought it applied particularly at the local level).
with a tiny chance of winning, and in a plurality Still, not all political scientists are convinced it is
system, most third parties have only that chance, valid, and that is exactly as it should be, for skep-
because plurality rules give large parties a large ticism about supposed truths is the heart of sci-
relative advantage over small parties (Rae 1971, ence. Still nearly everyone would agree, I believe,
pp. 88-92, and Sprague 1980). Similarly a poten- that there has been some accumulation of knowl-
tial leader buys a career, and as a rational pur- edge, and that is what I set out to demonstrate.
chaser he has no interest in a party that may lose
throughout his lifetime. So the answer to the
question of failure is that third parties are rejected References
in the rational calculus of expected utility especial-
ly by leaders, though also in the calculus by many Aldrich, J. H. 1976. Some problems in testing two
simple voters. Any adequate theory to subsume rational models of participation. American Journal
Duverger's law must, I believe, begin there, which of Political Science 20:713-33.
Ashworth, T. R., and Ashworth, H. P. C. 1901. Pro-
is a task for scholars in the next decade. portional representation applied to party govern-
ment: a new electoral system. London: Swan Son-
nenschein.
VIII Beck, N. 1975. The paradox of minimax regret. Ameri-
can Political Science Review 69:918.
I began this survey of the history of Duverger's Bensel, R. F., and Sanders, E. 1979. The effect of
law to demonstrate that a history existed. I think electoral rules on voting behavior: the electoral col-
it is clear that in a forty-year period in which lege and shift voting. Public Choice 34:69-85.
Black, J. H. 1978. The multicandidate calculus of
writers struggled to enunciate it, through another
voting: application to Canadian federal elections.
half century, when it was clarified until Duverger American Journal of Political Science 22:609-38.
asserted it as a law, and in the succeeding thirty Black, J. H. 1980. The probability-choice perspective
years, it has been examined with increasing scien- in voter decision making models. Public Choice 35:
tific sophistication 565-74.

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
766 The AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol. 76
Cain, B. E. 1978. Strategic voting in Britain. American Mayer, L. and Good, I. J. 1975. Is minimax regret
Journal of Political Science 22:639-55. applicable to voting decision? American Political
Canon, B. C. 1978. Factionalism in the South: a test of Science Review 69:916-17.
theory and a revisitation of V. 0. Key. American Meehl, P. E. 1977. The selfish voter paradox and the
Journal of Political Science 22:833-48. thrown-away vote argument. American Political
Carstairs, A. M. 1980. A short history of electoral sys- Science Review 61:11-30.
tems in WesternEurope. London: George Allen and Mellen, S. L. W. 1943. The German people and the
Unwin. post-war world. American Political Science Review
Downs, A. 1957. An economic theory of democracy. 37:607-25.
New York: Harper & Bros. Mill, J. S. 1861. Considerations on representative gov-
Droop, H. R. 1871. On the political and social effects of ernment. In Utilitarianism, liberty, and representa-
different methods of electing representatives. tive government, ed. A. D. Lindsay. London: J. M.
Papers, 1863-70. London: Juridical Society, 3: Dent (Everyman Ed. 1910).
469-507. Munro, W. B. 1919. The government of the United
Droop, H. R. 1881. On methods of electing representa- States. New York: Macmillan.
tives. Journal of the Statistical Society 44:2. Nanson, E. J. 1882. Transactions, Melbourne: Pro-
Duverger, M. 1963. Political parties: their organization ceedings of Royal Society of Victoria. 19:197-240.
and activity in the modern state, North, B. and O'Leary, C. 1961. The Irish Republic and its experi-
North R., tr. New York: Wiley, Science Ed. ment with proportional representation. Notre
Ferejohn, J. A., and Fiorina, M. P. 1974. The paradox Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
of not voting: a decision theoretic analysis. Ameri- 1979. Irish elections 1918-77: parties, voters
can Political Science Review 68:525-36. and proportional representation. New York: St.
1975. Closeness counts only in horseshoes and Martin's Press.
dancing. American Political Science Review 69: Ostrogorski, M. 1908. Democracy and the organization
920-25. of political parties, 2 vols. New York: Macmillan.
Finer, H. 1924, Rev. 1935. The case against propor- Polyzoides, A. 1927. Greece's experiment with propor-
tional representation, Fabian Tract No. 211. Lon- tional representation. American Political Science
don: Fabian Society. Review 21:123-28.
Fisher, S. L. 1974. A test of Anthony Downs' wasted Popper, K. 1963. Conjectures and refutations: the
vote thesis: West German evidence. Unpublished growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge
paper prepared for the Public Choice Society, New and Paul.
Haven, Conn. Rae, D. W. 1971. The political consequences of elec-
Friedrich, C. J. 1937. Constitutional government and toral laws, rev. ed. New Haven, Conn.: Yale Univer-
politics: nature and development. New York: sity Press.
Harper & Bros. Riker, W. H. 1976. The number of political parties: a
Grumm, J. 1958. Theories of electoral systems. Mid- reexamination of Duverger's law. Comparative Poli-
west Journal of Political Science 2:357-76. tics 9:93-106.
Hansard's Parliamentary Debates, Third Series 1867, 1977. The future of a science of politics. Ameri-
1885. vol. 188, 294. can Behavioral Scientist 21:11-38.
Hare, T. 1859. The election of representatives, parlia- Riker, W. H. and Ordeshook, P. C. 1968. A theory of
mentary and municipal. London: Longmans Green. the calculus of voting. American Political Science
Hermens, F. 1941. Democracy or anarchy: a study of Review 62:25-42.
proportional representation. Notre Dame, Indiana: Royal Commission Appointed to Enquire into Elec-
Review of Politics. toral Systems. 1910. Report. London.
Holcombe, A. 1911. Direct primaries and the second Schattschneider, E. E. 1942. Party government. New
ballot. American Political Science Review 5:535-52. York: Farrar and Rinehart.
Katz, R. S. 1980. A theory of parties and electoral sys- Shively, W. P. 1970. The elusive psychological factor: a
tems. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. test for the impact of electoral systems on voters'
Key, V. O., Jr. 1949. Southern politics. New York: behavior. Comparative Politics 3:115-25.
Alfred A. Knopf. Spafford, D. 1972. Electoral systems and voters'
Kuhn, T. S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolu- behavior: comment and a further test. Comparative
tions; 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Politics 5:129-34.
Lemieux, P. 1977. The liberalparty and British political Sprague, J. 1980. On Duverger's sociological law: the
change: 1955-1974. Ph.D. dissertation. Massachu- connection between electoral laws and party sys-
setts Institute of Technology. tems. Political Science Paper No. 48. Xeroxed. St.
Leys, C. 1959. Models, theories, and the theory of Louis: Washington University.
political parties. Political Studies 8:127-46. Tufte, E. R. 1973. The relation between seats and votes
Lowell, A. L. 1896. Government and politics of conti- in two-party systems. American Political Science
nental Europe, 2 vols. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Review 67:540-54.
MacDonald, J. R. 1909. Socialism and government. Weiner, M. 1957. Party politics in India: the develop-
London: Independent Labour Party. ment of a multiparty system. Princeton: Princeton
MacMahon, A. W. 1933. Political parties, United University Press.
States. Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, ed. A. Williams, J. F. 1918. The reform of representation.
Johnson, 6:596-601. New York: Macmillan. London: John Murray.

This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Thu, 5 Sep 2013 04:36:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like