You are on page 1of 17

Angelaki

Journal of the Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

“MAKING REASON THINK MORE”

Patrick T. Giamario

To cite this article: Patrick T. Giamario (2017) “MAKING REASON THINK MORE”, Angelaki, 22:4,
161-176, DOI: 10.1080/0969725X.2017.1406055

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2017.1406055

Published online: 05 Dec 2017.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 47

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 22 number 4 december 2017

ant’s Analytic of the Aesthetic Power of


K Judgment – the opening section of the Cri-
tique of the Power of Judgment – is famous for
its claims about beauty, sublimity, and artistic
genius. While these arguments have come to
form a touchstone for modern philosophical aes-
thetics, scant attention has been paid to how
Kant concludes this Analytic. In particular,
section 54 (the Analytic’s final section) provides
an extended “Remark” on laughter.1 Here Kant
contends that “laughter is an affect resulting
from the sudden transformation of a heigh- patrick t. giamario
tened expectation into nothing” (332, §54).2
How and to what extent is laughter philosophi-
cally important in Kant? Does laughter contrib- “MAKING REASON
ute to his aesthetic project and broader
philosophical system in ways that he and his THINK MORE”
readers have failed to acknowledge? The few
scholars who have studied section 54 hesitate
laughter in kant’s aesthetic
to characterize laughter as anything more than philosophy
a supporting player in Kant’s aesthetic philos-
ophy.3 This article offers a new reading of
Kant’s account of laughter that takes issue fact, Kant describes laughter as a merely sensu-
with these assessments and demonstrates how ous pleasure that does not concern the power of
laughter plays a crucial, even decisive role in reflective judgment in its freedom. However, a
the third Critique. closer reading of section 54 reveals that Kant’s
Most interpretations of the Critique of the discussion of laughter is deeply imbricated in
Power of Judgment focus on how two types of his analyses of the beautiful and the sublime
aesthetic judgment reveal the possibility of and that he provides many reasons and
human freedom in the determinist natural resources for interpreting laughter as a conse-
world.4 Judgments of taste (or judgments on quential piece of his critical aesthetic philos-
the beautiful) assure the subject that nature ophy. In what follows I read Kant’s account of
can harmonize with the duty to act freely, laughter in a way that remains faithful to the
while judgments of the sublime inspire the concepts and principles governing his philoso-
subject to act freely even if the natural world phical system even as I depart from his con-
is not amenable to such action. At first, laughter clusions about laughter’s significance in that
does not appear to contribute to Kant’s account system. I contend that interpreting section 54
of aesthetic judgment in any significant way. In with and against Kant in this manner can

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/17/040161-16 © 2017 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2017.1406055

161
“making reason think more”

productively challenge and transform how we what the parallels between laughter and the
understand the Kantian critical project. practice of reflective judgment at the heart of
I advance three arguments along these lines. Kant’s critical philosophy reveal about a specifi-
First, although Kant describes joking as an cally “Kantian” practice of critique.
“agreeable art” carrying only empirical signifi-
cance (330–34, §54), I argue that section 54
demonstrates that laughter constitutes a highly
I the beautiful and the sublime
specific form of aesthetic judgment within his Kant’s first two Critiques carefully differentiate
critical philosophy. Laughter involves a discor- nature (the empirical domain of appearances)
dant relation between the cognitive faculties from freedom (the transcendental domain of
that is characteristic of the sublime, but this things-in-themselves). The Critique of the
relation obtains between the understanding Power of Judgment – especially the first half
and the imagination, the two faculties at play on aesthetics – aims to bridge the “incalculable
in judgments of taste on the beautiful. Laughter gulf” dividing these two domains (175). To that
in Kant is the analog of the sublime in the end, the Analytic of the Aesthetic Power of
realm of taste. Second, I argue that instead of Judgment focuses on two types of judgments:
reflecting an afterthought of Kant’s aesthetic judgments of taste (i.e., judgments about
philosophy, laughter constitutes the most whether an object is beautiful) and judgments
basic aesthetic judgment in Kant. The beauti- of the sublime. The beautiful and the sublime
ful and the sublime, while consequential com- are aesthetic judgments because they concern
ponents of Kantian aesthetics, both how the representation of an object pleases or
presuppose laughter as their transcendental con- displeases the subject (203, §1). No objective
dition of possibility. Third and finally, an logical, empirical, or moral criteria are involved
account of aesthetic judgment that begins with in the beautiful and the sublime; all that matters
laughter transforms how we understand the is the subject’s feeling of pleasure or displea-
role of aesthetic judgment in Kant. Rather sure. Understanding laughter’s role in Kant’s
than simply assuring the subject that nature aesthetic philosophy requires a familiarity with
can harmonize with the ends of freedom (as in these two judgments. In this section I introduce
the beautiful) or inspiring the subject to act the beautiful and the sublime, focusing on five
freely in an inhospitable natural world (as in items in particular: (1) the conditions under
the sublime), laughter constitutes an aesthetic which the subject feels the beautiful and the
judgment that immediately enacts reason’s sublime; (2) the specific cognitive faculties at
power of free self-transformation in a sensible play in these judgments; (3) the form of the
world not predisposed to the subject. The aes- relation between the cognitive faculties; (4) the
thetic judgment of laughter reveals how a sensi- types of pleasure felt by the subject; and (5)
ble world at odds with the subject’s purposes the role that the beautiful and the sublime
can nevertheless advance the subject’s rational play in uniting the domains of nature and
vocation to think and act freely. freedom.
The article proceeds in five sections. Section I
introduces the beautiful and the sublime and
explains how these judgments contribute to
I.i the beautiful
the third Critique’s goal of unifying the con- The third Critique opens with an analysis of
cepts of nature and freedom. This section lays judgments of taste, or judgments about
the groundwork for the reading of Kant’s whether an object is beautiful. A beautiful
account of laughter that follows in Sections II object, such as a flower, is one whose formal fea-
and III. Section IV specifies the role that an tures arouse a completely disinterested feeling
account of aesthetic judgment oriented around of pleasure in the subject (211, §5; 229, §16).
laughter plays in the broader Kantian philoso- The pleasure that a subject takes in a beautiful
phical system. Section V concludes by exploring object consists in its “mere form of

162
giamario

purposiveness” with respect to the reflective with the former to the final end in accordance
power of judgment (221, §11). The form of an with the latter. (196)
object is “purposive” when it launches the sub-
Judgments of taste help unify the Kantian
ject’s faculties of the understanding and the
system by assuring the subject of the possibility
imagination into a harmonious relation with
of freedom in nature.
one another (189–90; 217, §9; 222, §12).
Whereas in an ordinary determinative judgment
the understanding provides a concept or rule for I.ii the sublime
the imagination to obey, in a reflective judgment The sublime is the second aesthetic judgment
of taste an object’s form sends the imagination Kant analyzes. Whereas in the beautiful a
into a “free play” with the understanding feeling of pleasure results from nature’s purpo-
(179–80; 217, §9). Here the representation of siveness with respect to the subject’s cognitive
the imagination harmonizes only with the faculties, in the sublime a highly paradoxical
understanding’s lawfulness in general (217–19, feeling of pleasure results from nature’s contra-
§9; 241). The stimulation of the two faculties purposiveness with respect to these faculties.
by one another yields a feeling of pleasure Nature is “contrapurposive” when its represen-
(217, §9). Because the pleasure produced in a tation clashes with the subject’s ability to judge
judgment of taste is grounded in nothing other it. Rather than feeling as if nature is “predeter-
than the free and harmonious relation between mined” (245, §23) or “suitable” (189) for the
the faculties of the understanding and the subject, the sublime leaves the subject feeling
imagination that are common to all subjects, as if nature is at odds with her power of judg-
the subject can demand that all others agree ment. As Kant writes,
with her judgment (211–19, §§6–9).
Judgments of taste play a crucial role in that which […] excites in us the feeling of the
Kant’s philosophical system. Although the sublime, may to be sure appear in its form to
moral law commands the subject to act freely be contrapurposive for our power of judg-
without regard to sensible interests (Critique ment, unsuitable for our faculty of presen-
of Practical Reason 29–30), Kant worries tation, and as it were doing violence to our
whether the subject has grounds for believing imagination. (245, §23)
in the possibility of achieving the ends of
freedom in nature. To what extent is the sensi- The sublime appears to widen rather than
ble world disposed toward a will determined bridge the gulf between nature and freedom.
morally (Critique of the Power of Judgment To explain how the sublime contributes to
176)? The feeling of the beautiful encourages the third Critique’s goal of unifying nature
the subject to believe in the possibility of brid- and freedom, Kant differentiates two ways of
ging the gulf between freedom and nature presenting the sublime. The mathematical
because the beautiful constitutes a subjective sublime arises when the subject attempts to
experience of freedom within the natural aesthetically “comprehend” an empirical
world. The beautiful object’s formal purposive- object like the Egyptian pyramids or
ness with respect to the subject’s cognitive fac- St. Peter’s Basilica that appears “absolutely
ulties suggests that the purposes of nature can great” or “great beyond all comparison” (248,
readily harmonize with those of the subject. §25; 252, §26). Here reason, “which requires
Kant explains that aesthetic judgment totality for all given magnitudes” (254, §26),
asks the imagination to do something of which
provides the mediating concept between the it is not capable: represent the “un-represent-
concepts of nature and the concept of able” (i.e., something large beyond all compari-
freedom, which makes possible the transition son) (251–52, §26). Reason and the imagination
from the purely theoretical to the purely arrive at a violent impasse that agitates the mind
practical, from lawfulness in accordance (258, §27). Kant explains that a pleasure

163
“making reason think more”

unexpectedly issues from this displeasurable faculties, whereas the sublime arises when a
discordance as the imagination’s failure to rep- natural form is contrapurposive with respect
resent the object reveals the strength of the sub- to these faculties. Second, the beautiful involves
ject’s power of reason (257–58, §27). Only a a relation between the faculties of the under-
being endowed with reason would ever standing and the imagination, whereas the
demand the representation of the un-represent- sublime involves a relation between the imagin-
able in cognition. Kant writes: “the subject’s ation and reason. Third, the understanding and
own incapacity reveals the consciousness of an the imagination enter into a simple, harmonious
unlimited capacity of the very same subject, play in the beautiful, whereas in the sublime the
and the mind can aesthetically judge the latter imagination and reason enter into a complex,
only through the former” (259, §27). The para- violent discordance. Fourth, the beautiful
doxical pleasure of the mathematical sublime pleases the subject immediately, while the
inspires reason in its theoretical vocation. sublime pleases the subject only by means of a
Meanwhile, the dynamical sublime is a para- corresponding displeasure. Fifth and finally,
doxical pleasure that inspires reason in its prac- the beautiful assures the subject that nature
tical vocation. The dynamical sublime arises can harmonize with the duty to act freely,
when the imagination represents a natural whereas the sublime inspires the subject to
object, such as a threatening rock formation or think and act freely even when nature is not pre-
large thundercloud, as arousing great fear disposed to these purposes (267). By bridging
(260–61, §28). Provided that the subject is at a the gulf between nature and freedom in differ-
safe distance (such that she can judge the ent ways, the beautiful and the sublime work
object without interest), this representation together to secure the unity of the Kantian phi-
unexpectedly yields a feeling of pleasure (262, losophical system.
§28). The subject takes pleasure in how the rep-
resentation of a fearsome natural object reminds
her that she possesses the even more powerful
II kant’s account of laughter
capacity to determine her will freely in accord- Kant’s discussion of laughter in section 54 com-
ance with the moral law. Sublime objects pletes a lengthy examination of the relationship
between art, taste, and genius (§§43–54). In
elevate the strength of our soul above its these sections Kant identifies a type of art that
usual level, and allow us to discover within pleases the subject by stimulating his cognitive
ourselves a capacity for resistance of quite
faculties (“beautiful art”) rather than by provid-
another kind, which gives us the courage to
ing sensuous gratification (“agreeable art”) (305,
measure ourselves against the apparent all-
powerfulness of nature. (261, §28) §44). Beautiful art launches the understanding
and the imagination into the harmonious, disin-
The subject feels the paradoxical pleasure of the terested, pleasurable play described above (306,
dynamical sublime when the imagination’s rep- §45). After assessing the value of various artistic
resentation of a fearsome natural object reveals practices as beautiful art, Kant concludes in
her even greater power of practical reason. In section 54 with an extended, yet rather unex-
both its mathematical and dynamical forms, pected analysis of the “play of thoughts,” or
the sublime bridges the gulf between nature joking, that subjects engage in at dinner
and freedom by inspiring the subject to think parties (331–32, §54). He describes how clever
and act freely in the sensible world. witticisms generate laughter among guests by
Before moving on to Kant’s account of laugh- playfully reversing their expectations. Kant
ter, allow me to briefly review the beautiful and offers an example:
the sublime along the lines proposed at the
beginning of this section. First, the beautiful If someone tells this story: An Indian, at the
arises when the form of a natural object is pur- table of an Englishman in Surat, seeing a
posive with respect to the subject’s cognitive bottle of ale being opened and all the beer,

164
giamario

transformed into foam, spill out, displayed judgment, he concludes that because the gratifi-
his great amazement with many exclama- cation it provides is ultimately bodily, “the joke
tions, and in reply to the Englishman’s ques- […] deserves to be counted as agreeable rather
tion “What is so amazing here?” answered, than as beautiful art” (ibid.; see also 305, §44).
“I’m not amazed that it’s coming out, but Kant’s disqualification of joking as a beauti-
by how you got it all in,” we laugh, and it
ful art is clear and unambiguous. As a bodily
gives us a hearty pleasure. (333, §54)
sensation, laughter cannot claim the a priori val-
According to Kant, a quick reversal in the sub- idity that belongs to the pleasure taken in beau-
ject’s expectations (here, in the response the tiful art and which critical aesthetic philosophy
guests expect from the Indian) provokes laugh- in general aims to ground and legitimate (168).
ter. Kant provides several additional examples However, a closer examination of the moments
of this kind of joking and the laughter it produces in section 54 where joking resembles a beautiful
(333–34, §54).5 Laughter for Kant constitutes the art reveals that laughter is deeply entangled in
final stage of a dinner party where “men of taste and bears the traces of the conceptual apparatus
(aesthetically united)” allow themselves a degree that Kant develops around the judgments of the
of sensuous pleasure after recounting the news of beautiful and the sublime. In what follows, I
the day and engaging in a robust philosophical trace these connections between laughter, the
discussion (Anthropology 278–81).6 beautiful, and the sublime and argue that
Joking poses a problem for Kant’s distinction rather than reflecting an inconsequential
between beautiful and agreeable art. On the one endnote to Kant’s analysis of aesthetic judg-
hand, the dinnertime exchange of witticisms is a ment, laughter constitutes an aesthetic judg-
“play of thoughts” or “play of the power of ment that brings the logics of both the
judgment” that involves quick changes in the beautiful and the sublime into a highly specific
representations considered by the mind (Cri- relationship with one another. I will begin by
tique of the Power of Judgment 331, §54; 335, examining the relation between laughter and
§54). Because laughter is a “pleasure of reflec- the sublime.
tion” in this way (306, §44), joking appears to
constitute a beautiful art. But Kant also II.i laughter and the sublime
describes laughter as an enjoyable vibration of
the body’s organs that aids digestion, thus Laughter and the sublime both occur when the
suggesting that joking more closely approxi- world of appearances departs from its normal
mates a merely agreeable art (332–34, §54; mode of operating in harmony with the subject’s
Anthropology 281). The following quote illus- faculty of judgment. Kant explains that laughter
trates how joking troubles Kant’s distinction arises when a joke presents an idea that clashes
between beautiful and agreeable art: with the subject’s expectations:

In everything that is to provoke a lively,


Music7 and material for laughter are two
uproarious laughter, there must be some-
kinds of play with aesthetic ideas or even rep-
thing nonsensical (in which, therefore, the
resentations of the understanding, by which
understanding in itself can take no satisfac-
in the end nothing is thought, and which
tion). Laughter is an affect resulting from
can gratify merely through their change,
the sudden transformation of a heightened
and nevertheless do so in a lively fashion;
expectation into nothing. (332, §54)
by which they make it fairly evident that
the animation in both cases is merely corpor-
Later, Kant claims that a joke presents an illu-
eal, although it is around by ideas of the
sion “that can deceive for a moment” (334,
mind. (Critique of the Power of Judgment
332, §54) §54). The dinner party guests laugh at Kant’s
joke about the overflowing bottle of beer
While Kant acknowledges that laughter orig- because the Indian guest’s response “tricks”
inates in a play within the reflective power of their power of judgment. The sublime also

165
“making reason think more”

originates in a representation that is contrapur- involve a discordance between the cognitive fac-
posive with respect to the subject’s faculty of ulties; and (3) please the subject by way of a cor-
judgment (245, §23). The subject feels the responding displeasure.
sublime when the immense size or power of a These close connections between laughter
natural object stymies the imagination’s and the sublime have not gone unnoticed by
attempt to represent it to the satisfaction of scholars of Kantian aesthetics.9 Stephen
reason. Laughter and the sublime both originate Nichols, for example, argues that laughter con-
in a representation that is contrapurposive with stitutes the “anti-sublime.” According to
respect to the subject’s cognitive faculties. Nichols, laughter is a sudden gesture of the
Laughter and the sublime also constitute body that generates a critical, though sometimes
complex judgments that yield paradoxical feel- frightening breach within the subject. Through
ings of pleasure. Kant describes both laughter laughter, previously inexpressible or unima-
and the sublime as a “mental agitation” (Bewe- gined possibilities for selfhood become more
gung des Gemüths) that pleases the subject only plausible (381). (Here we might note Kant’s
by means of an unpleasant discord between the claim that in laughter “the joker in ourselves
faculties (247, §24; 334, §54).8 The pleasure of is exposed” (Critique of the Power of Judgment
laughter consists paradoxically in how a joke 335, §54).) As in the terrifying (yet pleasurable)
frustrates and fatigues the mind: breach that the sublime introduces within the
subject (specifically, between his faculties of
When the illusion disappears into nothing, imagination and reason), the subject experi-
the mind looks back again in order to try it ences “a kind of dread and awe” at the disjunc-
once more, and thus is hurried this way and tion laughter generates between him and
that by rapidly succeeding increases and himself (Nichols 381). Unlike the sublime,
decreases of tension and set into oscillation: however, the paradoxical pleasure of laughter
which, because that which as it were struck
does not serve to reassure the subject about
the string bounces back suddenly (not
the power of his rational faculty (382). Laughter
through a gradual slackening), is bound to
cause a movement of the mind [agitation] instead
and an internal bodily movement in
produces the opposite result: a sense of the
harmony with it, which continues involunta-
body as grotesque and abject, linked to the
rily, and produces weariness, but at the
self in a mocking caricature of identity,
same time also cheerfulness. (334, §54)
with the mind actively questioning what
The sublime also originates in an unpleasant this means, while yet incapable of formulat-
mental vibration. Kant writes: ing answers, let alone of imposing order –
in essence, a kind of negative or anti-
sublime. (384)
The mind feels itself moved [agitated] in the
representation of the sublime in nature […] For Nichols, laughter obeys the logic of the
This movement [agitation] (especially in its Kantian sublime but reverses its sign. Rather
inception) may be compared to a vibration,
than culminating in the triumph of reason,
i.e., to a rapidly alternating repulsion from
laughter proliferates incongruity and difference
and attraction to one and the same object.
(258, §27) across the thinking subject.
Nichols presents a compelling case for under-
The pleasure of the sublime arises only by way standing laughter as the anti-sublime. As a para-
of this unpleasant mental agitation: “the object doxical pleasure stemming from a discord
is taken up as sublime with a pleasure that is between the cognitive faculties, laughter in
possible only by means of a displeasure” (260, Kant is indeed formally analogous to the
§27). Laughter and the sublime both (1) orig- sublime, even as the two experiences work in
inate in a representation that is contrapurposive diametrically opposed directions. Before
with respect to the power of judgment; (2) unpacking the full significance of laughter’s

166
giamario

status as the formal analog of the sublime, the understanding, in this presentation in
however, we must attend to laughter’s connec- which it does not find what was expected,
tion to the other aesthetic judgment in Kant – suddenly relaxes, [and] one feels the effect
the beautiful. of this relaxation in the body through the
oscillation of the organs, which promotes
the restoration of their balance and has a ben-
II.ii laughter and the beautiful eficial influence on health. (332, §54)

The third Critique and Anthropology offer Here, and on two other occasions on the same
many reasons and resources for interpreting page, Kant identifies the understanding as the
Kant’s account of laughter through the lens of cognitive faculty involved in laughter. The
the beautiful. First, section 54 seeks to deter- subject laughs when the understanding cannot
mine whether the category of beautiful art can make sense of the world with the empirical con-
accommodate the practice of joking responsible cepts and rules it normally employs. As the
for laughter. We see Kant’s preoccupation with world of appearances diverges from its expec-
the beautiful in his reference to “the harmonies tations, the understanding experiences a
in [musical] tones or sallies of wit […] with their certain frustration before suddenly relaxing
beauty” and his characterization of joking as a and providing the subject with the paradoxical
“beautiful play” (332, §54). Second, Kant pleasure of laughter.
characterizes the capacity to produce laughter The second key passage in §54 introduces the
as an ability akin to genius, the talent of produ- imagination into the equation. Kant writes:
cing beautiful art (307, §46; 334, §54). Third,
Kant describes dinner party jesting as an music and material for laughter are two kinds
activity enjoyed by “men of taste (aesthetically of play with aesthetic ideas or even represen-
united)” – that is, men who have a particular tations of the understanding, by which in the
end nothing is thought, and which can gratify
sensitivity to the beautiful (Anthropology
merely through their change, and neverthe-
278). Fourth, Kant claims that laughter, just less do so in a lively fashion. (332, §54)
like the beautiful, originates in a disinterested
play of the faculties: The important part here is Kant’s claim that
laughter originates in a “play with aesthetic
the play of thoughts […] arises merely from ideas.” While Kant in this passage reduces aes-
the change in the representations, in the thetic ideas to “representations of the under-
faculty of judgment, by means of which, to standing,” his more detailed discussions of
be sure, no thought that involves any sort aesthetic ideas suggest an alternative reading.
of interest is generated, but the mind is An aesthetic idea, Kant explains in section 49,
nevertheless animated. (331, §54) is a representation of the imagination that the
understanding cannot account for with its con-
Kant’s description of laughter as a play of cepts and rules:
thought is itself significant because the cognitive
faculties enter into a “play” in the beautiful, by an aesthetic idea […] I mean that rep-
while “seriousness” characterizes the mind’s resentation of the imagination that occasions
attitude in the sublime (244–45, §23). much thinking though without it being poss-
ible for any determinate thought, i.e.,
The most important link between laughter
concept, to be adequate to it, which, conse-
and the beautiful, however, concerns the cogni-
quently, no language fully attains or can
tive faculties that both feelings call into play. make intelligible. (314, §49)
Like the beautiful, laughter in Kant involves a
relation between the understanding and the Aesthetic ideas express the imagination’s crea-
imagination. Two key passages in section 54 tive power free from interference or regulation
establish this. The first describes what by the understanding (342, §57). In an aesthetic
happens when a subject laughs: idea, “the imagination (as a productive cognitive

167
“making reason think more”

faculty) is […] very powerful in creating, as it and not based on concepts. But while in a judg-
were, another nature, out of the material ment of taste the understanding and the imagin-
which the real one gives it,” allowing the mind ation enter into a reciprocal harmony with one
to “transform” experience (314, §49). The another, in laughter these faculties work at
power of aesthetic ideas is made manifest in cross-purposes and arrive at an impasse. The
art forms like poetry (ibid.). Kant’s description imagination overburdens the understanding
of laughter as “a play with aesthetic ideas” is with ideas it cannot comprehend, and the under-
decisive because it reveals that laughter does standing clings to a set of expectations that it
not constitute a judgment that originates would rather abandon completely than accom-
merely in an activity of the understanding but modate to these ideas. From both sides, the
instead arises out of a particular relationship harmony of the beautiful is foreclosed. The
between the understanding and the imagination. paradoxical pleasure generated by the discord
In section 21 Kant notes that the “attune- between the imagination and the understanding
ment” (Stimmung) between the understanding in laughter mirrors the paradoxical pleasure
and the imagination “has a different proportion generated by the discord between the imagin-
depending on the difference of the objects that ation and reason in the sublime. Laughter is
are given” (238).10 How can we describe the the analog of the sublime in the realm of
attunement between these faculties when the taste. Kantian laughter applies the sublime’s
subject laughs at a witty joke? The first logic of discord and impasse to the cognitive fac-
passage above indicates that the understanding ulties of the imagination and understanding at
carries a tense set of expectations that it regu- play in judgments of taste.
larly employs to order and make sense of the This argument extends and deepens Kant’s
world. A joke, however, confronts the under- commitment to analogical reasoning in the
standing with aesthetic ideas that it cannot com- third Critique. As Lyotard and Callanan point
prehend with its concepts and rules. After out, analogy plays a central role in Kant’s philo-
trying and failing to subsume these aesthetic sophical project, particularly his work on judg-
ideas under its concepts and rules, the under- ment. In fact, Kant defends the very viability
standing suddenly relaxes, and the subject and necessity of the third Critique by establish-
laughs. Kant insists that the understanding ing an analogy between the faculty of judgment
simply surrenders in its encounter with the and the other cognitive faculties. He introduces
imagination’s aesthetic ideas: its expectations the Critique of the Power of Judgment by
are transformed into “nothing,” rather than noting that
into their opposite (332–33, §54). Instead of
comprehending these ideas with new concepts in the family of the higher faculties of cogni-
or rules, the understanding simply relents, and tion there is still an intermediary between the
its expectations transform into nothing. This understanding and reason. This is the power
change in the posture of the understanding of judgment, about which one has cause to
presume, by analogy, that it too should
(rather than the production of new knowledge)
contain in itself a priori, if not exactly its
yields laughter. As Kant notes, laughter is an
own legislation, then still a proper principle
aesthetic experience: “nothing is thought, and of its own for seeking laws. (177)
[it] can gratify merely through [the represen-
tations’] change” (332, §54). Analogical reasoning reappears at other decisive
Pulling these strands together, we can say moments in the third Critique. For example, the
that laughter constitutes an aesthetic judgment concept of the purposiveness of nature rests on
that brings the beautiful and the sublime into an analogy with the idea of practical purposive-
a highly specific relation with one another. ness (181); the famous argument about beauty
Like the beautiful, laughter is a pleasure orig- as the symbol of the morally good is ultimately
inating in a relation between the understanding a claim about their analogical relationship (353–
and the imagination that is both disinterested 54, §59); and Kant’s contention that the subject

168
giamario

can conceive of the properties of God involves that it contributes to the third Critique’s task
drawing an analogy between God and man of unifying freedom and nature. She explains
(456, §88). My argument that laughter is the that laughter performs the same unifying func-
analog of the sublime in the realm of taste is, tion as the beautiful, but in reverse. Whereas
in short, authorized by the third Critique itself. in the beautiful a natural form pleases the
subject on a cognitive level, in laughter an
activity between the cognitive faculties pleases
III laughter and aesthetic judgment the subject on a sensuous level: “Though the
Kant is undoubtedly aware on at least some level operation is reversed, the significance is the
of these connections between laughter and the same: the body – which we experience as
beautiful and the sublime. If he were not, it phenomenon – and the mind – noumenon –
would be difficult to explain why he devotes are connected; they communicate, they affect
more than six pages to joking and laughter in each other” (323). Hounsokou also claims that
the middle of a treatise of critical philosophy certain kinds of laughter remind the subject of
(330–36, §54). No other art – certainly no her moral vocation in a manner akin to the
other agreeable art – receives this amount of sublime (326–27). Despite Kant’s dismissal of
attention in the third Critique. How can we laughter’s significance in his critical philosophy,
account for the presence of Kant’s “Remark” Hounsokou concludes that laughter participates
on laughter? We can begin by noting that for in the third Critique’s project of bridging the
Kant a key task of critical philosophy is “to gulf between nature and freedom (330).
institute a court of justice” that distinguishes While Hounsokou’s reading undoubtedly
between proper and improper objects of trans- marks an advance over Kant’s own appraisal
cendental analysis (Critique of Pure Reason of laughter’s importance in his project, her argu-
Axi–xii). Kant dwells on laughter because he ment actually prevents us from grasping the full
worries that its source in a “play of the power significance of Kant’s account of laughter. For
of judgment” (Critique of the Power of Judg- Hounsokou, the links between laughter, the
ment 335, §54) might lead readers into matters beautiful, and the sublime consist only in the
that ultimately carry only empirical signifi- similar effects these judgments have on the
cance, thus distracting them from the proper subject. Like the beautiful, laughter involves a
object of critical-transcendental analysis (the feeling of freedom within the sensible domain
possibility of a priori judgments). His efforts (323), and like the sublime, laughter can
to disqualify joking from the domain of beauti- inspire the subject to act morally (326–27,
ful art in section 54 suggest that laughter resides 330). But this narrow focus on how laughter,
just beyond the borders of critical-transcenden- the beautiful, and the sublime affect the
tal legitimacy.11 Due to its origin in a play of the subject leads Hounsokou to conflate these aes-
power of judgment, laughter is more than a thetic judgments and likewise mischaracterize
simple affect Kant can write off as an empirical laughter. She argues that “laughter is arguably
or anthropological issue, but its status as a aesthetic, beautiful, and even sublime,” and
bodily sensation precludes us from including that we should consider laughter “a species of
it in critical philosophy. Section 54 functions, beauty and the sublime, and consequently, as
in other words, to protect Kant’s larger critique point of reconciliation between nature and
of judgment from contamination by the ambig- freedom, sensible and supersensible, in its own
uous judgment of laughter. right” (318). The problem here is that we
Several scholars claim that section 54’s cannot treat laughter as both beautiful and
account of laughter plays a more important sublime or as a “species” of the beautiful and
role in the Kantian project than Kant himself the sublime. The beautiful and the sublime in
acknowledges. Most recently, Annie Hounsokou Kant are highly specific judgments that differ
has argued that laughter’s status as both an aes- in fundamental ways (e.g., they involve different
thetic judgment and bodily sensation means cognitive faculties that enter into different

169
“making reason think more”

forms of relation with one another). They do not My understanding of Kantian laughter
constitute a single genus of which laughter departs from the approaches of both Hounso-
could form a species.12 Rather than eliding the kou and Godfrey. As described above, laugh-
important differences between laughter, the ter cannot constitute a “species” of the
beautiful, and the sublime by focusing on beautiful and the sublime because the latter
their similar effects, grasping the full signifi- do not constitute a single genus of which
cance of Kant’s account of laughter requires laughter could be a member. Godfrey’s
attending to the specific relations that obtain account, while more careful on these points,
between these aesthetic judgments along the nevertheless fails to refine and develop its
lines pursued in Sections I and II above. key insight that laughter is a species of taste
A second commentator adopts an approach analogous to the sublime. I contend that
that is much more sensitive to these issues. In when we identify laughter as the analog of
an apparently forgotten 1937 essay, “The Aes- the sublime within the realm of taste
thetics of Laughter,” F. Godfrey offers a (Section II), we find that rather than reflecting
reading of Kant’s account of laughter within a species of the beautiful and the sublime
the context of his aesthetic philosophy. (Hounsokou) or a third type of aesthetic judg-
Godfrey contends that laughter “fulfils a distinc- ment (Godfrey), the judgments of the beauti-
tive function in the rational life” and constitutes ful and the sublime intersect and share a
an important component of the Kantian critical common root in the judgment of laughter.
project (126). He describes laughter as a Laughter is the cloth from which both the
“species of taste” (ibid.) involving a breakdown beautiful and the sublime are cut. The beauti-
between the cognitive faculties “analogous” to ful transforms laughter’s discordant relation
that which occurs in the sublime (130). A joke between the understanding and the imagin-
frustrates the understanding, and laughter ation into a harmonious relation, while the
reflects an effort by reason to preserve the sublime transforms laughter’s discordant
mind’s sanity in the face of an unexpected dis- relation between the imagination and the
ruption (129). In addition to performing this understanding into a discordant relation
“defensive” function through laughter, reason between the imagination and reason. Hounso-
actively benefits from laughter’s indulgence of kou’s argument is thus correct, but only in
the imagination: reverse: the beautiful and the sublime are
species of laughter. Insofar as the beautiful
the mind when confronted with an absurdity and the sublime are related to one another in
is not reduced to nothing, but plays with it in Kant’s philosophical system, both judgments
fancy, and so sanity is preserved. The imagin- presuppose laughter. A transcendental laugh
ation now is not merely reproductive […] but – a laugh that does not actually occur, but
productive, for reason refuses to be confined
always must have occurred – is the condition
to the actual, but widens our outlook to the
of possibility for the beautiful and the
infinite realm of the possible, contingent,
and impossible. (132) sublime.13 Laughter, considered from a trans-
cendental point of view, constitutes the most
Unlike Hounsokou, Godfrey is attentive to the basic aesthetic judgment in Kant. This con-
specific relations that obtain between the cogni- clusion requires us to reassess the role that aes-
tive faculties in laughter, the beautiful, and the thetic judgment plays in the Kantian
sublime, and rather than characterizing laughter philosophical system as a whole.14
as a “species” of the beautiful and the sublime,
he concludes that laughter constitutes a third IV laughter in kant’s critical
form of aesthetic judgment in Kant. Godfrey
philosophy
writes that laughter “is an aesthetic judgment,
akin to, though distinct from, the judgments In the Second Introduction to the Critique of
of the beautiful and the sublime” (126). the Power of Judgment Kant suggests that the

170
giamario

sections on aesthetic judgment take precedence An aesthetic idea is the “counterpart” of a


over those on teleological judgment. He writes: rational idea because the former attempts to
make the latter more real and palpable to the
In a critique of the power of judgment the
subject. Aesthetic ideas “strive toward some-
part that contains the aesthetic power of judg-
ment is essential, since this alone contains a thing lying beyond the bounds of experience,
principle that the power of judgment lays at and thus seek to approximate a presentation of
the basis of its reflection on nature entirely concepts of reason (of intellectual ideas),
a priori. (193) which gives them the appearance of an objective
reality” (Critique of the Power of Judgment
If the third Critique aims to connect the con- 314, §49). For example, a poet’s aesthetic ideas
cepts of nature and freedom, and aesthetic judg- can give sensible expression to the rational
ment belongs to this Critique “essentially,” then idea of God (314, §49).
my argument that laughter (rather than the Kant goes on to suggest that aesthetic ideas
beautiful or the sublime) constitutes the most do more than merely exhibit the ideas of
basic aesthetic judgment entails a radical re- reason. In section 49 he explains that they
evaluation of aesthetic judgment’s role in stimulate reason to “think more,” or to trans-
Kant’s philosophical system. In this section I form its ideas:
determine how laughter achieves the third Cri-
tique’s task of bridging the gulf between Now if a concept is provided with a presen-
nature and freedom. tation of the imagination such that, even
To do this, we must return to Kant’s descrip- though this presentation belongs to the exhi-
tion of laughter as a “play with aesthetic ideas” bition of the concept, yet it prompts, even by
(332, §54). As described above, aesthetic ideas itself, so much thought as can never be com-
are representations of the imagination that the prehended within a determinate concept and
understanding cannot account for with its con- thereby the presentation aesthetically
cepts and rules (314, §49; 342–43, §57). Kant expands the concept itself in an unlimited
also notes, however, that an aesthetic idea “is way, then the imagination is creative in this
and sets the power of intellectual ideas (i.e.,
the counterpart (pendant) of an idea of
reason) in motion: it makes reason think
reason” (314, §49). Whereas an aesthetic idea
more, when prompted by a presentation,
is an intuition that no concept can adequately than what can be apprehended and made dis-
grasp, an idea of reason (or a rational idea) is a tinct in the presentation.15 (314–15, §49;
concept that no representation of the imagin- emphasis added)
ation can adequately exhibit (314, §49). Kant
claims that reason generates its own concepts According to Kant, the imagination can stimu-
(or “ideas”) that do not derive from the under- late reason to think beyond what is presently
standing or intuition and that strive for the entailed by its ideas. This is an absolutely
absolute or the unconditioned in the realms of crucial point because it means that laughter’s
theoretical knowledge and practical action (Cri- “play with aesthetic ideas” is in the end not a
tique of Pure Reason A299/B355, A326–29/ mental activity limited to the understanding
B382–85). He writes: and the imagination. The confrontation
between the understanding and the imagination
Reason does not give in to those grounds in laughter jostles the mind as a whole and puts
which are empirically given, and it does not
reason to work. The force that laughter exerts
follow the order of things as they are pre-
on reason exceeds that typically exerted by an
sented in intuition, but with complete spon-
taneity it makes its own order according to aesthetic idea because in laughter an aesthetic
ideas, to which it fits the empirical conditions idea is brought into direct conflict with the
and according to which it even declares understanding’s empirical concepts, and this
actions to be necessary that have not occurred discordance dramatizes precisely what is at
and perhaps will not occur. (A548/B576) stake in reason: the subject’s capacity to think

171
“making reason think more”

and act beyond the empirical. Laughter makes V conclusion: laughter and critique
reason “think more” by prompting it to revise
or generate new ideas about the world and how After arguing that the sublime reveals the supre-
the subject ought to act in it. Through laughter macy of human reason over nature, Kant
the mind can arrive at new principles for remarks: “To be sure, this principle seems far-
thought and action. Because reason is always fetched and subtle, hence excessive for an aes-
the source of its own ideas (Critique of Pure thetic judgment” (Critique of the Power of
Reason A548/B576), this transformation con- Judgment 262, §28). Perhaps one could say
stitutes an enactment of reason in its freedom. the same for the conclusions reached in this
Laughter actualizes what John Zammito ident- essay. Should we really regard laughter pro-
ifies as reason’s “immanent dynamism, the duced by dinner party witticisms as of greater
capacity to set its own goals and to pursue importance in Kant’s aesthetics than the beauti-
them” (171) and what Nikolas Kompridis ful and the sublime? My goal has been to ident-
describes as reason’s power to disclose new pos- ify and follow a minor thread in Kant (section
sibilities for thought and action (235). Laughter, 54’s account of laughter) in order to trace its
in short, stimulates a free transformation of the effects on our thinking about his aesthetic phil-
ideas of reason.16 osophy. Pursuing this thread has yielded a
Returning to the question posed at the reading of Kantian aesthetics at odds with
beginning of this section: how does a reading both Kant’s own conclusions and conventional
of laughter as the most basic aesthetic judg- interpretations of his project. Whereas Kant
ment in Kant impact our understanding of aes- argues that laughter merely enhances the sub-
thetic judgment’s role in his philosophical ject’s “feeling of health” (332, §54), we find
system? The aesthetic judgment of laughter that laughter affects the subject on the intellec-
unites nature and freedom in a very particular tual level of reason’s ideas. Laughter prompts
way. If the pleasure of the sublime consists in reason to freely transform how the subject
how the contrapurposiveness of nature para- thinks about and acts in the world, and it like-
doxically reveals the strength of the subject’s wise plays a crucial – if until now largely unac-
reason, then the pleasure of laughter consists knowledged – role in his aesthetic philosophy.
in how the contrapurposiveness of a joke para- I conclude by following this minor thread a
doxically stimulates the free activity of reason. few steps further to consider how my interpret-
The joke is purposive from the perspective of ation of section 54 impacts our conception of a
reason because the laughter it generates stimu- specifically “Kantian” practice of critique.
lates reason to freely transform its principles In the first Critique Kant declares the task of
for thinking about and acting in the sensible critical philosophy to be one of judgment (Axi–
world. Aesthetic judgment thus mediates xii). That is, reason determines its proper
between nature and freedom not simply by capacities and limits by instituting “a court of
assuring the subject that the purposes of justice” between its mutually incompatible yet
nature can harmonize with those of freedom equally necessary metaphysical theses (i.e., anti-
(as in the beautiful) or inspiring the subject nomies) (Axi; A420–25/B448–53). Such dis-
to act freely in an inhospitable natural world putes arise out of a “transcendental illusion,”
(as in the sublime), but by actually enacting namely, reason’s unavoidable propensity to
reason’s power of free self-transformation by confuse subjective principles of empirical
means of a sensible stimulus that is ostensibly knowledge for knowledge of objects as they
at odds with the subject’s purposes. An are in themselves (A297/B353–54). In a 1786
account of aesthetic judgment that begins essay “What does it mean to orient oneself in
with laughter showcases how a sensible world thinking?” Kant argues that in the absence of
not predisposed to the subject can nevertheless objective criteria, reason judges the metaphys-
advance his or her rational vocation to think ical assertions it is justified in making by
and act freely. means of a feeling:

172
giamario

One can easily guess that it will be a concern between Kant’s critical method and the aes-
of pure reason to guide its use when it wants thetic judgment of laughter. These parallels
to leave familiar objects (of experience) appear quite readily. Recall that in laughter an
behind, extending itself beyond all the illusion generated by a joke occasions a
bounds of experience […] For then it is no discord between the faculties, and this discord
longer in a position to bring its judgments
stimulates a free self-transformation within the
under a determinate maxim according to
objective grounds of cognition, but solely to
subject’s power of reason (Sections II–IV).
bring its judgments under a determinate Similarly, in critical philosophy more generally,
maxim according to a subjective ground of an illusion (the mind’s propensity to take sub-
differentiation in the determination of its jective principles of thought for objective
own faculty of judgment. This subjective knowledge about the world) occasions a conflict
means still remaining is nothing other than within reason that prompts the formation of a
reason’s feeling of its own need. (136; new self-understanding of its capacities and
emphasis added) bounds (Critique of Pure Reason A497–507/
B525–35). In both laughter and critique, a
According to Kant, reason “orients” itself (or discord between the cognitive faculties occa-
critically judges which metaphysical assertions sioned by an illusion prompts a free self-trans-
it can justifiably advance) solely by means of a formation within the power of reason. To be
subjective feeling. From the very beginning certain, the illusions that spark the judgments
there exists an irreducibly aesthetic dimension of laughter and critique are very different –
to Kantian critique. the former is a contingent, sensible, and incon-
The Second Introduction to the Critique of sequential joke shared among dinner party
the Power of Judgment makes this connection guests, while the latter is a necessary, transcen-
between critique, judgment, and aesthetics dental, and intractable illusion generated by
explicit. Here Kant identifies the centrality of reason itself. However, the form that judgment
aesthetic judgment to the critical enterprise as takes in laughter and critique is identical.
a whole: Laughter constitutes the modality of judgment
at the heart of Kantian critical philosophy as a
the aesthetic power of judgment contributes whole. Driven to laughter by the “joke” played
nothing to the cognition of its objects and on it by its own transcendental illusion, reason
thus must be counted only as part of the cri- freely attains enlightened self-knowledge.
tique of the judging subject and its cognitive
Attending to the account of laughter that Kant
faculties, insofar as these are capable of a
advances in section 54 of the Critique of the
priori principles […] which is the propaedeu-
tic of all philosophy. (194) Power of Judgment demon-
strates that Kantian critical phil-
The subject determines what she is capable of osophy is – despite its well-
knowing by means of an aesthetic judgment. earned reputation as serious
As Lyotard notes, “aesthetic judgment conceals and uncompromising – a philos-
[…] a secret more important than that of doc- ophy of laughter.
trine, the secret of the ‘manner’ (rather than
the method) in which critical thought proceeds
in general” (6). The third Critique’s Analytic
disclosure statement
of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment thus No potential conflict of interest was reported by
serves as a meditation on the possibility of criti- the author.
cal philosophy in general.
If there exists an irreducibly aesthetic dimen-
sion to Kantian criticism, and if laughter is the notes
most basic form of aesthetic judgment in Kant, The author thanks the anonymous reviewer for his
then we would expect to find important parallels or her generous comments and helpful suggestions.

173
“making reason think more”

Sincere thanks also go to Samuel Chambers, famous proponents” of “the incongruity theory”
William Connolly, Andrew Cutrofello, Tripp of laughter (16).
Rebrovick, Zach Reyna, Jon Masin-Peters, and the
7 While Kant often considers joking and music in
participants of the 2015 Western Political Science
the same breath, he does not hold the two arts
Association panel “Painful Sensations, Radical
in equal esteem. At different points Kant includes
Affects, and Corporeal Autonomy.” Deepest
and excludes music from the category of beautiful
thanks are reserved for Ayla Amon for always
art (329–30, §53; 332, §54), but he always describes
reading my work carefully and offering guidance
joking as an agreeable art (305, §44; 332, §54). The
and support.
proximity of joking to an ambiguous art like music
1 As Guyer notes, the first two editions of the further evinces its liminal status in Kant’s
third Critique leave this “Remark” unnumbered. aesthetics.
However, the Remark falls between sections 53
8 Here and below I prefer Pluhar’s translation of
and 55, and in order to avoid confusion with the
Bewegung des Gemüths as “mental agitation” over
text’s numerous other “Remarks,” I will refer to
Guyer’s choice of “movement of the mind.” “Agita-
it as section 54.
tion” better captures the forceful, disorienting
2 All Kant citations in this article refer to the stan- effects of laughter and the sublime.
dardized page numbers of the Akademie Ausgabe.
9 In addition to Nichols’s “Laughter as Gesture,”
Unless otherwise indicated, all italics and parenth-
see Adorno’s Aesthetic Theory (198–99), Banki’s
eses belong to the original text.
“Humor as the Inverted Sublime,” Borch-Jacob-
3 See Meredith’s Introductory essay to Kant’s Cri- sen’s “The Laughter of Being,” and Marmysz’s
tique of Aesthetic Judgment, Hounsokou’s “Exposing “Humor, Sublimity and Incongruity.”
the Rogue in Us,” Godfrey’s “The Aesthetics of
10 Here I once again prefer the Pluhar translation.
Laughter,” and Arnold’s “Laughter, Judgment and
Pluhar’s rendering of Stimmung as “attunement”
Democratic Politics.”
better grasps the importance of the relation
4 For various takes on how the third Critique between the understanding and the imagination
bridges the gulf between nature and freedom, than Guyer’s more literal translation of Stimmung
see Deleuze’s Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Guyer’s as “disposition.”
Kant and the Experience of Freedom, Raymae-
11 Perhaps this is why Kant affords laughter such
kers’s “The Importance of Freedom,” and Zam-
an important role at dinner parties. Because it
mito’s The Genesis of Kant’s Critique of
straddles the boundary between sensuous and cog-
Judgment.
nitive pleasure, laughter is uniquely positioned to
5 While Kant briefly examines laughter gener- satisfy the dinner party’s dual mandate of promot-
ated by two other practices, namely naiveté ing “good living” and moral virtue (Anthropology
and caprice (335–36, §54), his analysis of these 277–78).
sources of laughter is much shorter and, in my
12 Following Hounsokou, my use of “genus” and
view, less philosophically rich than his examin-
“species” here and below is non-technical in
ation of laughter generated by joking. For more
nature and serves simply to distinguish between a
on Kant’s account of laughter produced by
group (e.g., the beautiful and the sublime) and its
naiveté and caprice, see Hounsokou’s “Exposing
subgroups (e.g., laughter).
the Rogue in Us.”
13 Laughter’s status as the transcendental con-
6 Importantly, Kant’s analyses of laughter here and
dition of possibility for the beautiful and the
in the Anthropology almost exclusively concern
sublime may dispel some of the mystery about
witty joking that occurs at dinner parties (Critique
why Kant devotes so much attention to laughter
of the Power of Judgment 305–06, §44; Anthropology
in the third Critique.
264–65, 278–81). Because Kant discusses laughter
in extremely narrow terms, section 54 does not 14 To be clear, my claim that laughter constitu-
provide a comprehensive “Theory of Laughter,” tes the most basic aesthetic judgment in Kant is
and we should resist the common characterization not a historical argument. There is no evidence
of Kant as, as Morreall puts it, one of the “most that Kant himself conceives of laughter as more

174
giamario

important than the beautiful or the sublime. My Godfrey, F. la T. “The Aesthetics of Laughter.”
contention is instead a philosophical argument Hermathena 25.50 (1937): 126–38. Print.
about the relation between these three judg-
Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Experience of Freedom.
ments in Kant’s aesthetic system. Insofar as the
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1993. Print.
beautiful and the sublime are related to one
another as modes of unifying nature and Hounsokou, Annie. “‘Exposing the Rogue in Us’:
freedom, they both necessarily presuppose laugh- An Exploration of Laughter in the Critique of
ter as their transcendental condition of Judgment.” Epoché 16.2 (2012): 317–36. Print.
possibility.
Kant, Immanuel. Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point
15 I utilize the Pluhar translation for this quota- of View. Trans. and ed. Robert B. Louden.
tion. Pluhar’s rendering (“it makes reason think Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2006. Print.
more”) captures the stimulative and generative Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgment. Trans. Werner
force that the imagination exerts on reason more S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. Print.
effectively than Guyer’s translation (“it gives
[reason] more to think about”). Kant, Immanuel. Critique of the Power of Judgment.
Trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge:
16 Importantly, when an aesthetic idea “makes Cambridge UP, 2000. Print.
reason think more,” it does not necessarily trans-
form reason’s ideas; it only stimulates reason to Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Practical Reason.
transform its ideas. In other words, jokes do not Practical Philosophy. Trans. and ed. Mary J.
always yield new or revised ideas of reason. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2008. 133–
However, as noted above, the particularly power- 271. Print.
ful agitation of the mind that occurs in laughter
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. and
suggests that laughter exerts a greater stimulative
ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge:
effect on reason than an aesthetic idea acting in
Cambridge UP, 2009. Print.
isolation.
Kant, Immanuel. “What does it mean to orient
oneself in thinking?” Religion and Rational Theology.
Ed. and Trans. Allen Wood. Cambridge:
bibliography Cambridge UP, 2001. 1–18. Print.
Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory. Trans. Kompridis, Nikolas. Critique and Disclosure: Critical
Robert Hullot-Kentor. Minneapolis: U of Theory between Past and Future. Cambridge, MA:
Minnesota P, 1997. Print. MIT P, 2006. Print.
Arnold, Jeremy. “Laughter, Judgment and Lyotard, Jean-François. Lessons on the Analytic of the
Democratic Politics.” Culture, Theory and Critique Sublime. Trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg. Stanford:
50.1 (2009): 7–21. Print. Stanford UP, 1994. Print.
Banki, Peter. “Humor as the Inverted Sublime: Jean Marmysz, John. “Humor, Sublimity and
Paul’s Laughter within Limitations.” Parrhesia 21 Incongruity.” Consciousness, Literature and the Arts
(2014): 58–68. Print. 2.3 (2001): n. pag. Print.
Borch-Jacobsen, Mikkel. “The Laughter of Being.” Meredith, James Creed. “Art and the Artist.”
MLN 102.4 (1987): 737–60. Print. Introduction. Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment.
Ed. James Meredith Creed. Oxford: Clarendon,
Callanan, John J. “Kant on Analogy.” British Journal
1911. cxviii–cxliv. Print.
for the History of Philosophy 16.4 (2008): 747–72.
Print. Morreall, John. Taking Laughter Seriously. Albany:
State U of New York P, 1983. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles. Kant’s Critical Philosophy: The
Doctrine of the Faculties. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson Nichols, Stephen G. “Laughter as Gesture: Hilarity
and Barbara Habberjam. Minneapolis: U of and the Anti-Sublime.” Neohelicon 32.2 (2005):
Minnesota P, 2007. Print. 375–89. Print.

175
“making reason think more”

Raymaekers, Bart. “The Importance of Freedom in


the Architectonic of the Critique of Judgment.” Kants
Ästhetik/Kant’s Aesthetics/L’Esthétique de Kant. Ed.
Herman Parret. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1998. 84–92.
Print.
Zammito, John H. The Genesis of Kant’s Critique of
Judgment. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1992. Print.

Patrick T. Giamario
Department of Political Science
Johns Hopkins University
338 Mergenthaler Hall
3400 N. Charles Street
Baltimore, MD 21218
USA
E-mail: pgiamar1@jhu.edu

You might also like