You are on page 1of 3

1 40 E XT E N S I O N T H E G OALS O F PSYC H O L I N G U I S T I C S 1 41

THE GOALS O F PSYCHOLl N G U ISTICS materials - can be summarized as tests of a person' s ability to repeat the speech George A.

This text is a shortened version of an important article written in the early days of . he hears under various conditions of audibility or delay. M ill e r
George A.
Psycholinguistics. The issues it outlines are still very much the concern of the field If a listener can hear and match an utterance, the next question to ask is whether
M ill er "
�� � 8 '"
today. Amongst the points it makes, note the concept of levels of processing. This he will accept it as a sentence in terms of his knowledge of grammar. At this level
assumes that readers and listeners achieve understanding by taking language through we encounter processes difficult to study experimentally, and one is forced to rely
a series of stages, starting with perception and ending with evaluation. most heavily on linguistic analyses of the structure of sentences. Some experiments
are possible, however, for we can measure how much a listener' s ability to accept
the utterance as a sentence facilitates his ability to hear and match it; grammatical
The Psycholinguists
sentences are much easier to hear, utter, or remember than are ungrammatical strings
of words, and even nonsense (pirot, karol, elat, etc.) is easier to deal with if it looks
George A. Miller (from The Psychology of Communication: Seven Essays. Harmon d sworth,
grammatical (pirots karolize elatically, etc.) (Epstein, 1 96 1 ) . Needless to say, the gram­
Penguin, 1 968: pp. 74-86. Abridged with permission of the author.)
matical knowledge we wish to study does not concern those explicit rules drilled
into us by teachers of traditional grammar, but rather the implicit generative know­
Interest in psycholinguistics . . . is not confined to psychologists and linguists . Many ledge that we all must acquire in order to use a language appropriately.
people have been stirred by splendid visions of its practical possibilities. One thinks Beyond grammatical acceptance comes semantic interpretation: we can ask how
of medical applications to the diagnosis and treatment of a heterogeneous variety listeners interpret an utterance as meaningful in terms of their semantic system.
of language disorders ranging from simple stammering to the overwhelming com­ Interpretation is not merely a matter of assigning meanings to individual words;
plexities of aphasia. One thinks too of pedagogical applications, of potential improve­ we must also consider how these component meanings combine in grammatical
ments in our methods for teaching reading and writing, or for teaching second sentences. Compare the sentences: ' Healthy young babies sleep soundly' and
languages. If psycholinguistic principles were made sufficiently explicit, they could •
' Colourless green ideas sleep furiously. ' Although they are syntactically similar,
be imparted to those technological miracles of the twentieth century, the com­ the second is far harder to perceive and remember correctly - because it cannot
puting machines, which would bring into view a whole spectrum of cybernetic be interpreted by the usual semantic rules for combining the senses of adjacent
possibilities. . . . English words (Miller and Isard, 1 963). The interpretation of each word is affected
The integration of psycholinguistic studies has occurred so recently that there by the company it keeps ; a central problem is to systematize the interactions of
is still some confusion concerning its scope and purpose; efforts to clarify it neces­ words and phrases with their linguistic contexts . . . .
sarily have something of the character of personal opinion . In my own version, At the next level it seems essential to make some distinction between inter­
the central task of this new science is to describe the psychological processes that preting an utterance and understanding it, for understanding frequently goes well
go on when people use sentences . The real crux of the psycholinguistic problem beyond the linguistic context provided by the utterance itself. A husband greeted
does not appear until one tries to deal with sentences , for only then does the at the door by 'I bought some electric light bulbs today' must do more than inter­
importance of productivity become completely obvious . It is true that productiv­ pret its literal reference; he must understand that he should go to the kitchen and
ity can also appear with individual words, but there it is not overwhelming. With replace that burned-out lamp . Such contextual information lies well outside any
sentences, productivity is literally unlimited. grammar or lexicon. The listener can understand the function of an utterance in
Before considering this somewhat technical problem, however, it might be terms of contextual knowledge of the most diverse sort.
well to illustrate the variety of processes that psycholinguists hope to explain. This Finally, at a level now almost invisible through the clouds, a listener may
can best be done if we ask what a listener can do about a spoken utterance, and believe that an utterance is valid in terms of its relevance to his own conduct. The
consider his alternatives in order from the superficial to the inscrutable. child who says ' I saw five lions in the garden' may be heard, matched, accepted,
The simplest thing one can do in the presence of a spoken utterance is to interpreted, and understood, but in few parts of the world will he be believed.
listen. Even if the language is incomprehensible, one can still bear an utterance as The boundaries between successive levels are not sharp and distinct. One shades
an auditory stimulus and respond to it in terms of some discriminative set: how off gradually into the next. Still the hierarchy . is real enough and important to
loud, how fast, how long, from which direction, etc. keep in mind. Simpler types of psycholinguistic processes can be studied rather
Given that an utterance is heard, the next level involves matcbina it as a phon­ intensively; already we know much about hearing and matching. Accepting and
emic pattern in terms of phonological skills acquired as a user of the language . interpreting are just now coming into scientific focus . Understanding is still over
The ability to match an input can be tested in psychological experiments by ask­ the horizon, and pragmatic questions involving belief system are at present so vague
ing listeners to echo what they hear; a wide variety of experimental situations - as to be hardly worth asking. But the whole range of processes must be included
experiments on the perception of speech and on the rote memorization of verbal in any adequate definition of psycholinguistics.
1 42 EXTEN S I O N T H E GOALS O F PSYC H O L I N G U I ST I C S 1 43

'
George A. ' I phrased the description of these various psycholinguistic processes in terms is rule-governed behaviour characterized by enormous flexibility and freedom of George A.
M i ller " of a listener; the question inevitably arises as to whether a different hierarchy . choice . Miller "
, "
is required to describe the speaker. One problem a psycholinguist faces is to Obvious as this conclusion may seem, it has important implications for any
decide whether speaking and listening are two separate abilities, co-ordinate but scientific theory of language. If rules involve the concepts of right and wrong, they
distinct, or whether they are merely different manifestations of a single linguistic introduce a normative aspect that has always been avoided in the natural sciences.
faculty. One hears repeatedly that the scientist's ability to suppress normative judgements
The mouth and ear are different organs; at the simplest levels we must dis­ about his subject matter enables him to see the world objectively, as it really is .
tinguish hearing and matching from vocalizing and speaking. At more complex To admit that language follows rules seems to put it outside the range of phenom­
levels it is less easy to decide whether the two abilities are distinct. At some point ena accessible to scientific investigation.
they must converge, if only to explain why it is so difficult to speak am). listen At this point a psycholinguist who wishes to preserve his standing as a natural
simultaneously. The question is where . . . . scientist faces an old but always difficult decision. Should he withdraw and leave
Suppose we accept the notion that a listener recognizes what he hears by com­ the study of language to others? Or should he give up all pretence of being
paring it with some internal representation. . . . One trouble with this hypothesis a 'natural scientist' , searching for causal explanations, and embrace a more
. . . is that a listener must be ready to recognize any one of an enormous number phenomenological approach? Or should he push blindly ahead with his empirical
of different sentences. It is inconceivable that a separate internal representation of methods, hoping to find a causal basis for normative practices but running the risk
each of them could be stored in his memory in advance. Halle and Stevens [ 1 962] that all his efforts will be wasted because rule-governed behaviour in principle lies
suggest that these internal representations must be generated as they are needed beyond the scope of natural science?
by following the same generative rules that are usually used in producing speech. To withdraw means to abandon hope of understanding scientifically all those
In this way, the rules of the language . . . need not be learned once by the ear human mental processes that involve language in any important degree . To
and again by the tongue . This is a theory of a language user, not of a speaker or [pers�vere] means to face the enormously difficult, if not actually impossible, task
a listener alone . . . . of finding a place for normative rules in a descriptive science .
A listener' s first [attempt to interpret the speech Signal] probably derives in Difficult, yes. Still one wonders whether these alternatives are really as mutu­
part from syntactic markers in the form of intonation, inflection, suffixes, etc . , ally exclusive as they have been made to seem.
and in part from his general knowledge of the semantic and situational context. The first thing we notice when we survey the languages of the world is how
Syntactic cues indicate how the input is to be grouped and which words function few we can understand and how diverse they all seem. Not until one looks for
together; semantic and contextual contributions are more difficult to characterize, some time does an even more Significant observation emerge concerning the per­
but must somehow enable him to limit the range of possible words that he can vasive similarities in the midst of all this diversity.
expect to hear. . . . With an advance hypothesis about what the message will be, Every human group that anthropologists have studied has spoken a language .
we can tune our perceptual system to favour certain interpretations and reject The language always has a lexicon and a grammar . The lexicon is not a haphaz­
others . . . . ard collection of vocalizations, but is highly organized; it always has pronouns,
I have already offered the opinion that productivity sets the central problem means for dealing with time, space, and number, words to represent true and
for the psycholinguist and have referred to it indirectly by arguing that we can false, the basic concepts necessary for propositional logiC. The grammar has dis­
produce too many different sentences to store them all in memory. . . . Original tinguishable levels of structure, some phonological, some syntactic. The phono­
combinations of elements are the lifeblood of language . It is our ability to pro­ logy always contains both vowels and consonants, and the phonemes can always be
duce and comprehend such novelties that makes language so ubiquitously useful . described in terms of distinctive features drawn from a limited set of possibilities .
As psychologists have become more seriously interested in the cognitive processes The syntax always specifies rules for grouping elements sequentially into phrases
that language entails, they have been forced to recognize that the fundamental and sentences, rules governing normal intonation, rules for transforming some types
puzzle is not our ability to associate vocal noises with perceptual objects, but rather of sentences into other types.
our combinatorial productivity - our ability to understand an unlimited diversity The nature and importance of these common properties, called 'linguistic uni­
of utterances never heard before and to produce an equal variety of utterances versals' , are only beginning to emerge as our knowledge of the world's languages
similarly intelligible to other members of our speech community . . . . grows more systematiC (Greenberg, 1 96 3 ) . These universals appear even in lan­
As psychologists have learned to appreciate the complexities of language, the guages that developed with ·a minimum of interaction. One is forced to assume,
prospect of reducing it to the laws of behaviour so carefully studied in lower therefore, either that (a) no other kind of linguistic practices are conceivable, or
animals has grown increasingly remote. We have been forced more and more into that (b) something in the biological makeup of human beings favours languages
a position that non-psychologists probably take for granted , namely, that language having these similarities. Only a moment's reflection is needed to reject (a) . When
1 44 E XT E N S I O N T H E EVO L U T I O N O F S P E E C H 1 45

George A. one considers the variety of artificial languages developed in mathematics, in the THE EVOLUTION O F SPEECH
M ill e r communication sciences, in the use of computers, in symbolic logic, and else­
Three contrasting views can be taken of how speech and language evolved.
where, it soon becomes apparent that the universal features of natural languages Ib U l baek
" "'

are not the only ones possible . Natural languages are, in fact, rather special and
often seem unnecessarily complicated. a Evolution of the brain and body
A popular belief regards human language as a more or less free creation of Human beings came to need a sophisticated form of communication because they
the human intellect, as if its elements were chosen arbitrarily and could be com­ began to live in societies. Consequently, their brains and vocal apparatus evolved
bined into meaningful utterances by any rules that strike our collective fancy. The to support this survival need. After many generations, they evolved a capacity for
assumption is implicit, for example, in Wittgenstein' s well-known conception of language which is innate i.e. is transmitted at birth.
'the language game ' . This metaphor, which casts valuable light on many . aspects
of language, can if followed blindly lead one to think that all linguistic rules are b Evolution of language
just as arbitrary as, say, the rules of chess or football. As Lenneberg ( 1 960) has Language began with simple noises to express pleasure, pain, etc. It gradually evolved
pointed out, however, it makes a great deal of sense to inquire into the bio­ in ways that reflected how the human brain operates and the possibilities and limita­
logical basis for language, but very little to ask about the biological foundations tions of the human vocal apparatus. As societies became more and more sophisticated,
11 so did language. There were slow evolutionary modifications to the brain and the vocal
of card games .
Man is the only animal to have a combinatorially productive language . In the apparatus in order to accommodate these new demands.
jargon of biology, language is ' a species-specific form of behaviour' . Other animals
have signalling systems of various kinds and for various purposes - but only man c The 'big bang'
has evolved this particular and highly improbable form of communication. Those Language came about when human brain evolution took a lucky direction and we
who think of language as a free and spontaneous intellectual invention are also developed an innate language faculty.
likely to believe that any animal with a brain sufficiently large to support a high
level of intelligence can acquire a language. This assumption is demonstrably false. Which view do you take and why? Consider the different timescales of evolutionary [0 Activity I
The human brain is not just an ape brain enlarged; its extra size is less important change and of linguistic change.
than its different structure . Moreover, Lenneberg ( 1 962) has pointed out that
nanocephalic dwarfs, with brains half the normal size but grown on the human This article presents an overview of some issues in language evolution. In reading it,
blueprint, can use language reasonably well, and even [Down' s Syndrome suffer­ try to establish clearly:
ers , unable] to perform the simplest functions for themselves, can acquire the rudi­
What is the writer's position on the evolution of language?
m�nts . Talking and understanding language do not depend on being intelligent or
2 What is the writer's view of animal cognition?
having a large brain. They depend on 'being human' .
3 Why, according to the writer, have animals not developed language?

Glossary The origin of language and cognition


cognitive: involving the processes of thought and reasoning.
generative rules: a set of principles which enable a language user to produce (and to Ib Ulbaek (in J. R. Hurford, Studdert-Kennedy, M. and Knight, C. (eds) Approaches to the Evolution
understand) all possible grammatical sentences of a language. of Language, Cambridge: Cambridge U n iversity Press, 1 998. Abridged with permission of the
Obvious as this conclusion may seem . . . : Miller argues that a view of language as author).

governed by rules suggests a normative approach to psycholinguistic research, an


approach which assumes that human behaviour follows highly consistent patterns and Two kinds of theories have dominated recent discussion of the origin of language
can be accounted for by a general theory. We can contrast this with the empirical (see Pinker & Bloom 1 990) : a continuity approach and its counterpart, a discon­
approach preferred by natural scientists, which draws upon concrete evidence and aims tinuity approach. The continuity approach has often labelled itself Darwinian and
to attribute causes to results without any presuppositions. One alternative suggested looked for predecessors Clf language, typically in animal communication systems.
is a phenomenological approach based on observation of events, with no conclusions It claims that language is such a big system that it could not have evolved out of
reached as to external causes and influences. nothing (de novo) . Just as we cannot conceive of the eye jumping into existence,
nanocephalic: with a smaller brain than normal. so we cannot conceive of language as having no precursors.

You might also like