You are on page 1of 10

Are There Counterexamples to Aesthetic Theories of Art?

Nick Zangwill

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 60, No. 2. (Spring, 2002), pp. 111-118.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8529%28200221%2960%3A2%3C111%3AATCTAT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-J

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism is currently published by The American Society for Aesthetics.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/tasfa.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Tue Jul 31 23:43:43 2007
NICK ZANGWILL

Are There Counterexamples to


Aesthetic Theories of Art?

Do all works of art have an aesthetic purpose? It aesthetic properties are those possessed by
is not particularly controversial that many works works of art or that they are those it is the func-
of art have an aesthetic purpose. What will be tion of art to possess. We need an independent
disputed is whether they all do. According to account of aesthetic properties. My view is that
aesthetic theories of art, having an aesthetic pur- aesthetic properties should be delineated with
pose makes a thing art. It will be said that the reference to beauty and ugliness. Beauty and ug-
trouble with aesthetic theories of art is that there liness are the central aesthetic properties, and
seem to be works of art with no aesthetic pur- other properties are aesthetic if they stand in a
pose. Most aestheticians in the last few decades particular intimate relation to beauty and ugli-
have thought it is obvious that there are clear ness. Daintiness, dumpiness, elegance, balance,
counterexamples to aesthetic theories, and so and delicacy are so related, unlike nonaesthetic
they think that such views are easily shown to be properties. Daintiness, dumpiness, elegance,
false. I shall begin by arguing that this rests on a balance, and delicacy are all ways of being
hasty view of one kind of counterexample, and a beautiful or ug1y.J
methodologically nai've approach to another. I
then consider different notions of art, and I end I. AVANT-GARDE COUKTEREXAMPLES
with some reflections on methodology in the
philosophy of art. Aesthetic theories emerge Aestheticians, art-historians, critics, and to a
looking fit and healthy. lesser extent artists sometimes complain that
Let me say a little about aesthetic theories of aesthetic considerations do not play a particu-
art, so that we have something substantial to larly significant role in the production of many
work with. For the purposes of this discussion, works of art, especially those of the twentieth
we can take such theories to span a family of dif- century.5 Many artists, we are told, eschew any
ferent theories. But all such theories have two interest in the aesthetic. Are aesthetic theories of
components.1 The first component is the claim art out of date? Are they out of touch with the
that it is the function of art to have certain aes- avant-garde? Are they a hangover from a past
thetic properties in virtue of certain nonaesthetic era, when perhaps they were true of most or all
properties. That function is determined in part art?
by the maker's intentions.2 Nature possesses Aesthetic theorists can concede that works of
aesthetic properties, but nature does not have the art have important nonaesthetic purposes. For
function of possessing them. The second com- example, they often have important religious
ponent is an account of aesthetic properties. Dif- purposes. The claim is that having some aes-
ferent aesthetic theories of art deploy different thetic function is a necessary and sufficient con-
accounts of aesthetic properties. For example, dition of being a work of art. But having a spe-
Monroe Beardsley's aesthetic theory of art cific aesthetic function may only be a necessary
rested on a very specific dispositional view of condition of being some particular work of art,
aesthetic properties,3 while other aesthetic theo- and there may be other nonaesthetic necessary
ries of art deploy different accounts of aesthetic conditions for being a particular work.6
properties. Obviously, we should not say that However, it will be argued that this conces-
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 60:2 Spring 2002
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

sion does not save aesthetic theories, because restrict the range of aesthetic theories of art. The
the aesthetic should not be among even the nec- thesis could be restricted to the vast majority of
essary conditions for being a work of art. Many works of art that have an aesthetic point. So aes-
works, it will be said, have absolutely no aes- thetic theories of art hold only of those works of
thetic purpose. But that some works of art have art that were created in part for aesthetic rea-
absolutely no aesthetic purpose is quite another sons. Such a theory covers most works of art,
matter from admitting that many works of art and perhaps we need not worry too much about
have important nonaesthetic purposes. Theorists the minority of works that do not fit. (The role
often slide too easily from the latter claim to the that such aberrant works have been given in re-
former. Furthermore, we should be circumspect cent art theory is wholly disproportionate to
about the thesis that a great many works of art their numbers and importance.7) The claim
have no aesthetic point at all. This is a mythol- would be that if something is a work of art and it
ogy. (One source of this mythology is that peo- has an aesthetic function, then it is necessary
ple take too seriously artists' "manifestos," that it has it, rather than the claim that if some-
which should often be taken no more seriously thing is a work of art then it has some aesthetic
than any other piece of advertising!) For in- function and it is necessary that it has it. The for-
stance, most conceptual art has some aesthetic mer claim, unlike the latter, allows that some
aspiration. Even if the aesthetic is not the most works of art have no aesthetic dimension at all.
important aspect of the work, it is still important Those works of art-if there are any-that lack
and indeed essential that the "concepts" in ques- aesthetic functions obviously do not necessarily
tion are embodied in aesthetically significant have aesthetic functions; but it is still the case
ways. There is room for scepticism about how that those works of art that have aesthetic func-
much conceptual art is purely conceptual. More- tions necessarily have them. This is the "retreat"
over, contrary to many art theorists, the ten- strategy.
dency of some visual artists to pursue b. Alternatively, we might say that those
"non-objectual" works of art, such as installa- works of art that lack aesthetic functions-if
tions or earthworks, has nothing to do with a re- there are any-do so necessarily. This has con-
jection of the aesthetic. For example, Robert siderable plausibility, because many of the
Smithson's "Spiral Jetty" has plenty of formal works in question-such as Duchamp's Foun-
aesthetic values. tain and L. H.0 . 0 . Q.-involve a conscious re-
It is true that many works of art'are not sup- jection of the aesthetic. They are anti-aesthetic
posed to be "beautiful" in some narrow sense; works. It is necessary that such works lack an
but they are supposed to possess "substantive" aesthetic function. Or perhaps we could say that
aesthetic properties, such as daintiness, dumpi- they have a negative aesthetic function. This is
ness, elegance, delicacy, balance, power, or se- historically appropriate if we consider the irony
renity. The same critics and artists who affect to that one of the failings of Fountain, from
eschew talk of beauty, ugliness, and even aes- Duchamp's point of view, was that quite a few
thetic merit talk liberally of substantive aesthetic people came to admire its sculpted curves and
properties. The aesthetic theorist can claim that gleaming surface, whereas that was not sup-
it is the function of sustaining these aesthetic posed to be the point-or so Duchamp said. Al-
properties that is essential to works of art. But though Duchamp may have been irritated by this
the appeal to these aesthetic properties only reaction, the urinal invited it. Perhaps he should
makes sense if they are thought of as making the have presented something more aesthetically
work beautiful or aesthetically valuable. neutral. This is the "negative" strategy.
However, it will be insisted that in at least c. Do these two responses concede too much?
some cases, such as Duchamp's Fountain and They concede that there are some works of art
L.H. 0 . 0 . Q., we have a complete rejection of all without a positive aesthetic function, and that
aesthetic properties-including substantive aes- seems to be a problem for aesthetic theories if
thetic properties. Here are three strategies that they are supposed to be entirely general theories
the aesthetic theorist can use to circumvent these of art. A less concessive line would be to say
residual cases. that works such as Fountain and L.H.O.O.Q. in-
a. A somewhat defeatist strategy would be to directly involve aesthetic functions. Although
Zangwill Are There Counterexamples to Aesthetic Theories of Art? 113

such works have no immediate aesthetic func- not. Just as a work of art need not succeed in
tion, their point lies in the fact that they are performing its aesthetic functions, so not all in-
meant to be seen in the context of, and by con- stances of an art form need share the usual func-
trast with, traditional works of art. They indi- tion of works of the art form. Consider that few
rectly involve the aesthetic functions of those would think that the waxworks at Madame
other works. It could not be the case that all Tussaud's are works of art. But how are they
works are like Fountain and L.H.O.O.Q. The different from Hanson's sculptures? It seems to
point of such works depends on the viewer be important that Hanson's figures are intended
being someone who has knowledge of conven- for exhibition in the contexts where we normally
tional works of art. Duchamp wanted Fountain see sculptures. They are deviant sculptures, or
to have no aesthetic point only because he extreme cases of sculptures of a certain sort, and
wanted it to contrast with those works of art that we are meant to see them as such.8 So, as with
did. The point of L.H.O.O. Q. would be lost on Duchamp's Fountain and L. H. 0 . 0 . Q., it is only
someone who did not know the Mona Lisa. because there are other works of art that have
Duchamp' s Fountain and L. H. 0 . 0 . Q. are sec- aesthetic functions that Hanson's sculptures can
ond-order works; and second-order works re- lack them. So Hanson's sculptures are sec-
quire first-order works. Nonaesthetic works are ond-order works after all. (Ironically, the appeal
second-order works that make no sense except to indiscernible counterparts in this case helps
in the context of other works. They are parasitic the aesthetic theorist.)
works, and they are parasitic on aesthetic works I am not entirely sure about how effective
of art. Although Fountain and L.H. 0 . 0 . Q. have these defensive strategies are. Much of the time I
no aesthetic functions themselves, their func- find them convincing-but I can imagine others
tions involve the aesthetic functions of the not being convinced. Nevertheless, given the ir-
works in the context of which they are meant to ritatingly dogmatic and simple-minded way that
be considered. In this respect they are like forg- many aestheticians assert that avant-garde works
eries. The aesthetic functions of other works are are unproblematic refutations of aesthetic theo-
essential to the functions of the parasitic works. ries of art, I would be showing great self-
This is the "second-order" strategy. restraint if I merely replied that it is not obvious
that such theories cannot defend themselves
There are some works that are difficult to inter- against this charge. It is in fact absolutely certain
pret according to either the negative or sec- that such works do not provide an absolutely cer-
ond-order strategies. One interesting artist in tain refutation of aesthetic theories of art, as is so
this respect is Duane Hanson. His "hyper-real- often alleged. Moreover, the negative and sec-
ist" sculptures neither seem to have a negative ond-order accounts of many of these aberrant
point, nor do they seem to be second-order, like works do more justice to their actual nature than
Duchamp's appropriations. Hanson's sculpture the account given by those who seek to conscript
seems to be an extreme case of pure meaning them willy-nilly in the service of their ideologi-
without any aesthetic aspiration, or even cal campaign against aesthetic theories of art.
anti-aesthetic aspiration. Hanson's sculptures
are disturbing while offering a kind of dignity to 11. THE NARRATIVE ARTS
his subjects. But it is hard to see how they have
an aesthetic point. Moreover, Hanson's work However, there is potentially a more trouble-
does not seem to be second-order, like Du- some and mainstream range of counterexamples.
champ's appropriations. In this respect, Hanson What about narrative arts, such as novels, plays,
was more radical than Duchamp. and films? Poems have some aspects that are of
A reply, which has some plausibility, is that aesthetic significance. The precise words used
Hanson's works are sculpture, and as such are can be aesthetically important, either as pure
an instance of a sort of things that has an essen- sound or as the aesthetically apt expression of a
tial aesthetic function. Hanson's sculptures are certain meaning.9 But it is not plausible that nov-
meant to be seen as sculptures. But sculptures els, plays, and films always have significant aes-
generally do have essential aesthetic functions, thetic aspects. There is often a purely visual
even though Hanson's unusual sculptures do aesthetic in films and performances of plays, but
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

its importance is often not central.10 And even if mingled together. In the latter case, we cannot
there are some films and performances of plays disentangle the meaning from the aesthetic as-
that have significant visual aesthetic virtues pect; so we cannot separate them as two inde-
(Passolini's wonderful films Medea and Oed- pendent sources of the value of the work, which
ipus Rex, for example), there are many others in have no connection with each other. But
which such aesthetic aspects are insignificant. It whether or not the aesthetic and narrative pur-
is the same with the poetic qualities of the lan- poses are entangled in this way, aesthetic theo-
guage used in plays and films. In some plays and ries of art are secure so long as there are some
films it is aesthetically important. The use of lan- aesthetic purposes in play. The problematic
guage may be beautiful or elegant. But in others, cases with only narrative content are not like
this is not so. There are plays and films in which this. They have no aesthetic point at all, which
what we see and hear is only dramatically impor- seems to be bad news for aesthetic theories.
tant; it is not beautiful or elegant as pure form or Given the existence of purely narrative works,
as the aesthetically apt embodiment of a certain what then is left of a general aesthetic theory of
narrative meaning. (Ordinary horror movies are art?
examples.) It seems that there are arts of pure
narrative meaning. In these arts, what is impor- 111. CONCEPTS OF ART
tant is the story.
So if we say that works of art are necessarily At this point we need to reflect on our goals in
things that have an aesthetic point, then it seems the philosophy of art, and of our mode of achiev-
that some narrative works will fall outside the ing those goals. Aesthetic theories of art succeed
bounds of art. Similarly, some performance art in capturing the essential truth about a large
may fall into the class of works with meaning range of the objects and events in the category of
but no aesthetic point. And perhaps there are art. But they seem not to capture the truth about
some purely conceptual works that I have over- them all. How should we react to this? On my
looked that make no attempt to have an aestheti- view, it is not at all obvious that we must say that
cally interesting visual or aural aspect and that aesthetic theories are false because they suffer
are not meant to be seen as aberrant works of an- counterexamples. I do not think we are forced to
other sort. Of course, in such cases, the visual or react to the purely narrative arts in this way.
aural presentation of meaning is important. The Another reaction would be to say that the
narrative content must be realized in visually or "folk" category of art has an error built into it.
aurally significant ways. But perhaps the signifi- Stephen Stich argued that we might find out that
cance of the visual or aural presentation of con- although Folk Psychology presupposes that
tent is not always of aesthetic significance. To there is one kind of state underlying a variety of
recall, I take aesthetic significance to be either a kinds of behavior, in fact it turns out that there
matter of beauty and ugliness or of features such are two or more distinct kinds of underlying
as daintiness, dumpiness, and elegance, which state.]' And Jaegwon Kim says that our notion
make a thing beautiful or ugly. I thereby assume of jade in fact picks out two superficially similar
perhaps a rather restrictive notion of the aes- but different natural kinds. Jade is a disjunction
thetic. But I think that we need such a notion if of jadite and nephrite.]-o we need an error the-
the notion of the aesthetic is not to become vacu- ory of our folk concept of jade. Jade is not a uni-
ous and the interesting issues dissipated. Given fied natural kind as Folk Geology presumes.
such a nonvacuous notion of the aesthetic, it is Similarly, maybe there is an error built into the
plausible that there are some works of art that folk concept of art, because falling under that
have no aesthetic functions. 1 ' concept there are two different kinds of phe-
It is only when there are narrative meanings nomena (with an overlap)-things that have aes-
without an aesthetic point that there is trouble thetic functions, and things that have narrative
for aesthetic theories of art. When there are aes- functions. Maybe art is like jade. Perhaps art is a
thetic purposes as well as meanings, then the disjunctive kind: works of art either have an aes-
works are not works of pure meaning, and there thetic point or a narrative point (or some combi-
is no problem. In these cases, either the aesthetic nation of the two). Or perhaps there is more of a
and narrative purposes are separate or they are continuum-with absolute music and abstract
Zangwill Are There Counterexamples to Aesthetic Theories of Art? 115

painting at one end; representational paintings because they are being taught a piece of theory,
and operas in the middle; then poetry; with nov- not something they knew all along." It is the
els, plays, and films at the other end. same with the notion of "art" in aesthetics
The possibility that "art" is like "jade" is no courses. There is no pretheoretic notion that stu-
mere abstract possibility. Peter Kivy has drawn dents are recollecting or making explicit. In-
attention to the fact that our concept of "Fine stead they are imbibing and internalizing the
Art" has its origin in the "Modern System of the ideology of the Modem System of the Arts,
Arts," which canonized certain art forms in the which is embodied in the notion of Fine Art. The
eighteenth century.13 At that time, a number of idea that students are drawing on a neutral folk
artistic activities were for the first time concep- concept, which they already possess, and which
tually grouped together and deemed the "Fine can be analyzed at leisure, is an illusion. Instead,
Arts" or simply "The Artsn-painting, sculp- the students are being subtly indoctrinated.
ture, architecture, poetry, music. That concept (Conceptual analysis as ideology.)
had a certain extension. It included both the aes- We might call the high-fallutin concept of
thetic and the narrative arts. That concept is the Fine Art the "bourgeois" concept of art (which I
one that is deployed in contemporary philoso- do not take to have pejorative overtones). If the
phy (in courses and textbooks). But need we bourgeois concept of art is not the most common
have our hands tied by that concept?l" folk concept of art,there is no reason for us to
If we are not to use the concept of Fine Art, contemplate an error theory about most of the
then we might wonder what other concept we folk because of the diversity of things that fall
should use. Perhaps we should use a more ev- under the bourgeois concept. And if the bour-
eryday concept of art, which contrasts with the geois concept is not the most common folk
notion of Fine Art. The trouble is that it is not concept, we do not have to worry about
obvious what our ordinary folk notion is. It is counterexamples to aesthetic theories of art that
not obvious that there is such a folk notion. stem from the fact that there are things that are
One common use of "art" just means a art according to the bourgeois concept that are
skill-but the philosopher's use is more restric- not art according to aesthetic theories. Of
tive than that. Another common use of "art" just course, the bourgeoisie are themselves folk. (I
means visual art-but the philosopher's use is am one of them.) But the bourgeois concept of
more general than that. Some, but not all, dictio- art is not very widespread. We should hold an
naries list the high-fallutin philosophical use of error theory about the bourgeois concept of art,
"the arts" that includes literature, music, and the because the things it groups together have no
visual arts. But that high-fallutin concept is not a common nature. But this error theory is modest
common concept deployed by many ordinary and restricted. The folk, or at least most of the
folk. That concept is one deployed by those who English-speaking folk, are not in error. I am not
accept the theory implicitly embodied in the sure about the extent to which speakers of other
Modem System of the Arts, and those who de- languages have words that select all and only
ploy that concept may buy into the values that those arts (in the skill sense) that are canonized
that concept presupposes.16 in the Modern System of the Arts.18 If they do,
The disconcerting fact is that there is no com- perhaps the folk who use those words in those
mon folk concept of art that we must respect. It languages are in systematic error when they de-
is simply not true that English-speaking folk use ploy those words, and my error theory would
the English word "art" to pick out the arts that then be less modest and restricted than it is in re-
were selected in the Modern System of the Arts spect of English-speaking folk. I leave this as an
or those arts that tend to be covered in philoso- open question, although I must admit to some
phy of art courses and textbooks. Many dictio- default skepticism about whether very many of
naries list no such usage. (A philosopher's opin- those folk have such a concept.19
ion about what the folk think is often an
expedient mythology.) Gilbert Harman notes the 1V. METHODOLOGICAL REFLECTIONS
way philosophy instructors have to teach stu-
dents to make the analyticlsynthetic distinction. In all this it is crucial to remember that what we
It does not come naturally to them. And that is are interested in when we reflect on art is not a
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

concept but a range of puzzling objects and of Scottishness. The real question is: which no-
events and a range of puzzling attitudes to those tion slzould we deploy? (This issue has recently
objects and events." We need to understand come to the fore now that there are different
these phenomena. It is an open question how funding rules for Scottish and English students.)
much in common there will be in some grouping Those who would rest with conceptual analysis
of these phenomena. The eighteenth-century are complacent here as they are elsewhere. Per-
Modern System of the Arts does violence to the haps there could be reasons to cultivate a notion
nature of the things that it classifies together. of a Scotsman from which it does turn out that
The items on the list of the Modem System of all Scotsmen wear kilts! That might be a useful
the Arts should be viewed as more heteroge- notion of a Scotsman for other reasons. Simi-
neous than has been thought. So a theory of art larly, given the virtues of the aesthetic theory of
that applies to many but not all of the items on art, a "No True Scotsman" style of argument
the list may be unobjectionable. may on balance be a good move.
Furthermore, on my view we need a theory of What we are in search of is a good theory of
art that includes items that the Modern System the nature of art. This issue does not concern the
of Arts excludes. For example, I am keen to word "art" or the category or the concept of art.
have a notion that includes painting, music, ar- We want to know about a range of objects and
chitecture, and some literature, and which also events, not about the words or concepts that we
includes everyday creative activities such as in- use to talk about those things. We are interested
dustrial design, advertising, weaving, whistling, in objects, not concepts-the world, not words.
cake-decorating, arranging and decorating We are doing metaphysics, not linguistic or con-
rooms, religious rituals, and fireworks d i s ceptual analysis. Indeed, the task of defining art,
plays.?' The fact that the items that the aesthetic so popular for so long, is clearly a category mis-
theory includes and excludes do not coincide take, unless "defining" is meant in the sense of
with the items that the Modem System of the "real definition." (In any ordinary sense of defi-
Arts includes and excludes is of little conse- nition, we might try to define "art" but not art.) I
quence. suspect that many aestheticians hanker after the
Am I flagrantly committing what is known as project of conceptual analysis. If we need to re-
the "No True Scotsman" fallacy'? (Someone of- fashion concepts in order to understand things,
fers the generalization that all Scotsmen wear then so be it. We want to understand the nature
kilts; someone else points out Hamish, who is of a range of things, not gaze at our own concep-
Scottish but who seems not to be wearing a kilt; tual navels.
to this, the original person replies that Hamish is Someone might object: how are we to know
"no true Scotsman," thus apparently saving the which things are the things we want a theory of?
generalization.) Am I just dismissing counter- Surely, it will be argued, at this point we have to
examples to aesthetic theories of art in an ad hoc think about words or concepts, for we are inter-
way merely to save my theory? But the analogy ested in the nature of the things that we typically
is somewhat illuminating. I have tried to pick out with the word "art" or to which we usu-
"problematize" the notion of art. But the con- ally apply the concept of art. However, a warn-
cept of a Scot is also problematic. Who is a Scot, ing light should go on whenever a philosopher
and in what does being a Scot consist? Must one uses the word "we" in this way. It is a reliable
have been born in Scotland? Brought up in Scot- indicator of a rhetorical move. The objection as-
land? Educated in Scotland? Identify in some sumes that there is some universally shared con-
way with Scotland? For all but the blindest na- cept and some kind of consensus in its applica-
tionalist, the notion of a Scot is problematic. tion. But there is no such universally shared
Similarly problematic is the notion of art, for all concept and no such consensus. Furthermore,
but the blindest adherent of the Modern System even if there were, the question is not what con-
of the Arts. Maybe the folk notion of a Scot is cept or concepts of art we have, but what con-
oversimplistic or even based on an error. (Ac- cept or concepts we need given the natures of a
cording to Anthony Smith, all national identities wide range of human artifacts. Those artifacts
are based on myths about the past.22) There may have natures independent of our conceptualiza-
even be different and incompatible folk notions tion, and our job as theorists is to track those na-
Zangwill Are There Counterexarnples to Aesthetic Theories of Art? 117

tures in our theories and concepts. Common folk a nature common to a great many things, why
concepts or more erudite concepts that are al- not reach out for it?25
ready in circulation may or may not be what we
need.23 NICK ZANGWILL
It seems that what counts as the target for ex- Department of Philosophy
planation in the theory of art is somewhat shift- University of Glasgow
ing. To some extent, we must set up the target Glasgow, Scotland G I 2 8QQ
and then shoot at it. So long as the aesthetic the-
ory succeeds in giving the essence of a great
many art forms, I do not think that we should
worry too neurotically about whether it covers I. I give a full account of my preferred aesthetic theory of
every item in the Modern System of the Arts. I art in my "The Creati~eTheory of Art." American Philo-
maintain that if we draw a circle around most of ~ophical Quarterly 32 (1995):123-148, and "Aesthetic
Functionalism," in Ae.stlletic Concepts: E.\tuyc After Sibley,
the traditional arts (painting, sculpture. architec- ed. Emily Brady and Jerrold Levinson (Oxford: Oxford Uni-
ture, music, and poetry). together with the sort versity Press. 200 1 ).
of everyday creative activities that I mentioned. 2. Two comments: ( 1) the appeal tofiinctions means that
we get an interesting grouping. We get a class of works of art do not necessarily succeed in possessing the
aesthetic properties that it is their function to possess:
things with an interesting unifying princi-
works can fail to fulfill their purpose, at least to some de-
ple-the one given by the aesthetic theory. On gree. (2) I assume that works of art have positive aesthetic
the other hand, if we retain the traditional five functions, though I suppose we can imagine someone delib-
arts in the Modern System of the Arts, exclude erately trying to make something ugly for some further pur-
the everyday cases, and add those novels, plays. pose.
3. Monroe Beardsley, "An Aesthetic Definition of Art."
and films that are purely narrative, then the aes- in What Is Art? ed. Hugh Curtler (New York: Haven. 1983).
thetic is no longer a unifying principle. And See also William Tolhurst, "Towards an Aesthetic Theory of
there is no other, so far as I can see.23 Art," The Jorrrn~ilqfAecthetict and Art Criticitnz 42 (1984):
I am skeptical about the possibility of provid- 26 1-269.
4. See my "The Beautiful. The Dainty and the Dumpy,"
ing an entirely general theory of the nature of art
The British Journal ofAesrhetics 35 (1995), and "The Con-
in the sense of providing a theory of the nature cept of the Aesthetic," European Journal of Philosophy 6
of all and only the items in the Modern System (1998): (both also in The Met~ip1~j.sic.sof Beatih [Ithaca,
of the Arts. I do not think that this is something NY: Cornell University Press, 20011, pp. 9-23 and 24-42).
we should aspire to do. However. we should not 5. For example, see the writings of Arthur Danto. George
Dickie, and many sociological and continental Theorists.
lurch from one extreme to the other. Some re- 6. Stephen Davies put forward the suggestion that " . . .
cent writers in the philosophy of art. such as the aesthetic character [of art] must be relevant to its serving
Kivy, have been concerned to proselytize in the main purpose at which it is a i m e d (Southern Jorrrn~ilof
favor of the quest for differences among the arts. Pllilosophj 35 [1997]: 29). This is an interesting suggestion.
but I fear it may be overstrict.
They resist any attempt to impose a unified the-
7. The idea that the philosophy of art should turn on such
ory of the nature and value of art. They worry trivial, tedious. and transitory artists as Claus Oldenburg or
that such a theory will not be able to do justice to Robert Rauschenberg is surely laughable.
the differences among the arts. While I think 8. On deviant properties of works within an established
that there is something to be said for this, I also art form, see Kendall Walton, "Categories of Art." Pllilo-
s o ~ ~ l ~ i Review
cal 79 (1970). He calls such properties "con-
think it can be taken too far. Down that path lies tra-standard" properties. See my discussion, "In Defence of
a kind of anarchy of the individual case that pre- Aesthetic Formalism," Pllilosopllical Quurterlj 50 (2000):
cludes the understanding that finding something 334-367 (also in The Metapllysicc of Beciuh [Cornell Uni-
in common yields. The aesthetic theory of art versity Press, 20011, pp. 476493).
provides such an understanding of a wide range 9. See section 4 of my "Feasible Aesthetic Formalism,"
N o h 33 (1999) (also in The Metaphj.~icsof Beciuh, pp.
of things. It provides an account of the nature of 69-72).
those things, as well as providing the basis for 10. The film The English Patient, for example, had some
an explanation of our interest in those things, visual virtues, but it was flawed in so many other respects
and of the actions and institutions that sustain that its purely visual aesthetic virtues did little to redeem it.
1 1. See further my "AestheticISensory Dependence." The
them. We should not allow pessimism about British J o ~ ~ r n aqfAettherics
l 38 (1998): 66-85 (also in The
general theories to derail such a theory. If there Met~ip1~y.sic.s of Beauty. pp. 127-145). It might be argued
is an aesthetic theory close to hand that captures that the narrative arts possess substantive aesthetic proper-
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

ties, such as power, balance, elegance. or delicacy. But in There is some justice to the complaints of the sociologically
that paper I argue that such descriptions may not be aesthetic minded that such groupings are evaluatively and politically
descriptions, and that when they deploy typically aesthetic loaded. (See Pierre Bourdieu. Distinction [London:
words (such as "elegance" or "beauty"), their use may be Routledge & Kegan Paul, 19841.) What is deemed "high" or
metaphorical. "fine" art is thereby given a higher value than what is ex-
12. Stephen Stich, From Folk P.\xchology to Cogiziti~,e cluded. I firmly reject reductionist sociological approaches
Science (MIT Press, 1983), p. 23 1. to general theorizing about art (see my "The Creative The-
13.Jaegwon Kim. "Multiple Realization and the ory of Art" and "Art and Audience," The Jo~~rizcil ofAesthet-
Metaphysics of Reduction," in S~~pemenience cind Mind icc and Art Criticisni 57 [1999]: 315-332). But I have to
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). agree that these sociological theorists are sometime.\ right
14. Peter Kivy. Philotophies of the Arts: An Essay in Dd- about those distinctions.
fercvzcec (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). 20. See further my "Groundrules in the Philosophy of
15. Paul Kristeller describes the way the arts were Art." Philosophy 70 ( 1995): 533-544.
grouped completely differently in ancient Greece and in the 21. For discussion of the status of "non-Western" art, see
Renaissance in his "The Modern System of the Arts," in Stephen Davies. "Non-Western Art and Art's Definition."
Paul Kristeller, Renaissance Thorrght and the Arts (New and Denis Dutton, "'But They Don't Have Our Concept of
York: Harper & Row. 1965). A shortened version of this Art'," both in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noel Carroll (Uni-
essay can be found in Aesthetics, ed. Susan Feagin and Pat- versity of Wisconsin Press. 2000).
rick Maynard (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1997). This 22. See. for example, Anthony Smith. The Ethnic origin.^
makes salutary reading. In Japan, there is a high art cate- ofNutions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).
gory-"the road"-that includes calligraphy. some martial 23. Walter Gropius writes: "There is a widespread heresy
arts, flower arranging. incense, and the tea ceremony. that art is just a useless luxury. This is one of our fatal lega-
16. Francis Sparshott describes the way that dance came cies from a generation which arbitrarily elevated some of its
to be thought of as one of the Fine Arts when it was not pre- branches above the rest as the 'Fine Arts,' and in so doing
viously so classified (in Off the Grotind [Princeton Univer- robbed all of their basic identity and common life. . . . By de-
sity Press, 19881). He also th~nksthat some dance is "art" priving handicrafts and industry of the informing services of
and some is not. He addresses the question of what marks the artist the academies drained them of their vitality, and
this distinction (ibid., p. 269). The general account he offers brought about the artist's complete isolation from the com-
is in terms of "appreciation" (ibid.. p. 274). As he sees it. this munity." Gropius, The New Architectrrre cind the Bcilrhaus
means that he cannot avoid blurring the boundaries between (MIT Press. 1965). pp. 57-58. Gropius is someone who con-
dance and other activities rarely considered "art." such as rit- tests the notion of Fine Art. See also Miller, The Garden as
uals, ceremonies, martial arts. many kinds of sport. cin Art, chap. 4.
bullfighting, cheerleading, and parades. This blurring is a 24. Someone might suggest that something like Kant's
good thing. on my view. Mara Miller describes the fall of the idea of pleasures of the imagination is a mental act that is the
garden from Fine Art status (in The Garden as an Arr appropriate response to all the items in the Modern System
[SUNY Press, 19931). She also addresses the "art" status of of the Arts. But this is a vain hope, for that mental act is also
gardens. and finds the notion of Fine Art wanting. appropriately exercised in response to the everyday creative
17. Gilbert Harman. Reasoning. Meaning cind Mind (Ox- activities I listed.
ford: Clarendon, 1999). p. 142. 25. This paper was presented at the American Society for
18. Perhaps the German word kunst expresses such a no- Aesthetics National Meeting, Reno. Nevada, in October
tion. 2000. I am grateful for questions from those present in the
19. I am not interested in characterizing "high" or "fine" audience and also for comments from Stephen Davies and
art as opposed to more lowly sorts. On my view. the philoso- Alan Goldman.
phy of art should be blind to the high-artllow-art distinction.
http://www.jstor.org

LINKED CITATIONS
- Page 1 of 1 -

You have printed the following article:


Are There Counterexamples to Aesthetic Theories of Art?
Nick Zangwill
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 60, No. 2. (Spring, 2002), pp. 111-118.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8529%28200221%2960%3A2%3C111%3AATCTAT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-J

This article references the following linked citations. If you are trying to access articles from an
off-campus location, you may be required to first logon via your library web site to access JSTOR. Please
visit your library's website or contact a librarian to learn about options for remote access to JSTOR.

[Endnotes]

3
Toward an Aesthetic Account of the Nature of Art
William Tolhurst
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 42, No. 3. (Spring, 1984), pp. 261-269.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8529%28198421%2942%3A3%3C261%3ATAAAOT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C

8
Categories of Art
Kendall L. Walton
The Philosophical Review, Vol. 79, No. 3. (Jul., 1970), pp. 334-367.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108%28197007%2979%3A3%3C334%3ACOA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5

8
Physicalism and the Falacy of Composition
Crawford L. Elder
The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 50, No. 200. (Jul., 2000), pp. 332-343.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8094%28200007%2950%3A200%3C332%3APATFOC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-L

19
Art and Audience
Nick Zangwill
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 57, No. 3. (Summer, 1999), pp. 315-332.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-8529%28199922%2957%3A3%3C315%3AAAA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-2

NOTE: The reference numbering from the original has been maintained in this citation list.

You might also like