You are on page 1of 22

This article was downloaded by: [Flinders University of South Australia]

On: 31 December 2014, At: 13:09


Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954
Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH,
UK

American Journal of Clinical


Hypnosis
Publication details, including instructions for
authors and subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ujhy20

Hypnotic Involuntariness and


the Automaticity of Everyday
Life
a b
Irving Kirsch Ph.D. & Steven Jay Lynn
a
University of Connecticut , USA
b
SUNY Binghamton , USA
Published online: 21 Sep 2011.

To cite this article: Irving Kirsch Ph.D. & Steven Jay Lynn (1997) Hypnotic
Involuntariness and the Automaticity of Everyday Life, American Journal of Clinical
Hypnosis, 40:1, 329-348, DOI: 10.1080/00029157.1997.10403402

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00029157.1997.10403402

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the
information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform.
However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no
representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness,
or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views
expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and
are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the
Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with
primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any
losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages,
and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or
indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the
Content.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes.
Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan,
sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is
expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014
Hypnotic Involuntariness and the Automaticity
of Everyday Life
Irving Kirsch
University of Connecticut

Steven Jay Lynn


SUNY Binghamton
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

We present a new theory of hypnotic involuntariness based on an integration


and extension of recent social and cognitive theories on the automaticity of
mundane, intentional behavior. According to this model, experiences of
volition and involuntariness - in and out of hypnosis - are constructions
or interpretations made possible by the high degree of automaticity that is a
characteristic of all complex behavior, including novel behavior. Suggested
non volitional behaviors are intentional acts that are triggered automatically
by situational cues (suggestions) and cue-related sensations. The triggering of
both the behaviors and the sensations are enabled by the formation of a
generalized response expectancy, which is a cognitive set to respond appro-
priately to suggestions. Response expectancies are functionally equivalent to
implementation intentions taking the form, "emit response x when situation
y is encountered." The classification of a response set as either an expectancy
or an intention and the experience of the response as volitional or nonvolitional
depend on interpretations derived from instructional cues and prior beliefs.

One of the most interesting phenom- litional status of suggested behavior has
ena of hypnosis is an apparent alteration become a source of intense controversy
in volitional control over behavior. In (Kirsch & Lynn, 1995).
response to suggestions, hypnotized in- There are four conventional criteria of
dividuals execute movements that they automaticity (Bargh, 1994). A cognitive
report as having occurred without voli- process or behavioral action is automatic
tional effort (ideomotor responses), and ifit is 1.) outside of awareness, 2.) uncon-
they display a suggested inability to ex- trollable (i.e., it cannot be prevented or
ecute simple motor acts (responses to stopped), 3.) unintentional (i.e., volitional
challenge suggestions). Early theorists effort is not needed for its initiation), and
took these displays at face value and 4.) efficient (i.e., it does not consume
assumed that hypnotic behavior was in attentional resources). At one time, be-
fact involuntary. More recently, the vo- havior was thought to be either controlled
or automatic, the assumption being that
any instance of behavior met either all
For reprints write to: Irving Kirsch, Ph.D., four or none of these criteria. However, it
Department of Psychology, U-20, Univer- later became clear that few, if any, pro-
sity of Connecticut, 406 Babbidge Road,
Storrs, CT 06269-1020. cesses satisfy all four criteria (Bargh,
1994). Thus, the question to be asked is:

329
KIRSCH AND LYNN

To what extent does a particular type of theory, hypnotic inductions release


behavior meet these four criteria of auto- "lower-level functions from the integra-
maticity? tion that is normally imposed on them by
Hypnotic responses occur within consciousness" (Woody & Bowers, 1994,
awareness, and most data indicate that p. 57), resulting in a condition that is
they can be controlled (Lynn, Rhue, & functionally similar to that of patients
Weekes, 1990). The problem, then, is to with frontal lobe disorders. Because of
account for the self-reported feelings of this weakening of frontal lobe control,
involuntariness that accompany the ex- "subsystems of control can be directly
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

ecution or inhibition of movements that and automatically activated, instead of


are normally under voluntary control. being governed by high level executive
Solutions to this problem can begin with control" (Bowers, 1992, p. 267). There are
one of two premises. First, it is possible two major problems with the dissociated
that early theorists were right, that par- control model. First, by postulating a
ticipants have managed to cede control to weakening of frontal control, it requires
the hypnotist and that their responses are that the suggestions be externally admin-
directly activated by external suggestions. istered. Thus, it cannot explain self-hyp-
From this perspective, suggested re- nosis, during which participants adminis-
sponses are viewed as genuinely unin- ter suggestions to themselves. Second, it
tentional and therefore efficient (Bowers, requires the induction of a special state or
1992; Woody & Bowers, 1994). Alter- condition as a prerequisite for the occur-
nately, one could suppose that suggested rence of simple ideomotor responses.
responses are initiated intentionally, but However, hypnotic and non hypnotic sug-
that the person is unaware of that inten- gestibility are very highly correlated, and
tion (Kihlstrom, 1992; Spanos, 1986a, the effect of hypnotic inductions on sug-
1986b). gestibility is surprisingly small (Hull, 1933;
Each of these premises poses a differ- Hilgard & Tart, 1966). This suggests that
ent subsidiary problem. If suggested re- responses to hypnotic and nonhypnotic
sponses are in fact unintentional, how is suggestions are brought about by the
it that these normally voluntary behav- same causal mechanisms and that the
iors come to be activated directly by the induction of a hypnotic state is not one of
hypnotist's suggestions? Conversely, if those mechanisms (Barber, 1969; Hilgard,
the responses are initiated intentionally, 1969; Kihlstrom, 1985; Kirsch & Lynn,
how is it that the participant is unaware of 1995; Sarbin & Coe, 1972). Although typi-
those intentions? Answers to these ques- cally studied in the context of hypnosis,
tions are at the core of three current theo- the responses with which we are con-
ries of hypnosis. These are the theory of cerned can more accurately be character-
dissociated control (Bowers, 1992; ized as suggested, than as hypnotic.
Woody & Bowers, 1994), Hilgard' s (1986, According to neodissociation theory
1994) neodissociation theory, and (Hilgard, 1986; Kihlstrom, 1992), hypno-
Spanos's (l986a, 1986b) social-psycho- tized participants are unaware of inten-
logical theory (see Kirsch & Lynn, 1995, tions and other cognitive contents be-
for a more detailed description of these cause they have erected an amnesic-like
theories). barrier that divides consciousness into
According to dissociated control two parts. The hidden part of conscious-

330 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

ness can initiate and inhibit movements referred to the idea of an unconscious in-
and monitor stimuli of which the remain- tention as an oxymoron.
der of consciousness is unaware. Woody The purpose of this article is to intro-
and Bowers (1994) have identified the duce a new socio-cognitive account of
central problem with the neodissociation suggested involuntariness. In common
explanation of ideomotor and challenge with neodissociation and socio-psycho-
responses - it requires the occurrence of logical theories, we contend that hyp-
unsuggested, arbitrarily selective amne- notic responding is voluntary. In com-
sia. This is problematic because sug- mon with dissociated control theory, how-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

gested amnesia is a relatively difficult ever, we also endorse the seemingly con-
response, of which most hypnotized tradictory proposition that behavioral
people seem incapable (Kirsch, Silva, responses to suggestion are triggered
Corney, & Reed, 1995), and spontaneous automatically. Finally, in common with
amnesia is even less common (Hilgard & social-psychological theory, we regard
Cooper, 1965). In contrast, many simple reports of involuntariness as attributions
ideomotor responses can be experienced or interpretations, rather than introspec-
easily by most people (Kirsch et aI., 1995). tions (Kirsch & Lynn, 1995; Lynn et aI.,
"Hence, we have the unappealing pros- 1990). In contrast to neodissociation and
pect of attempting to explain routine hyp- dissociated control theories, we do not
notic behaviors in terms of a very rare postulate the creation of an amnestic
one" (Woody & Bowers, 1994, p. 55). barrier or the induction of a state of weak-
Spanos's (1986a, 1986b) social-psy- ened frontal control as a prerequisite for
chological account of involuntariness responding. In contrast to previous socio-
begins with the same premise as cognitive formulations, we contend that
neodissociation theory: Hypnotized people's interpretations of their re-
people intentionally produce behavioral sponses as automatic are not entirely
responses, but are not aware of that in- mistaken.
tention. Instead of postulating a division In this article, we first provide an over-
of consciousness, Spanos (1986b) char- view and extension of the burgeoning
acterizes reports of involuntariness as literature on automaticity in the produc-
mistaken attributions about the causes of tion of mundane, intentional behavior
hypnotic behavior. The problem with the (e.g., Bargh & Barndollar, in press;
social-psychological alternative is that it Gollwitzer, 1993; Norman & Shallice, 1986;
does not provide a convincing explana- Vallacher & Wegner, 1987), in which we
tion of how hypnotized individuals are argue that all behavior is instigated auto-
able to misattribute the cause of their matically at the moment of activation. We
responses (cf. Laurence & Gendron, then draw on these theories and on re-
1995). Characterizations of hypnotic re- sponse expectancy theory (Kirsch, 1985,
sponding as involuntary do not just oc- 1990) to formulate answers to the follow-
cur after the fact; they are also made ing questions: I.) How can voluntary
during the act. Ansfield and Wegner actions be interpreted as involuntary
(1996) note that "We all know what it is reactions? 2.) How can novel responses
like to do something...when we do it, we that are normally under voluntary con-
feel we are doing it" (p. 482, emphasis trol be triggered directly by sugges-
in the original). Similarly, Bowers (1992) tion?

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 331


KIRSCH AND LYNN

The Syntax of Action a speed and fluency that would not be


possible were each ofthese actions delib-
The revolution in psycholinguistics erately chosen. We propose that the au-
inaugurated by Chomsky's (1957) theory tomaticity that is inherent in all behavior
of generative grammar is one of the cor- can be understood within a framework
nerstones of contemporary cognitive derived from a synthesis of prior hierar-
psychology. It was propelled by the in- chical schema theories.
sights that human beings are able to pro-
duce and comprehend an infinite number Hierarchical Control
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

of linguistic utterances, that these utter- of Habitual Behavior


ances are formed in compliance with a A frequent assumption in cognitive
complex set of implicit linguistic rules, theories of planned and unplanned be-
and that this infinite variety of highly havior is that actions are controlled by
structured utterances cannot be explained hierarchically organized, interactive, sen-
by stimulus-response habit mechanisms. sorimotor schemas (e.g., Bargh &
The rules are implicit in that they need not Bamdollar, 1996; Hilgard, 1986; Miller,
be consciously known. The use of these Galanter, & Pribrim, 1960; Norman, 1981;
syntactic rules is an automatic process, in Norman & Shallice, 1986). At the top of
that it occurs effortlessly, without aware- this hierarchy is a central control struc-
ness, and unintentionally. Although ture (Hilgard, 1986) or supervisory
many aspects of Chomsky's explanation attentional system (Norman & Shallice,
of linguistic competence are controver- 1986) that selects or biases the selection
sial (Lieberman, 1991), the insights and of the act that is to be performed. It is this
resulting questions on which the theory highest level ofthe hierarchy that is iden-
is based have been widely accepted. tified with consciousness and intention-
A number of theorists have empha- ality. At its most molar level, the selected
sized the degree to which intentional be- act is represented by a parent (Norman,
havior may be controlled automatically 1981) or source (Norman & Shallice, 1986)
(e.g., Bargh, 1994; Bargh & Gollwitzer, schema. The task of a source schema,
1994; Norman & Shallice, 1986), but it is such as driving to a familiar location, is to
generally assumed that for this to occur, activate and monitor the activity of com-
the actions must have become routinized ponent schemas, such as turning left or
or habitual. In this section, we argue that right at specific locations. In turn, each of
there is considerable automaticity in the the component schemas acts as a source
production of novel behavior and that schema for even lower level, subordinate
nonlinguistic, mundane, intentional be- schemas, such as the minor adjustments
havior shares many ofthe characteristics in speed and steering that are required
of language learning and production (see while driving. Once activated, each of
Lewicki, 1986 for a similar extension of these component schemas is capable of
psycholinguistic assumptions to being triggered by particular environmen-
nonconscious social information process- tal stimuli.
ing). What we acquire is not a series of One consequence of the hierarchical
stereotypical habits, but rather, a series control of action is that much of behavior
of competencies to produce an infinite is performed automatically. Because con-
variety of highly structured actions with sciousness is required only in the initial

332 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

selection of the highest level source cues and induce direct (automatic) con-
schema, in the absence of unexpected trol of the intended behavior through
complications, complex acts can be per- these cues" (Gollwitzer, 1993,p. 141).Thus,
formed with little or no awareness, little the intention is formed in advance, rather
drain on attentional resources, and with- than at the time the response is executed.
out intentional activation of the compo- Bargh and Gollwitzer (1994) summarized
nent behaviors. This is adaptive, in that data from a series of studies supporting
by freeing attentional resources, it in- the hypothesis that when a prior imple-
creases our capacity to engage in simul- mentation intention has been formed, "at
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

taneous tasks, such as eating a candy bar the time of behaving, the effect of the
and holding a conversation, while driving triggering environmental features is di-
a car. The cost, however, is that automa- rect and immediate and requires no inter-
ticity increases the probability of vening conscious choice, intention, or
parapraxes or action slips (Reason, 1983). awareness" (p. 73). Nevertheless, the
Deviating from a habitual route, for ex- behavior is classified as intended, be-
ample, may require attention at a critical cause it is goal directed and was preceded
juncture. by the formation of a conscious intention.
In Norman and Shallice' s (1986) model, Gollwitzer's model is consistent with
the role of consciousness is even less Norman and Shallice' s (1986) hypothesis
than that indicated above. Not only are that source schemas are triggered directly
component movements selected directly by environmental stimuli. From the
by environmental triggers, but so too are Norman and Shall ice perspective, the role
source schemas. The role of the supervi- of implementation intentions would be to
sory attentional system is merely to bias bias the selection of intended acts by
the selection of source schemas by in- increasing their activation values.
creasing or decreasing their activation In Gollwitzer' s (1993) model, intentions
values. The degree of conscious atten- prepare behavioral schemas for automatic
tion required to initiate an act varies con- activation, but what about behavior that
siderably, according to this model, and is not activated by a particular cue? Evi-
some acts require no attention at all. Thus, dence for automatic activation of uncued
"getting out of bed in the morning is at behavior can be drawn from two studies
times an automatic act and at other times of the relation between intentional move-
requires great exertion of will" (p. 15). ments and cortical function. Grey Walter
A second account of the way in which (as cited in Dennett, 1991) asked patients
molar acts could be triggered directly by with electrodes implanted in the motor
the environment is provided by cortex to look at slides from a projector
Gollwitzer's (1993) notion of implementa- and to advance to the next slide whenever
tion intentions. An implementation inten- they liked. Unknown to the patients, the
tion is a conscious decision to execute an slides were actually advanced by an am-
act in specified environmental circum- plified signal from the implanted elec-
stance (e.g., "I will turn right, rather than trodes. The reported experience of the
left, when I get to Broad Street"). Accord- patients was that the slides moved just as
ing to Gollwitzer, these intentions "create they were about to push the button, but
a heightened accessibility of the mental before they had actually decided to do so.
representation of the specified situational Although they worried that the slide

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 333


KIRSCH AND LYNN

would advance a second time as they In fact, one can conjecture that extreme or
pushed the button, they did not have chronic self-consciousness might playa
sufficient time to inhibit the act. role in the development of this disorder.
Libet (1985) asked research partici-
pants to perform a simple, voluntary, The Novelty of Routine Habits
motor act, at will, and to note the position The term habit denotes a "mechanical,
of a spot on a revolving disk at the exact semi-automatic series of movements in-
moment at which they formed the inten- volved in routine actions such as dress-
tion to execute the act. At the same time, ing oneself' (Eysenck, Arnold, & Meili,
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

readiness potentials were recorded via 1979, p. 436). In contrast, consider the
electrodes placed on the scalp. Libet re- following description of the performance
ported that the awareness of an intention of a well-learned skill: "The professional
lagged behind the onset of the readiness tennis player does not consciously de-
potentials by 350 to 400 msec. Taken cide to run to a certain spot on the court,
together, these two studies suggest that but moves there 'instinctively' based on
cerebral initiation of supposedly sponta- the relevant cues: the speed of the ball,
neous, voluntary acts begins prior to the angle of the opponent's racket, ex-
awareness of a triggering intention. Thus, pectancies of where the return shot will
even with mundane, intentional acts, the land based on considerable experience in
experience of intentionally initiating the that same situation" (Bargh & Barndollar,
response may be an illusion. Although 1996, p. 460). Similarly, the movements
this conclusion may seem startling, it is required for navigating a familiar route
consistent with the assumption of deter- are different each time. The car waiting
minism that characterizes all scientific at an intersection on one day will proba-
endeavors, an assumption that is relin- bly not be there the next. A light that was
quished only in the face of compelling green on the last occasion may now be
data. It is for this reason that Kirsch red. New pot holes appear from time to
(1985) defined non volitional responses time, and old ones are filled in. Bargh and
in terms of self-reported experience (also Bamdollar (1996) note that when a sen-
see Lynn et al., 1990). sorimotor schema is activated, "what is
The automaticity of ongoing behavior running off autonomously and without
can lead to interesting or even disturbing conscious guidance here is not a static be-
consequences, when attention is directed havioral response, but an automated strat-
to it. Attention directed to the execution egy for dealing with the environment to
of skilled acts (i.e., the movement of fin- affect a desired goal" (p. 460). One can
gers while typing or playing a musical add that given the complexity of the en-
instrument) can impede performance vironment and the responses it demands,
(Vallacher & Wegner, 1987), and atten- the "running off' of highly skilled be-
tion directed toward any automatic be- havioral schemas (e.g., playing profes-
havior can produce a sense of sional tennis or sight reading music)
depersonalization - a feeling of detach- requires the capacity to produce an infi-
ment from one's own actions. This may nite number of sequences of specific
be experienced as pleasurable (during movements, not unlike the infinite num-
hypnosis, for example) or as distressing ber of verbal sequences required for nor-
(in a clinical depersonalization disorder). mal conversation.

334 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTIC INVOLUNTARINESS

Still, one might suppose that each of performed with a high degree of automa-
the component movements is well learned, ticity. Although the behaviors elicited by
even if they are being sequenced differ- ideomotor suggestions are certainly rou-
ently on each occasion in response to tine, the responses as performed by most
changing environmental circumstances. participants are far from routine. Raising
But even this is not quite right. Typists an arm as a well-learned response, for
can type fluidly on a miniature keyboard, example, is usually performed fluidly and
as long as it is large enough to accommo- relatively quickly. Responses to arm
date their fingers. Violinists can pick up leviation suggestions, however, often are
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

a viola and play the same tunes on it that slow and halting. First one finger may
they do on a violin. Full size cellists can begin to move, than another. Eventually
playa half size cello without too much the arm is suspended without support.
difficulty. In these cases, the sequencing Then it moves a little higher, stops, bobs
of the movements are the same, but the a little, moves higher again, and then
movements themselves are different (cf. stops again, suspended in mid air. This
Tolman, 1932). could hardly be described as a routine
Finally, consider the frequent occa- action.
sions in which two or more acts involving As shown earlier, routinized skills are
the same musculature are performed si- performed automatically in a very flexible
multaneously. Returning to a prior ex- manner. But what of creative behavior?
ample, a person can steer a car, gesticu- Unless one is prone to repetition, the
late (as part of holding a conversation), content of a normal conversation is likely
and eat a candy bar at the same time. Each to be new. But unless one is painfully shy,
of these are well practiced automatic acts, it may flow too fluidly to be deliberately
but once they have been routinized, they controlled. One might be conscious of
can easily be combined without further choosing a meaning to communicate (al-
practice. What makes this interesting, is though even here, consciousness may
that combining them disrupts the compo- come after the act), but the words them-
nent movements without disrupting the selves and the order in which they are
flow of behavior. The hand holding the produced (i.e., their syntactic structure)
candy might rest lightly on the steering flow effortlessly. At an even lower level,
wheel, with the fingers curling around the the movements involved in the formation
candy instead of the wheel; the move- of words occur without deliberation and
ment of the candy toward the mouth might cannot even be well specified by the
be momentarily diverted to add emphasis speaker. Similarly, typing is automatic,
to a particular word and then continue its even when that which is being typed is
journey; the words might then be paused novel and not cued by external stimuli.
for a bite and then spoken in a way that Thus, most of the components of creative
accommodates the candy that still has behavior are well-learned, routinized re-
not been swallowed; and so on. sponses that are run off automatically.
Extending the psycholinguistic model
Automaticity in the Production to behavior in general leads to the follow-
of Novel Acts ing conclusions: Human beings are able
There is general agreement that routin- to produce an infinite number of acts.
ized behavior can be - and usually is- These acts are formed in compliance with

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 335


KIRSCH AND LYNN

a complex set of implicit rules governing to identify introspectively where a pain is


the way in which component actions are felt. But where exactly does one feel a
linked together. The production of this volition? A century ago, psychologists
infinite variety of highly structured acts attempting to examine volition through
cannot be explained by stimulus-response introspection failed miserably (e.g.,
habit mechanisms. The rules are implicit Ogden, 1911), and current cognitive psy-
in that they are used without conscious chologists note that introspection fails in
awareness and need not be consciously such a seemingly simple task as determin-
known. The use of these rules is also an ing whether the lifting of an arm is inten-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

automatic process, in that it occurs effort- tional (Norman & Shallice, 1986).
lessly, without awareness, and uninten- In everyday life, perceptions of
tionally. voluntariness are more often post-hoc
attributions than products of introspec-
Summary tion. Ordinarily, we do not experience
The data in this section indicate con- most of the component acts of planned
siderable behavioral automaticity in a behavior as either voluntary or involun-
wide range of situations. Automatic pro- tary. In fact, we generally do not experi-
cesses are involved in the instigation of ence them at all. If asked whether the
the component movements of planned actions were intentional, our answer is
behavior, the selection of behavioral not based on introspection of how the act
schemas for activation, the activation of felt; instead our criterion is likely to be
behavioral responses to situational cues, whether the component acts were consis-
and the initiation of uncued behaviors. tent with the plan we initiated. For ex-
The variety of circumstances in which ample, when we intentionally go some-
automatic activation seems to occur sug- place, if going there required a right turn
gests the radical hypothesis that all be- and in fact we turned right, we are likely to
havior is initiated automatically. The role conclude (if asked) that the right turn was
of attentional processes may be to bias voluntary, even if it occurred with little or
the selection of behavioral schemas no effort, executive level control, or moni-
(Norman & Shallice, 1986) and to monitor toring. Conversely, if we have made the
behavior and the environment so that mistake of turning left, as a result of which
performances can be adjusted to meet we arrive a more usual, but unintended
one's goals (Hyland, 1988). destination, we are likely to conclude that
the turn was nonvolitional. But was there
really any difference in the two instances
Hypnotic Involuntariness at the time at which the turn was made?
Probably not. The subsequent report of
Intentionality as an Attribution volition or non volition was a post-hoc
It is generally assumed that we are attribution based on whether the behav-
aware of the voluntariness of our actions ior was consistent with an intended out-
and that the volitional status of an action come.
is easily and accurately introspectable Action slips, like driving to the wrong
(Ansfield & Wegner, 1996). However, destination or dialing a unintended but
the feeling of will is actually quite subtle, frequently dialed telephone number are
if there really is such a feeling. It is easy often used as examples of dissociation in

336 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

everyday life. The reasoning is as fol- facto interpretation, but also as a concur-
lows: Acts like going places and tele- rent experience. To what extent can our
phoning people are normally under vol- interpretation of unnoticed behavior (i.e.,
untary control. Going to an unintended behavior that is not centrally monitored)
place and dialing a wrong number are be applied to noticed behavior?
clearly involuntary. Therefore, they must Human experience is constructive. It
be due to a dissociation of the control that is influenced by expectations concerning
executive functions normally exert over what should occur, as well as by what
behavior. The problem with this syllo- actually happens. Despite the care with
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

gism is the that the major premise is wrong. which scientific observations are made,
Making an intended turn and dialing the the constructive nature of experience is
right number are every bit as automatic strikingly clear in the history of science.
as the behaviors that lead to unintended Astronomers believing in the immutabil-
outcomes. Parapraxes are important, not ity of the heavens failed to detect the
because they are examples of infrequently appearance of comets; early microsco-
occurring dissociations, but rather be- pists, holding the Aristotelian belief that
cause they reveal the degree to which mammalian offspring are solely the prod-
intentional behavior is carried out auto- uct of the impregnating male, drew
matically. Similarly, hypnotic involuntari- homunculi that they saw in human and
ness may be important because it illumi- animal sperm; and Renaissance physi-
nates the unnoticed automaticity of ev- cians saw supposedly possessed patients
eryday life. In short, as with other cogni- vomit objects that were too large to have
tive processes that appear to mediate the been swallowed (Hanson, 1958; Kirsch,
effects of stimuli on behavior, self-reports 1980; Kuhn, 1970). These data point to the
of intentionality may not be based on conclusion that the old adage needs to be
introspection. Instead, they may be attri- reversed. It's not that seeing is believing,
butions or interpretations based on a but rather that believing is seeing.
priori, implicit theories of behavior and Kirsch (1985, 1990) has identified re-
on perceptions of the stimulus situation sponse expectancy as a determinant of
(cf. Nisbett & Wilson, 1977; Spanos, subjective experience. Response expect-
1986b; Wilson, 1985). ancies are anticipations of automatic re-
actions in response to particular stimuli.
The Construction of Subjective The most important feature of these ex-
Experience pectancies is that they tend to be self-
/
We do not usually attend to the move- confirming, in that they tend to generate
ments of which our acts are composed, the expected subjective response, along
and that lack of attention contributes to with its physiological substrate. The pla-
the parapraxes that are so often cited as cebo effect is the prototype of a self-
analogues of hypnotic involuntariness. confirming response expectancy.
In this respect, parapraxes and other au- Placebo-induced expectancies have been
tomatic behaviors are different from shown to produce changes in asthma,
ideomotor responses. When given an anxiety, depression, panic, sexual arousal,
ideomotor suggestion, we attend quite tension, heart rate, blood pressure,
closely to the suggested behavior. Invol- dermatitis, and bronchial constriction
untariness is reported not only as a post (Kirsch, in press).

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 337


KIRSCH AND LYNN

The effect of theory on the observa- can increase responsiveness greatly


tion of data is an example of how a stimu- (Gearan, Schoenberger, & Kirsch, 1994;
lus expectancy can affect perceptual ex- Kirsch et al., 1995; Wickless & Kirsch,
perience. The considerably greater effect 1989). These data suggest that the sub-
of response expectancies on the percep- jective experience of hypnosis, including
tion of subjective experience led to the the experience of involuntariness, may be
downfall of the first paradigm of experi- shaped by expectancy (cf. Lynn et aI.,
mental psychology, when experimenters 1990; Spanos, 1986b).
came to realize that the contents of their The fact that subjective states are of-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

introspective observations were artifacts ten ambiguous is one reason why expect-
oftheir prior beliefs (Dodge, 1912). More ancies readily shape perceptions of in-
recently, response expectancies have voluntariness. The vocabulary for bodily
been implicated in the etiology and treat- feelings and sensations is meager, so-
ment of anxiety disorders, depression, matic feelings often are nebulous and
sexual dysfunction, and drug use defy adequate explanation (Sarbin & Coe,
(Goldman, Brown, & Christiansen, 1987; 1979), and access to mental and body
Ilardi & Craighead, 1994; Palace, 1995; states is often imperfect (Wilson, 1985).
Reiss & McNally, 1985; Teasdale, 1983, As Trope (1986) has noted, if sensations
1985). In nonclinical contexts, response or bodily cues are ambiguous, the context
expectancy appears to have a top-down in which the cues are embedded can affect
influence on both positive and negative the labeling and understanding of their
mood states (Kirsch, Mearns, & Catanzaro, meaning. Compounding this ambiguity of
1990;Wilson, Lisle, Kraft, & Wetzel, 1989). sensation is the ambiguity of language
Response expectancy has also been (Lynn et al., 1990). Our lexicon provides
shown to be related substantially to hyp- rich opportunities for construing experi-
notic experience and behavior. Hypnotic ence along a voluntary-involuntary di-
inductions have no specific procedural mension. Terms like voluntary and
components other than the hypnotic la- involuntary have multiple meanings.
bel (Kirsch et aI., 1995; Sheehan & Perry, Involuntary, for example, can mean spon-
1976), and hypnotic experiences and re- taneous, effortless, unconscious, forced,
sponses are exquisitely sensitive to cul- uncontrollable, or not involving delibera-
turally-induced and instructionally-ma- tion, choice or purpose.
nipulated expectancies (See reviews by The hypnotic context provides an ex-
Kirsch, 1990; Lynn et aI., 1990). More planatory framework for disambiguating
specific to the issue of involuntariness, mental states and bodily feelings. Hyp-
Lynn, Nash, Rhue, Frauman, and Sweeney nosis is a unique, culturally defined, so-
(1984) reported that voluntary control cial context, in which behavior is scripted
over hypnotic responses - as gaged by to occur without voluntary effort (Lynn &
the ability of highly responsive partici- Rhue, 1991; Spanos, Salas, Bertrand, &
pants to resist suggestions - could be Johnson, 1989). Experimental, correla-
influenced strongly by expectancy-alter- tional, and historical data indicate that
ing information. Similarly, measured ex- hypnotic behavior and attributions of
pectancies are highly correlated with be- involuntariness are almost invariably
havioral and subjective response to sug- consistent with participants' role percep-
gestion, and expectancy manipulations tions (Kirsch & Council, 1989; Lynn,

338 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTIC INVOLUNTARINESS

Snodgrass, Hardaway, & Lenz, 1984; ences, including the experience of invol-
Lynn, Snodgrass, Rhue, Nash, & Frauman, untariness that characterizes many hyp-
1987). In addition to the shaping influ- notic responses. In this section, we con-
ence of culturally based response expect- sider the degree to which interpretations
ancies or schemas about hypnosis, scripts of involuntariness are accurate. The view
contained within suggestions inform par- presented here is that behaviors follow-
ticipants that responses are happening to ing ideomotor and challenge suggestions
them without volition. Thus, studies in are cognitively prepared, intentional re-
Lynn's laboratory (Lynn, Neufeld, & sponses that are triggered efficiently by
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

Matyi, 1987; Lynn, Weekes, Matyi, & suggestion and subjective cues.
Neufeld, 1988; Weekes & Lynn, 1990) There are two ways in which responses
indicate that participants receiving au- could be triggered directly by sugges-
thoritatively worded suggestions (e.g., tion. First, responses could be initiated
"Your hand is rising by itself') rate their automatically as components of an inten-
responses as more involuntary than do tionally adopted plan. Responsive par-
those given permissive suggestions. This ticipants enter into the hypnotic context
increases the likelihood that participants with the intent of experiencing hypnosis,
will attribute their responses to sugges- as shown by correlations between re-
tions and perceive their actions as invol- sponsiveness and attitudes toward hyp-
untary (see Lynn & Sivec, 1993). Also, nosis (Kirsch, et al., 1995), by the influ-
research reviewed by Lynn et al. (1990) ence of rapport on hypnotic responding
has shown that participants are more (Lynn, Nashetal., 1984; Lynn et al., 1987;
likely to rate their responses to sugges- Lynn, Snodgrass et al., 1984), by the ea-
tions as more involuntary than their re- gerness with which students volunteer
sponses to direct instructions for move- for hypnosis experiments, and by their
ments. compliance with the various instructions
In summary, the experience of hyp- that precede suggestions, such as clos-
notic involuntariness can be explained by ing their eyes, extending their arms, and
the degree to which voluntary behavior is so forth.
executed automatically (Bargh & There is general agreement that at this
Gollwitzer, 1994), the resulting subjective level, hypnotic responses are intended;
ambiguity of volition (Norman & Shallice, automaticity is claimed only for the sub-
1986), and the degree to which experi- sidiary level of the motor responses called
ence, especially of ambiguous events, is for by the suggestions. According to
shaped by expectancies (Kirsch, 1985, Vallacher and Wegner (1987), people tend
1990; Lynn, Weekes, & Rhue, 1989; Lynn to identify their actions at as high a level
et al., 1990). as possible, moving to lower levels of
identification only when the action is
Response Sets and Environmentally difficult to maintain at the higher level.
Triggered Behavior Thus, successful hypnotic respondents
In the previous section, we presented are likely to identify their behavior as
a model of how the ambiguity of intro- being hypnotized or responding to sug-
spected experience combines with cultur- gestion, rather than lifting an arm or keep-
ally-shaped and stimulus-cued response ing it stiff. These are automatically ex-
expectancies to produce hypnotic experi- ecuted components of the hypnotic plan.

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 339


KIRSCH AND LYNN

Conversely, ratings of involuntariness an unfamiliar route cedes some control to


may depend on the nature of the queries a navigator. The implementation inten-
(Lynn et al., 1990). Participants asked tion in these cases are to execute the
about specific movements (e.g., "Did you behavior requested by the other person.
intend to move your arm?") might report This might be termed a generalized
little volitional control, because the ac- implementation intention. The hypno-
tion is consciously represented at a higher tized person's intention can be character-
level. The same person might report a ized as a motivated cognitive commitment
great deal of voluntariness, however, if to respond (Lynn, Weekes, Brentar,
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

the act is defined in more global terms that Neufeld, Zivney, & Weiss, 1991; Sheehan,
match the person's conscious represen- 1991) or an experiential set marked by the
tation at the time of the enactment (e.g., willingness to experience suggested
"Did you intend to respond to sugges- events as occurring effortlessly and
tions?"). nonvolitionally (Tellegen, 1981).
A second, but not incompatible, way In generalized implementation inten-
in which behavioral responses could be tions, the situational cues and intended
triggered directly by suggestion is af- responses are specified structurally,
forded by Gollwitzer's (1993) notion of rather than semantically. In this sense
implementation intentions. According to they are similar to scripts that allow com-
Gollwitzer, prior formation of an imple- plex social interactions to be performed
mentation intention can lead to automatic without conscious attention (Langer,
initiation of the intended behavior when Blank, & Chanowitz, 1978). Langeret al.
the appropriate situational cues are en- demonstrated instances in which sense-
countered. Thus, hypnosis can be under- less instructions were carried out mind-
stood as the adoption of an intention to lessly, if the form of the instruction was
respond to hypnotic suggestions, which consistent with previously acquired
then allows for automatic activation of scripts.
the suggested response. Lynn et al. (1990) described a particu-
An important feature of the hypnotic larly compelling example of the automatic
situation that may seem at variance with triggering of an action schema by a gen-
Gollwitzer's model is that the responses eralized implementation intention. In the
and their triggers are not generally speci- game Simon Says, players adopt the in-
fied in advance. If the person is not told tention of responding quickly to what-
what hypnotic suggestions will be given, ever the designated leader commands,
how can an implementation intention be but only if the command is preceded by
formed? Instead of forming intentions for the words "Simon Says." Enjoyment of
specific actions, hypnotized individuals the game comes from the frequent failure
appear to cede or delegate some control to inhibit responses to commands that
of their experience and behavior to the have not been preceded by "Simon Says."
hypnotist (Hilgard, 1986). However, the These action slips clearly demonstrate
phenomenon of delegating control and that the responses are triggered auto-
carrying out suggestions supplied by matically by the stimulus command. A
another person is not unique to hypnosis particularly important feature of this ex-
and does not require dissociation. It oc- ample is that prior awareness of the par-
curs, for example, when a person driving ticular response to be performed is not

340 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

needed. Instead, the response set in- lated. More impressively, despite the very
vol ves responding to whatever command high proportion of shared variance (70%),
is given. In this respect, the Simon Says subjective response expectancies pre-
phenomena is similar to hypnosis, in dicted hypnotic behavior and experience
which people adopt a response set that significantly, even with behavioral ex-
prepares them to respond to whatever is pectancies controlled (Gearan etaI., 1994).
suggested by the hypnotist. Conversely, with subjective response
Finally, although responses may be expectancies controlled, behavioral ex-
triggered automatically, suggestion alone pectancies fail to predict responding.
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

is not sufficient to trigger them. Instead,


suggested physical movements are pre- Intentions and Expectancies as
ceded by altered subjective experiences Response Sets
(Silva & Kirsch, 1992). In response to an Most people who enter hypnotic situ-
arm levitation suggestion, for example, ations want to be hypnotized, and they
the expectation is not only that the arm intend to do their best to fulfill the re-
will lift, but that it will feel light enough to quirements of the hypnotic role. One of
move upward automatically. Most people the requirements ofthat role is to respond
lift their arms only if they succeed in to suggestions for automatic movements.
generating a sensation oflightness suffi- Thus, participants intend to emit the sug-
cient to allow them to interpret their be- gested movements. What is intended,
havior as nonvolitional. Their experience however, is not merely to execute the
is not that they are intentionally moving, movements, but also to experience them
but rather that they are not inhibiting a as non volitional. This is what makes re-
movement that is consistent with their sponding to suggestion more difficult
subjective experience. The subjective than responding to comparable requests
experiences of both lightness and invol- for voluntary movements. Data indicate
untariness are generated, at least in part, that participants do not intend to make
by the expectancies of their occurrence, suggested movements voluntarily; in-
and the feeling of lightness is one of the stead, they expect those movements to
situational cues that must be present for occur without voluntary effort (Lynn, et
the response to be triggered. aI., 1990; Silva & Kirsch, 1992). Their
Support for the contention that experi- expectancy is that behavior x (the sug-
enced sensations are triggering cues for gested response) will occur whenever
behavioral responses is provided by re- stimulus condition y (the suggestion) is
cent studies in which correlations of re- encountered, which is identical in form to
sponsiveness with expectancies were an implementation intention (Gollwitzer,
examined. Measures of hypnotic response 1993), but differs from an intention in that
expectancy usually focus on predicting the response is to occur without direct
behavioral responses (e.g., Council, volitional effort.'
Kirsch, Vickery, & Carlson, 1983). In the Kirsch (1985, 1990) has noted the par-
more recent studies, measures of expected allel between intentions and response
subjective experiences were added expectancies. Both are predictions of the
(Gearan, et al., 1994; Kirsch et aI., 1995). occurrence of a behavior. They differ in
Consistent with our hypothesis, these the person's perception about the voli-
two measures were very highly corre- tional status of the behavior. One intends

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 341


KIRSCH AND LYNN

to emit a voluntary response, but expects The ability of response expectancies


to emit an automatic response. Thus, to generate movements derives from the
implementation intentions and response characteristics they share with intentions.
expectancies can be thought of as two Both are response sets that prepare the
subtypes of response sets. Expectancies person to automatically emit the appro-
and intentions are temporary states of priate response when the appropriate trig-
readiness to respond in particular ways to gering conditions are encountered. Strong
particular stimuli. The distinction between support for the importance of response
them rests on the person's understand- expectancies in generating and shaping
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

ing of the voluntariness of the response. hypnotic behavior was described earlier
If the response is interpreted to be voli- in this article and has been reviewed in
tional, the set is an intention; if it is greater detail by Kirsch and Council (1989)
interpreted to be nonvolitional, the set is and Lynn et al. (1990).
an expectancy.' Two features of the way in which re-
For example, in the game Simon Says, sponse sets activate behavioral schemas
players are directed to make movements, are worth noting. First, once established,
whereas in hypnosis, involuntary move- they can fade from awareness, yet con-
ments are suggested. In both cases the tinue to determine behavior (Ach' s stud-
person has adopted a response set to ies as cited in Titchener, 1909). To suc-
carry out the suggested actions. But, in cessfully execute the task of adding pairs
the first case, the interpretation is that the of numbers, for example, one need not
action is carried out intentionally, and remain consciously focused on the fact
even though the prepared response may that one is engaging in the act of addition.
occur automatically, the mediating re- Second, once a response set is in place,
sponse set can be categorized as an in- conscious intervention may be needed to
tention. Conversely, in the second case, inhibit the response, rather than to acti-
the expectation is that the response will vate it.
play itselfout, and the mediating set would
be characterized as an expectancy. Thus, Summary and Conclusions
the distinction is one of interpretation;
the difference between an intention and Our new theory of suggested involun-
an expectancy is in the person's interpre- tariness is able to accommodate a wide
tation of the causality of the behavior. variety of observations and experimental

"The qualification "direct" is included because the person might intentionally engage in
various imaginative strategies in an effort to generate the non volitional response (Spanos,
1971 ).
2This does not mean that expectancies and intentions are identical. For example, a person
might intend to emit a suggested non volitional response, but expect to be unable to do so.
Conversely, one might expect to emit a response that is inconsistent with one's goals. In
nonhypnotic situations, sexual dysfunction would be an instance of the first case (Palace,
1995) and anxiety disorders would be an instance of the second (Reiss & McNally, 1985).
In both cases, intentions and expectancies are in conflict, and the resulting behavior may
depend on both the strength of each and the person's belief about the degree to which the
behavior can be controlled voluntarily. Note that this allows the possibility of uncontrollable
hypnotic responses in exceptional cases.

342 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

findings in the hypnosis literature that ence between the two is in the specifica-
are not addressed by neodissociation or tion of the triggering conditions. In
dissociated control theories. We have hetero-hypnosis, the response set links
reviewed many studies that document the responding to the hypnotist's words; in
influence of culturally based expectan- self-hypnosis, responding is linked to the
cies and response sets, and we have con- person's own intentionally generated
sidered the potential influence of other thoughts. Also, in our model, suggested
variables that affect the evaluation and experiences are triggering conditions for
interpretation of hypnotic action and ex- behavioral responses.
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

perience. These include the motivation to Granting that hypnotic responses are
experience suggested effects, the way experienced as involuntary, what are they
suggestions are worded and questions really? Are they intentional or automatic?
are posed to participants, rapport with Our answer to this question is that they
the hypnotist, performance standards, are both. More importantly, this is not the
and the degree to which bodily states are important question to ask. Finding mean-
ambiguous. ingful answers presupposes asking ap-
Additionally, our theory implies that propriate questions, and the appropriate
ability factors, such as imaginative ability question in this case may be whether the
and fantasy proneness, bolster percep- response is produced attentionally,
tions of involuntariness in two ways. rather than whether it is initiated inten-
First, they do so by strengthening posi- tionally. In other words, how efficient are
tive response expectancies. Second, par- suggested responses? Do they require
ticipants for whom hypnotic responding more or less attentional resources than
is relatively easy are likely to identify corresponding, simple actions (e.g., rais-
their actions at relatively high levels (e.g., ing one's hand in response to a request to
responding to hypnosis), thereby facili- do so). Data pertaining to this question
tating the experience of automaticity and are mixed (reviewed by Kirsch & Lynn,
the attribution of their responses to the in press) and have largely been confined
influence of the hypnotist's suggestions. to more complex responses, often ones
In contrast, those participants who are that do not require an involuntary motor
unable to experience suggested effects response. Data on Chevruel pendulum re-
and have difficulty in responding are likely sponses in nonhypnotic contexts indi-
to identify their responses at the level of cate that expending attentional resources
molecular components (e.g., getting their by engaging in competing tasks inhibits
arm to rise), which disrupts performance responding when participants are in-
and hinders the interpretation of involun- structed to imagine a movement (Easton
tariness. & Shor, 1976), but enhances it when they
Although our theory parallels the are instructed to prevent the movement
theory of dissociated control (Bowers, (Ansfield & Wegner, 1996). In the latter
1992; Woody & Bowers, 1994) in its con- case, the competing task may divert at-
tention that responses can be triggered tention from the effort to inhibit a move-
efficiently, it does so without postulating ment that is produced by the idea or
a special condition resembling frontal lobe expectancy of the response.
dysfunction. This allows for self-hypnosis Although the issue remains to be re-
as well as hetero-hypnosis. The differ- solved, we anticipate finding that re-

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1. July 1997 343


KIRSCH AND LYNN

sponding to suggestion requires ordinary, voluntary acts (Bargh &


attentional resources. The reason for this Gollwitzer, 1994). Thus normal, voluntary
is not the initiation of the motor move- behavior and ideomotor responses dur-
ments, which in themselves may be quite ing hypnosis are triggered in the same
simple and require little attention. In- way, but are experienced differently be-
stead, attention may be required for the cause of situationally and culturally pro-
generation and monitoring ofthe subjec- duced interpretations.
tive experiences that are among the trig- Our theory underlines the construc-
gering conditions required for emitting tive nature of human experience. Experi-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

the response. I The response expectancy ences of volition and involuntariness -


for arm levitation, for example, is that the in and out of hypnosis - are construc-
arm will rise by itself. This means that a tions or interpretations made possible by
sufficiently convincing experience of the high degree of automaticity that is
lightness must be perceived for upward characteristic of all complex behavior.
movements to be triggered. The required Hypnosis is special, not because it in-
degree oflightness may vary from person volves any unique mechanisms, but rather
to person, as shown by research on the because it illuminates normal human pro-
effects of performance standards on hyp- pensities that are not as readily apparent
notic responding (Lynn, Green, & in most nonhypnotic situations.
Jacquith, 1995).
In closing, we have proposed that most
people enter hypnotic situations with a
References
conscious intention to respond to sug-
gestions. Because of this intention, they Ansfie1d, M.E., & Wegner, D.M.
do their best to fulfill the requirements of (1996). The feeling of doing. In P.M.
the hypnotic role, one of which is to Gollwitzer & J.A. Bargh (Eds.), The psy-
experience suggested movements as au- chology of action: Linking cognition and
tomatic. People differ in the degree to motivation to behavior. New York: Guil-
which they expect to succeed in generat- ford. (pp. 482-506).
ing the required sensations and move- Barber, T. X. (1969). Hypnosis: A sci-
ments, and differences in the strength of entific approach. New York: Van Nostrand
their expectations are among the determi- Reinhold.
nants of their subsequent responses Bargh, J. A. (1994). The four horsemen
(Kirsch et aI., 1995; Wickless & Kirsch, of automaticity: Awareness, intention,
1989). Subjective expectancies contrib- efficientcy, and control in social cogni-
ute to the production of suggested sub- tion. InR. S. Wyer,Jr., & T. K. Srull (Eds.),
jective experiences (Gearan et aI., 1994), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed.).
but these experiences may also be contin- Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
gent on the presence of particular apti- Bargh, lA., & Barndollar, K. (1996).Au-
tudes or attributes that have not yet been tomaticity in action: The unconscious as re-
well established. pository of chronic goals and motives. In
Behavioral expectancies function as P.M. Gollwitzer & lA. Bargh (Eds.), The
response sets that allow behavior to be psychology ofaction: Linking cognition and
triggered automatically, in the same way motivationto behavior. New York:Guilford.
that implementation intentions trigger Bargh,J. A.,&Gollwitzer,P. M. (1994).

344 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

Environmental control of goal-directed Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns ofdis-


action: Automatic and strategic contin- covery. New York: Cambridge University
gencies between situations and behav- Press.
ior. Nebraska symposium on motivation, Hilgard, E. R. (1969). Altered states of
41,71-124. awareness. Journal ofNervous and Men-
Bowers, K. S. (1992). Imagination and tal Disease, 149, 68-79.
dissociation in hypnotic responding. Hilgard, E. R. (1986). Divided con-
International Journal of Clinical and sciousness: Multiple controls in human
Experimental Hypnosis, 40,253-275. thought and action (expanded ed.). New
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic struc- York: Wiley.


tures. The Hague: Mouton. Hilgard, E. R. (1994). Neodissociation
Council, J., Kirsch, I., Vickery, A. R., theory. InS.J.Lynn&J. W. Rhue (Eds.),
and Carlson, D. (1983). "Trance" vs. Dissociation: Clinical, theoretical and
"skill" hypnotic inductions: The effects research perspectives (pp. 32-51). New
of credibility, expectancy, and experi- York: Guilford Press.
menter modeling. Journal ofConsulting Hilgard, E. R., & Tart, C. T. (1966).
and Clinical Psychology, 51,432-440. Responsiveness to suggestions follow-
Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness ing waking and imagination instructions
explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and and following induction of hypnosis.
Company. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 71,
Dodge, R. (1912). The theory and limi- 196-208.
tations of introspection. American Jour- Hilgard, E. R., & Cooper, L. M. (1965).
nal ofPsychology, 23, 214-229. Spontaneous and suggested post-hyp-
Easton, R. D. & Shor, R. E. (1976). An notic amnesia. International Journal of
experimental analysis of the Chevreul Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 13,
pendulum illusion. The Journal ofGen- 261-273.
eral Psychology, 95,111-125. Hyland, M. E. (1985). Do person vari-
Eysenck, H. J., Arnold, W., & Meili, R. ables exist in different ways? American
(1979).Encyclopedia ofpsychology. New Psychologist, 40, 1003-1010.
York: Seabury Press. Hull, C. L. (1933). Hypnosis and sug-
Gearan, P., Schoenberger, N. E., & gestibility: An experimental approach.
Kirsch, I. (1995). Modifying hypnotizabil- New York: Appleton-Century Crofts.
ity: A new component analysis. Interna- Ilardi,S. S.,&Craighead, W. E. (1994).
tional Journal of Clinical and Experi- The role of nonspecific factors in cogni-
mental Hypnosis, 42,70-89. tive-behavior therapy for depression.
Goldman, M. S., Brown, S. A., & Clinical Psychology Science and Prac-
Christiansen, B. A. (1987). Expectancy tice, 1,138-156.
theory: Thinking about drinking. In H. T. Kihlstrom, J.F. (1985). Hypnosis. An-
Blane & K. E. Leonard (Eds.),Psychologi- nual Review ofPsychology, 36,385-418.
cal theories of drinking and alcoholism Kihlstrom, J. F. (1992). Hypnosis: A
(pp.181-226). New York: Guilford. sesquicentennial essay. International
Gollwitzer, P. M. (1993). Goal achieve- Journal of Clinical and Experimental
ment: The role ofintentions. In W. Stroebe Hypnosis, 50,301-314.
& M. Hewstone (Eds.), (Vol. 4, pp. 141- Kirsch, I. (1985). Response expectancy
185). Chichester: Wiley. as a determinant ofexperience and behav-

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 345


KIRSCH AND LYNN

ior.American Psychologist, 40, 1189-1202. Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure ofsci-


Kirsch, I. (1990). Changing expecta- entific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago:
tions: A key to effective psychotherapy. University of Chicago Press.
Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Langer, E., Blank, A., & Chanowitz, B.
Kirsch, I. (1991). The social learning (1978). The mindlessness of ostensibly
theory of hypnosis. In S. J. Lynn & J. thoughtful action: The role of"placebic"
Rhue (Eds.), Theories of hypnosis: Cur- information in interpersonal interaction.
rent models and perspectives (pp. 439- Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
466). New York: Guilford Press. chology, 36,635-642.
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

Kirsch, I. (1980). Demonology and sci- Laurence,J. R., & Gendron, M. J. (1995
ence during the scientific revolution. Jour- November). Pay atention, it may happen
nal of the History of the Behavioral Sci- by itself. Paper presented at the annual
ences, 16,359-368. meeting of the Society for Clinical and
Kirsch, I. (in press). Specifying non- Experimental Hypnosis, San Antonio, TX.
specifics: Psychological Mechanisms of Lewicki, P. (1986).Nonconscious so-
Placebo Effects. In A. Harrington (Ed.), cial information processing. Orlando, FL:
The Placebo Effect. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.
Harvard University Press. Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral
Kirsch, I., & Council, J. R. (1989). initiative and the role of conscious will in
Response expectancy as a determinant voluntary action. Behavioral and Brain
of hypnotic behavior. In N. P. Spanos Sciences, 8, 529-566.
& J. F. Chaves (Eds.), Hypnosis: The Lieberman, P. (1991). Uniquely hu-
cognitive-behavioral perspective. (pp. man: The evolution of speech, thought,
360-379). Buffalo, NY: Prometeus and selfless behavior. Cambridge, MA:
Press. Harvard University Press.
Kirsch, I., & Lynn, S. J. (1995). Lynn, S.J., Green, J., & Jacquith, L.
The Altered State of Hypnosis: (1995). Hypnosis and performance stan-
Changes in the Theoretical Land- dards. Manuscript submitted for publi-
scape. American Psychologist, 50, cation.
846-858. Lynn, S. J., Nash, M.R., Rhue, J.W.,
Kirsch, I., & Lynn, S.J. (in press). Frauman, D.C, & Sweeney, C. (1984).
Dissociation Theories ofHypnosis. Psy- Nonvolition, expectancies, and hypnotic
chological Bulletin. rapport. Journal of Abnormal Psychol-
Kirsch, I., Mearns, J., & Catanzaro, J. ogy, 93, 295-303.
(1990). Mood-regulation expectancies as Lynn, S.J., & Rhue, J.W. (1991). An
determinants of depression in college integrative model of hypnosis. In S.J.
students. Journal of Counseling Psy- Lynn, & J.W. Rhue (Eds.), Theories of
chology, 37,306-312. hypnosis: Current models and perspec-
Kirsch, I., Silva, c.a., Corney, G., & tives(pp. 397-438). New York: Guilford.
Reed, S. (1995). A spectral analysis of Lynn, S.J., Rhue, J.W., & Weekes, J.
cognitive and personality variables in (1989).Hypnosis and experienced
hypnosis: Empirical disconfirmation of nonvolition: A social-cognitive integra-
the two-factor model of hypnotic re- tive model. In N.P. Spanos & J. Chaves
sponding. Journal of Personality and (Eds.) Hypnosis: The cognitive-behav-
Social Psychology, 69,167-175. ioral perspective (pp. 78- 109). New

346 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997


HYPNOTICINVOLUNTARINESS

York: Prometheus Books. 88,1-15.


Lynn, S. J., Rhue, J. W., & Weekes, J. Ogden, R. M. (1911). Imageless
R. (1990). Hypnotic involuntariness: A thought: Resume and critizue. Psycho-
social-cognitive analysis. Psychological logical Bulletin, 8,183-197.
Review,97,169-184. Palace, E. M. (1995). A cognitive-physi-
Lynn, S.J., & Sivec, H. (1993). The ological process model of sexual arousal
hypnotizable subject as creative problem and response. Clinical Psychology Sci-
solving agent. In E. Fromm, & M.R. Nash ence and Practice, 2,370-384.
(Eds.),Contemporary hypnosis research Reason, J. T. (1983). Lapses of atten-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

(pp. 292-333). New York: Guilford. tion. In R. Parasuraman, R. Davies, & J.


Lynn, S.J., Snodgrass, M., Hardaway, Beatty (Eds.), Varieties ofattention. New
R., & Lenz, J. (1984, August). Hypnotic York: Academic Press.
susceptibility: Predictions and evalua- Reiss, S., & McNally, R. J. (1985). The
tions of performance and experience. expectancy model offear. In S. Reiss & R.
Paper presented at the 92nd Annual Con- R. Bootzin (Eds.), Theoretical issues in
vention of the American Psychological behavior therapy (pp. 107-121). New
Association, Toronto. York: Academic Press.
Lynn, S.J., Snodgrass, M., Rhue, J.W., Sarbin, T.R., &Coe, W.e. (1972). Hyp-
Nash, M.R., & Frauman, D.e. (1987). At- nosis: A social psychological analysis of
tributions, involuntariness, and hyp- influence communication. New York: Holt,
notic rapport. American Journal ofClini- Rinehart & Winston.
cal Hypnosis, 30, 36-43. Schopenhauer, A. (1923). Studies in
Lynn, S.J., Weekes, J., Brentar, J., pessimism. New York: Boni and Liveright.
Neufeld,V.,Zivney, 0., & Weiss,F. (1991). (Original work published in 1891).
Interpersonal climate and hypnotizability Shallice, T. (1972). Dual functions of
level: Effects on hypnotic performance, consciousness. Psychological review,
rapport, and archaic involvement. Jour- 79,383-393.
nal of Personality and Social Psychol- Sheehan, P. W. (1991). Hypnosis, con-
ogy, 60,739-743. text, and commitment. InS. J. Lynn&J. W.
Miller, G. A., Galanter, E. & Pribram, K. Rhue (Eds.), Theories of hypnosis: Cur-
H. (1960). Plans and the structure ofbe- rent models and perspectives (pp. 520-
havior. New York: Holt, Rinehart and 541). New York: Guilford Press.
Winston. Sheehan,P. W.,&Perry,C. W. (1976).
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Methodologies ofhypnosis. Hillsdale, NJ:
Telling more than we can know: Verbal Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
reports on mental processes.Psychologi- Silva, C. E, & Kirsch, I. (1992). Interpre-
cal Review, 84,231-259. tive sets, expectancy, fantasy proneness,
Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). and dissociation as predictors of hyp-
Attention to action: Willed and automatic notic response.Journal of Personality
control of behavior. In R. J. Davidson, G. and Social Psychology, 63, 847-856.
E. Schwartz, & D. Shapiro (Eds.), Con- Spanos,N. P. (1971). Goal-directed fan-
sciousness and self-regulation (Vol. 4, tasy and the performance of hypnotic test
pp. 1-18). New York: Plenum Press. suggestions. Psychiatry, 34, 86-96.
Norman, D. A. (1981). Categorization Spanos, N. P. (1986a). Hypnotic be-
of action slips. Psychological review, havior: A social-psychological interpre-

Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997 347


KIRSCH AND LYNN

tation of amnesia, analgesia, and "trance cial Psychology, 57,762-768.


logic." The Behavioral and Brain Sci- Wilson, T. (1985). Selfdeception with-
ences, 9,449-467. out repression. In M.W. Martin (Ed.),
Spanos, N.P. (1986b). More on the Self-deception and self-understanding.
social psychology of hypnotic respond- Lawrence: University of Kansas Press.
ing. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Wilson, T. D., Lisle, D. J., Kraft, D., &
9,489-502. Wetzel, C. G. (1989). Preferences as ex-
Spanos, N.P., Salas, J., Bertrand, L.D., pectation-driven inferences: Effects of
& Johnston, J. (1988- 1989). Occurrence affective expectations on affective expe-
Downloaded by [Flinders University of South Australia] at 13:09 31 December 2014

schemas, context ambiguity and hynotic rience. Journal of Personality and So-
responding. Imagination, Cognition, and cial Psychology, 56,519-530.
Personality, 8, 235-247. Woody, E. Z., & Bowers, K. S. (1994).
Teasdale,J. D. (1983). Negative think- A frontal assault on dissociated control.
ing in depression: Cause, effect, or recip- In S. J. Lynn & J. W. Rhue (Eds.),Disso-
rocal relationship? Advances in ciation: Clinical, theoretical and re-
Behaviour Research and Therapy, 5, 3-25. search perspectives (pp. 52-79). New York:
Teasdale, J. D. (1985). Psychological Guilford Press.
treatments for depression: How do they
work? Behaviour Research and Therapy, Footnote 1: Note, however, that the
23,157-165. attempt to resist that is requested in
Tellegen, A. (1981). Practicing the two a challenge suggestion (i.e., "Try to
disciplines for relaxation and enlighten- remember") may also require atten-
ment: Comment on "Role of the feedback tional effort. Also, although the di-
signal in electromyograph biofeedback: version of attention should diminish
The relevance of attention" by Qualls and responding to most suggestions, it
Sheehan. Journal of Experimental Psy- might facilitate responding to sug-
chology: General, /10,217-226. gestions for alalgesia or amnesia.
Titchener, E. B. (1909). Lectures on the Distraction is a method of pain con-
experimental psychology of the thought trol and might inhibit memory re-
processes. New York: MacMillan. trieval as well.
Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive be-
havior in animals and men. New York:
Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Trope, Y. (1986). Identification and
inferential processes in dispositional at-
tribution.Psychological Review, 93,239-
257.
Vallacher,R.R.,& Wegner,D. M. (1987).
What do people think they're doing?
Action identification and human behav-
ior. Psychological Review, 94, 3-15.
Wickless, C., & Kirsch, I. (1989). The
effects of verbal and experiential expect-
ancy manipulations on hypnotic suscep-
tibility. Journal of Personality and So-

348 Amer J Clin Hypn 40:1, July 1997

You might also like