You are on page 1of 3

Ethics

Life extension, overpopulation and the right to life:


against lethal ethics
D E Cutas

Correspondence to: ABSTRACT In this article I will assume that overpopulation


Dr D E Cutas, Philosophy Some of the objections to life-extension stem from a is a serious threat. Using this assumption as a
Department, University of starting point, I will show that demanding a halt
Gothenburg, Box 100, SE 405 30 concern with overpopulation. I will show that whether or not
Sweden; daniela.cutas@filosofi. the overpopulation threat is realistic, arguments from in the quest for life extension is not an ethically
gu.se overpopulation cannot ethically demand halting the quest legitimate solution. The practical aspects of
for, nor access to, life-extension. The reason for this is that the degree to which keeping the death rate up
Received 7 November 2007 we have a right to life, which entitles us not to have would relieve overpopulation have been discussed
Revised 6 February 2008 previously by Max More,4 i therefore I will not
Accepted 3 March 2008
meaningful life denied to us against our will and which does
not allow discrimination solely on the grounds of age. If the approach them again here. In order to discuss the
threat of overpopulation creates a rights conflict between ethical appropriateness of opposing life extension
the right to come into existence, the right to reproduce, the therapies in the name of overpopulation relief, I
right to more opportunities and space (if, indeed, these will approach the issue of the moral rights and
rights can be successfully defended), and the right to life, obligations involved in the relation between life
the latter ought to be given precedence. extension and overpopulation relief.

RIGHTS
Many objections have been and continue to be Whether we argue that there is a positive (which
formulated against life-extension, some of which requires an effort from the duty-bearer to create
are concerned with the issue of overpopulation. the conditions for the exercise of the right, and to
Other objections, very incisive, are formulated in assist the rights-holder in the fulfilment of her
terms of the ‘‘unnaturalness’’, intrinsic wrongness right) or a negative (a liberty from interference)
or social uselessness of living beyond a certain limit right to life, the least it requires us is not to kill,
now acknowledged or expected in humans,1 in and not to deny people the option of having their
terms of the ‘‘boredom’’ that immortals would lives extended. If the right to life does not become
experience,2 in terms of the impossibility of exhaust with the passing of time, then the
retaining the same ‘‘self’’ over a long period of requirements of the right to life make the
time,3 in terms of the ‘‘fair innings’’ that older argument from overpopulation irrelevant: even if
people are supposed to have had, and the list extending life span does prove to create over-
continues. According to another type of objection, population-related problems, and as long as there
the prospective beneficiaries of life-extending are other ways of relieving overpopulation, which
therapies are ‘‘burdens’’ to the society around involve less serious rights violations, the problems
them and particularly to their close families. This must be addressed without violating the right. I
last argument sometimes contains (and is related will indicate at least one other option to relieve
to) the overpopulation argument: the success of overpopulation, other than the halt of life-exten-
life extending therapies increases the number of sion therapies and research, and which is ethically
older people, thus depriving others (the young(er)) more acceptable.
of many goods. The successful application of such Christine Overall addresses the matter of the
therapies would lead to crowding, would be a right to life in the context of life extension, but she
burden on resource allocation, would demand the writes that we do not have a positive right to life,
imposition of heavier taxes and create higher that is, an ‘‘entitlement to all possible assistance to
unemployment if presumably the empowered preserve, enhance, and extend life’’ (pp109, 193),5
older population would desire or need to be whose acknowledgement would ‘‘devour
professionally active for longer. In the present resources’’ (p116).5 However, positive rights need
article I will deal strictly with the objections in not be absolute rights, but rights that require more
terms of overpopulation and related difficulties; than non interference. Whether or not we have the
therefore, my conclusions will not concern most of right to be provided with the means to life-
the other objections, at least not directly. extension, forbidding it, in principle, can be
Moreover, I will not make any claims regarding described as a violation of a negative right to life,
resource prioritisation: what I do claim, however, is the right not to be prevented from continuing
that when resource allocation decisions are made, one’s life. Thus, either as a negative or as a positive
age alone cannot legitimately be a determining right, the right to life seems to support at least
factor. Therefore, even when facing an overpopula-
tion threat, the development of therapies aimed at i
As More4 explains, correlating life extension treatments with
alleviating the diseases of old age or prolonging the improving access to healthcare and education for contraception may
life span should be treated with equal considera- well have better overall results than refusing to treat old age
tion as any other treatments. diseases for fear that people will live too long and crowd the planet.

J Med Ethics 2008;34:e7 (http://jme.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/34/9/e7). doi:10.1136/jme.2007.023622 1 of 3


Ethics

allowing (the negative version), if not providing when Secondly, if we are to take the right to life seriously, we
accomplishable (the positive version) access to life-extension cannot surrender it to the interests of future generations, or of
therapies. present persons, to having more resources. One of the reasons
But is there a right to life and if there is, where does it come for this, and perhaps the most compelling, is the fact that the
from, why do we have it, and do we cease to have it as we grow success of such a claim would demonstrate too much. Indeed,
old? we and future generations just may be much better off without
The right to life is beyond doubt an extremely popular many of our contemporaries who are consuming more resources
concept. Hundreds of books and articles explore and defend it, than autonomous older people do: we would be better off
and there are countless organisations and charities, as well as without, for instance, many people with severe disabilities.
laws, defending it; a mere Google search for ‘‘right to life’’ will Christine Overall is one of the authors who emphasised this
give hundreds of thousands of results. However, the over- very aspect. She writes that although she too accepts
whelming majority of these publications, organisations, institu-
tions and Google results, do not have anything to do with life that the costs of overpopulation within the contemporary
prolonging interventions in the sense that interests us in this human species may indeed be serious and that these problems
may be exacerbated by the fact that human beings live longer, at
paper. Instead, the right is generally invoked in relation to issues
least in the West, than they did in past times, I do not find it self-
such as abortion, embryonic stem cell research, embryo
evident that we must let people die for the sake of alleviating
experimentation and euthanasia—in most cases as the basis of overpopulation and certainly not that the burdens of so doing
objections to some or all such practices. It is as if the most should fall disproportionately and necessarily on older people […]
passionate proponents of the right to life only uphold it when it it seems just as practical to call on those with disabilities or
is of no meaning for its holder (the embryo, the irreversibly severe illnesses to pass on, or perhaps those who carry genetic
comatose human being), or when it is not wanted by its holder liabilities or those who cannot prosper because they are too poor
(the terminally ill person asking to be allowed to die). to afford food or medical care. (pp55–6).5
According to both the two most popular theories of rights,
the interest theory and the choice theory, persons are rights As long as the proponents of the legitimacy of the claim that
holders: only persons within the choice theory, and persons as older persons ought to die for the sake of sparing resources and
well as other beings who have interests (some of which entitle space are not prepared to claim that people from these other
them to make claims against others) within the interest theory. categories should also be sacrificed, we cannot take their
As the arguments lead to more generous conclusions within the proposal seriously. The underlying distinction between these
interest theory, let us take a look at the more restrictive theory, categories can be identified in the argument from the ‘‘fair
namely the choice theory. According to the choice theory of innings’’: older people who have already lived to the end of the
rights, the relation of justification of rights begins with ‘‘normal’’ lifespan have had their share of life and opportunities,
autonomy: autonomous beings only are bearers of rights. so they ought to let others live too. However, and Overall also
Because one is autonomous, one is also able to claim rights, to stresses this, we cannot assess and decide on the share of
exercise them, or to waive them: indeed this power is central to opportunities and quality years that people have had and lived,
the conception of rights as protected choices.6 It follows that we simply on the basis of their age, and this is especially so because
can uphold the right to life of persons at least as a result and a many people have not had access to opportunities, or have lived
condition of autonomy. As stated in a classical text in the their lives for the benefit of others (Overall’s example is that of
philosophy of rights, older women—which constitute the largest proportion of older
people). Refusing to acknowledge this is ageism, so long as
[i]t is possible to approach the right to life as an aspect of, as morally justifiable reasons cannot be advanced for the distinc-
being involved in, other rights. Thus it obviously is presupposed tion between older and younger people, to show that the former
in the right to liberty, and equally, in the right to be self-
are less entitled to life. Surely then, it cannot be the quantity of
developing and self-perfecting. If someone deprives us of our life,
life that one has had, since different people have different lives,
he deprives us of our liberty and the possibility of our being self-
perfecting, and indeed, of our other rights as well.7 which can be more intense in the cases of some, or more
burdened, more satisfying or more frustrated. Deciding on how
Thus it does not have to be the case that the right to life is much life is enough is likely to result in more injustice for people
argued for ‘‘for life’s sake’’, or as an absolute right in any way: as who, although they have lived for many years, have had fewer
McCloskey conceded, it does not have to be absolute, inviolable opportunities and fewer chances to flourish. The value of
or inalienable. It can be trumped. Is it, then, rightfully persons’ lives cannot be dependent upon the quantity of life at
‘‘trumpable’’ in the struggle for earthly space? one end or the other, but on their respective capacities to value
First of all, we must note that overpopulation at this moment their own lives, whatever the content of that which they
is not as crude as to demand the sacrifice of some persons’ lives actually value. For a detailed source of this argument see Harris.8
in any ethically defensible way. We do not have to oppose rights The right to life, thus, cannot become exhaust once a certain
to life of present persons endowed with a ‘‘normal’’ life-span, number of years of life have been reached.
against each other. Should it become the case that today’s Older people, it could be argued, have a moral duty to die
increase in life expectancy would require people to reproduce even in the absence of other people’s alleged rights to their
less (More’s4 suggestion), making it such that some members of deaths. However, in such an endeavour, we would have to
the future generations would not be born, again we do not have confront the same problem: if older people have a duty do die,
a defensible reason for the infringement of the right to life of why don’t other people, whose existence creates ‘‘difficulties’’,
present persons. Whether or not future generations can also have it? Yet those who oppose life extension because of
correctly be said to have any rights, they surely do not have immortals (or longer-lived) creating ‘‘difficulties’’ do not also
the right to be conceived, simply because without conception advocate for the moral obligation of the other above-mentioned
there are no rights, and there will be no rights holders who groups to die. It is important here not to lose sight of the fact
could be said to have the right to come into existence. that life extension is not advocated as the prolongation of frail

2 of 3 J Med Ethics 2008;34:e7 (http://jme.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/34/9/e7). doi:10.1136/jme.2007.023622


Ethics

and disabled old age, but as the delaying of the debilitating Besides the ageist flavour, the arguments in terms of the right
effects of ageing.9 ii Thus the immortals would not be old and to reproduce and the rights of future generations assume that,
dependent people being kept alive in a state of powerlessness firstly, life extension would be indefinite and immortals would
and dependence, to the detriment of the living standards and be invulnerable, and secondly, that killing people may be an
life opportunities of all, but active people able to function for a optimum solution in the race for space, whilst other solutions
longer while than they do today. They may thus prove to be less (such as the halt of reproduction) are unconceivable or more
of a burden than other people whose death no opponent of life problematic. However, invulnerability does not appear to be
extension demands. Various authors have suggested possible even foreseen by scientists anywhere in the near future (if ever),
solutions to the issue of the increase in numbers of the ‘‘mouths which means that ‘‘some’’ reproduction is likely to remain not
to feed’’,iii subsequent to the success of life extension therapies. only possible but necessary to human survival, and therefore a
Such are post-retirement employment, voluntary work (Overall, decision between not allowing people to live longer lives (and
p209),5 periodic retirement.10 It has also been argued that in fact continuing to reproduce) and halting reproduction altogether
life extension would be economically sound, or even that it is (and living longer) is not the priority at the moment.
the rational thing to do to enhance the economy.11 12 I will not
dwell on these aspects here, as our concern in this paper is not
with whether life extension creates any difficulties (which of CONCLUSION
course it does), but with whether any of the difficulties thus In this paper I have argued that, assuming that overpopulation
created can legitimately require older people’s demise. is a real problem we are being confronted with, this does not
Another right that is sometimes mentionediv as creating the justify not allowing people to seek to live lives longer than
duty to die of older people is the right to reproduce. Many of us average. It is important that we do not fall prey to ageism in
have a strong interest in reproducing, and too much reproduc- thinking that older people have had enough life and that
tion can (also) crowd the planet. In democratic societies it is therefore in the name of our competing interests (or of those of
however not considered morally legitimate to restrain people’s future generations) we can demand that, once they lived as
liberty to reproduce and to be parents, absent compelling much as most people live, they stop living. The right to life
arguments to the contrary, for example, parental abuse. Past entitles us not to have meaningful life denied from us against
attempts to deny people their liberty to reproduce are not our will, and does not allow discrimination solely on grounds of
popular. However, as More4 insists, population growth is much age. Whether we agree that there is a positive or a negative right
more closely related to fertility rates than to longevity, therefore to life, the least it requires us is not to kill, and not to deny
if in the name of overpopulation relief it can be legitimate to people the option of having their lives extended (even if it might
question to right to life of persons, it must also be legitimate to not require us to provide them with the means to do so). If the
question their right to reproduce. right to life does not have a deadline, then its requirements
While I do not deny that the interest that people may have to make the argument from overpopulation irrelevant: even if
become parents is indeed worthy of moral consideration, I extending life span does prove to create overpopulation related
cannot see how and why, in case it conflicts with other people’s issues, these have to be address without violating the right.
interest to go on living, it would demand that existing people Neither the right to come into existence nor the right to
die, that is, that the interest that people have in parenting can reproduce can rightly trump the right to life of present rights
trump the interest of other people in continuing their lives. holders.
Firstly, this is because living is often a much stronger interest
Competing interests: None.
than parenting (maybe except for cases of people who are
willing to give up their own life for the sake of reproducing. But
surely such can only be a personal decision and not a
requirement for all), and secondly because the loss of a life REFERENCES
1. See for instance Callahan D. What price better health? Hazards of the
one does not wish to lose is more of a tragedy than not research imperative. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press,
experiencing parenthood (again, with the above-mentioned 2003:57–85.
amendment of people for whom reproduction is more impor- 2. See for instance Williams B. The Makropulous case: reflections on the tedium of
tant than their own lives). The determinant reason for this is immortality. In: Problems of the self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1973:82–100.
that whilst the loss of life deprives us of everything (among 3. See for instance Glannon W. Identity, prudential concern, and extended lives.
others, as McCloskey7 was arguing, of our autonomy, but also Bioethics 2002;16:266–83.
of the satisfaction of most human interests), the failure to 4. More M. Superlongevity without overpopulation. In: Immortality Institute ed. The
scientific conquest of death. Libros En Red 2004:169–185.
reproduce deprives us of only one aspect out of our alternatives 5. Overall C. Aging, death, and human longevity; Berkeley, CA: Norton & Company,
to personal flourishing (with the amendment). 2003.
6. See, for example, Sumner LW. The moral foundation of rights. Oxford: Clarendon
ii
And, as points out gerontologist Tom Kirkwood,9 research in the US shows that Press, 2004 [1987]: 46.
whilst we live longer and longer, the period of disability at the end of life is getting 7. McCloskey HJ. The right to life. Mind 1975;84:335, 404.
8. Harris J. The value of life. An introduction to medical ethics. London: Routledge,
shorter, and that therefore ‘‘the health span may be lengthening even more than the 1985:7–27.
life span’’. In her book, Overall5 also discusses the matter of the dependency of the old 9. Kirkwood T. Time of our lives. The science of human ageing. London: Weindenfield &
(pp208–11). Nicholson, 1999:229.
iii 10. de Grey, A. Why hasten the end of aging? Available at http://www.mfoundation.org/
I thank an anonymous reviewer of the journal for pointing this out to me.
iv
For example, by Woods J Engineered death, cited in Overall5 (p137). Woods’ sens (accessed 28 Jun 2008).
11. de Magalhães, JP. Should we cure aging? Available at http://www.senescence.
proposal is that we might have to set ‘‘some definite upper limit on the duration of
info/myths.html (accessed 28 Jun 2008).
one’s right to life’’. For discussions of the tension between life extension and 12. Harris J. Intimations of immortality: the ethics and justice of life-extending therapies.
reproduction, see also Overall (pp137–40), Harris12 (pp76–7), More4 (pp169–85) and In Freeman MDA (ed) Current legal problems 2002:55. Oxford: Oxford University
Kirkwood9 (pp243–56). Press.

J Med Ethics 2008;34:e7 (http://jme.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/34/9/e7). doi:10.1136/jme.2007.023622 3 of 3

You might also like