You are on page 1of 18

218 PART IV • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1930-l94 rR 9 • STRUCTU RAL—FUNCTIONALISM 219

CHA^rE

Homeostasis is another metaphor. Equating equilibration with the status quo, as


do Kingsbury and Scanzoni, is valid only if the point of equilibrium cannot change. A
moving equilibrium helps explain both dynamic process and social stability. Alexander
(1985) claims that the concept of equilibrium serves as a reference point for human
applicatiom systems, not for the participants in these systems. The homeostatic metaphor is useful
in conceptualizing system-level, self-correcting processes, such as the assimilation of
role changes following the addition or removal of system members. There is no reason
to assume that such self-correction implies a return to status quo. In fact, growth,
change, and development are all concepts that benefit from the application of the
Functionalism May Be Down, But lt homeostatic concept.
One factor that differentiates the functional model from others is its epis-
Surely Is Not Out temological orientation. In a functional model, structures and functions are assumed to
have some degree of objective reality. Rather than being social constructions or
Another Point of View for Family Therapists phenomenological projections, structures are presumed to have some externality visi-
ble to different observers. The functions or consequences of structures are also con­
and Policy Analysts sidered relatively reliable, contingent phenomena, not idiosyncratic. In other words,
the functional model tends toward a realistic epistemology.
My purpose in these opening comments is to suggest that perhaps functionalism
Joe F. Pittman continues to have potential as an orientation to guide family research and application.
The reemergence of functional thinking in the 1980s (while not reaching the family field
as yet) is certainly suggestive of its perceived value in the discipline of sociology.
[Representatives of this revival include Alexander (1983), Munch (1981, 1982), and
Bershady (1973).] Below I will illustrate how family therapists and policy makers might
There can be little doubt that the functional model has passed lts heyday. In Burr, Hill, use a functionalist approach. I will begin with Vogel and Bell’s (1960) classic concep-
Nye, and Reiss (1979b), the functional model was not considered as a major orienta- tualization of the “family scapegoat.” Then 1 will take a policy maker’s perspective to a
tion for the family field. Rather, it was discussed as a variation on the theme of work-family issue, focusing on child care policy.
interactionism, which stressed the objective and structured aspects of family relations Vogel and Bell (1960) describe a process by which families create “problem
and family-society dynamics (Burr et al., 1979a). children” and then utilize them as family scapegoats. They suggest that scapegoats
Currently, Kingsbury and Scanzoni show strong leanings favoring the assump- are products of stressful family conditions. The stress is typically social (between
tions of the interactionist model. If policy makers and therapists are to utilize a func­ family members, usually parents) and chronic (unresolved or poorly managed). Ac-
tionalist framework, however, some assumptions presented in this chapter must be cording to Vogel and Bell, children are the usual “recruits” and are made into
reconsidered. For instance, does functionalism require a consensus orientation? While scapegoats by way of a three-phase process: (1) selection, (2) induction, and (3)
this approach focused originally on the problem of social organization (the Hobbesian rationalization.1 The selected child might have an emotional or physical problem that
question), the point would be moot if the answer were simply that preexisting stan- draws attention or could be perceived by one or both parents to reflect their interper-
dards, designed to support the whole against the parts, produced conformity in actors. sonal conflict. For instance, if parents often fight about financial stress, they might
Immediately one wonders, “How are disharmony and strife possible?” Functionalism choose for scapegoating the child who places the greatest financial demands on family
assumes a dynamic tension between the interests of social actors and the social
resources.
systems to which they belong. Alexander (1985) asserts that “Functionalism posits the “Induction,” the process by which designated scapegoats are taught to be prob-
distinctions between personality, culture and society as vital to social structure, and lems, is said to occur largely outside of the parent’s awareness. Vogel and Bell claim
the tensions produced by their interpenetration as a continuous source of change and parental inconsistency is the primary inductive mechanism, exemplified by incompati-
contrei" (p. 10). ble explicit versus implicit rules, mercurial consequences for misbehavior, or extremes
Kingsbury and Scanzoni rightly associate functionalism with homeostatic and of disciplinary severity. Research supports the idea that parental inconsistency would
organic metaphors. A metaphor, however, is only a tooi, not the thing itself. If meta- be effective in the development of problem children (Patterson, 1982; Wahler et al.,
phors facilitate thought about how families are organized by both culture and indi-
1990).
vidual, or how social structure affects behavior, they are useful. The organic metaphor When (if) the child responds to the induction, family members have a scapegoat
conceptualizes social systems as similar to organic systems and prompts func- or a lightning rod upon which they can turn their wrath when stress levels are high.
tionalists to consider patterns of family interaction as social structures that exist and However, family members may experience guilt about, or embarrassment with, the
operate at a different level of analysis than individual actors. While families do not think
or behave, their structures serve as more abstract variables than the acts of members.* 1The scapegoat role does not demand children. In fact, the nonresident parent in a bi-nuclear family
(Ahrons, 1980) would be ideally suited to the role of scapegoat. But for consistency with Vogel and
Bell’s analysis, the scapegoat will be considered a child. If a nonresident parent were treated as a
Joe F. Pittman • Department of Family and Child Development, Auburn University, Auburn, Ala- family scapegoat, the functions would be similar, but the process of induction would probably be quite
bama 36849.
different than that described here.
220 PART IV FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGLNG Dl]RING 1930 CHAPTER9 STRUCTURAL—FUNCTIONALISM

scapegoat’s behavior, necessitating rationalization. Family excuses tend to focus on ing programs and other welfare programs were put in place, but at tremendous expense.
the scapegoat's actual behavior, which, by all accounts, is deviant. Government grew and taxed, pinching pocketbooks and forcing mothers into the work place.
At the heart of the functionalist orientation is an interest in asking what might Birth rates declined. All this has been done elsewhere in the name of the family. It must be
seem an odd question, “How does an observed process serve the larger social avoided here, (pp. 7-8)

group?” Vogel and Bell identify several “functions" of family scapegoats. First, the This report maintains (wrongly) that the very policies implemented to ease the stress of
parents are able to divert their attention away from their interpersonal stress, at least to multiple roles are their cause! While functional policy analyses begin with structural
some degree. In addition, they have a common orientation to the scapegoat; they conditions and their presumed consequences, the interventions proposed are as de-
agree that the child is (or has) a problem. This opportunity for agreement effects a type pendent on the value system of the analysts as they are on the objective qualities of
of stability or integration in the marital and family systems that had not been possible in the problem.
the earlier tension-ridden family. Finally, the scapegoat draws the community’s atten­ In sum, the functional model places emphasis on existing, relatively objective
tion, preventing scrutiny of the “fragile” family. elements of system structure that have reliable consequences eitherforthe system, its
To reiterate, a functional analysis examines the effects of system structures on the constituent elements, or the larger system to which it belongs. The interest in examin-
behavior of system elements, as well as the consequences of this behavior for the ing phenomena at different levels of analysis (suprasystem, system, subsystem, sys­
social group(s) to which actors belong. It is common, therefore, for functional analyses tem element) is another common theme in the application of functionalism. A realistic
to involve different units and levels of analysis. To illustrate, both work and family epistemology, which has extensively and productively utilized an organic metaphor,
contexts have implications for workers and work organizations, as well as families and also marks the functional approach. However, the presumed moralism allegedly un-
family members. It should be clear that a “functional’’ consequence may not be desir- dergirding functionalism with a conservative, consensus-based, status quo bias, is
able. While functionalism has been accused of sporting a conservative value orienta­ almost certainly the product of the period of theory development (1940s and 1950s)
tion with a status quo ideological bias, the scapegoat concept is obviously a poor rather than inherent to the theory itself.
illustration of this criticism. Indeed, it shows how the primary institution of socialization
can undermine its own mandate in a self-serving fashion and produce social deviance.
It also reveals the tension between the “interests” of the levels of a system. While References
there may be “functional" consequences for the system, the consequences for the
scapegoat may be devastating. Ahrons, C. (1980). Divorce: A crisis of family transition and change. Family Relations, 29, 533-540.
The point has been made and stressed that there is no necessary value orienta­ Alexander, J. C. (1983). Theoretical logic in socioiogy: Vol. 4. The modern reconstruction of classic
tion to the functionalist approach. Flowever, policy makers cannot operate without thought: Talcott Parsons. Berkeley: University of California.
drawing upon some value system. The basic value neutrality of functionalism is proba- Alexander, J. C. (1985). Introduction. In J. C, Alexander (Ed.), Neofunctionalism. Beverly Mills, CA:
biy best illustrated by the ease with which liberal or conservative family policy can be Sage.
Bershady, H, J. (1973). Ideology and soda! knowledge. New York: Wiley,
generated and justified when beginning with the same structural conditions and the
Burr, W. R., Leigh, G. K., Day, R. D,, & Constantine, J. (1979a). Symbolic interaction and the family. In
same apparent consequences. The debate about public-sponsored child care is a W, R. Burr, R. Hill, F. I. Nye, & I. L. Reiss (Eds.), Contemporary theohes about the family (Vol. 2, pp.
good case study. 42-111). New York: Free Press.
Kamerman and Kahn (1981) discuss the family benefits implemented by several Burr, W, R,, Hill, R., Nye, F. I., & Reiss, I. L. (1979b). Contemporary theories about the family (Vol. 2).
European countries with regard to child care. While they do not claim to use a func­ New York: Free Press.
tional model, their work is consistent with a functional approach to policy analysis, Kamerman, S. B., & Kahn, A. J. (1981). Child care, family benefits, and working parents: A study in
comparative policy. New York: Columbia University Press.
First, they note changing structural conditions in Western societies, for example, more
Munch, R. (1981). Talcott Parsons and the theory of action. I. The structure of the Kantian core.
women in the labor market, more divorce, and smaller family sizes. Next they ask the
American Journal of Socioiogy, 86, 709-739.
logical, functional question, “can adults manage productive roles in the labor force at Munch, R. (1982). Talcott Parsons and the theory of action. II. The continuity of the development.
the same time as they fulfill productive roles within the family—at home” (p. 2). They American Journal of Socioiogy, 87, 771-826.
discuss how five countries applied differing cultural values and national goals for labor Patterson, G. R. (1982). A social learning approach to family intervention: Vol. 3. Coercive family
force participation and family fertility to similar structural patterns and developed vary- process. Eugene, OR: Castalia.
ing interventions. All were designed to support the dual roles of worker and parent and Vogel, E. F., & Bell, N. W. (1960). The emotlonally disturbed child as the family scapegoat. In N. W. Bell
& E. F. Vogel (Eds.), A modem introduction to the family (pp. 382-397). Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
included (depending on the sponsoring country) paid parental leave, high-quality child
Wahler, R. G., Williams, A. J„ & Cerezo, A, (1990). The compliance and predictability hypotheses;
(and infant) care services, and even a family allowance that increased with the number Sequential and correlational analyses of coercive mother-child interactions, Behavioral Assess-
of children in the family. ment, 12, 391-407.
Kamerman and Kahn’s analysis could be considered Progressive or liberal. Alter- Working Group on the Family. (1986). The family: Preserving America's future. Washington D.C.;
natively, a paper entitled “The Family: Preserving America’s Future,” written in 1986 by United States Department of Education.
the Working Group on the Family, appointed by President Reagan’s White Flouse
Domestic Policy Council, reveals how a value structure, rather than the theory em-
ployed, drives the policy machine. Their statement asserts,
We must guard against abusing and misusing the pro-family label... for instance, Social
Democrats in several European nations purported to “save” the family by socializing the costs
of child rearing. State funded day care, child allowances, national health systems, school feed­
CHAPTER 10

Family Development Theory


Roy H. Rodgers and James M. White

Family development theory has many things in has carried the label “family development” has
common with other theoretical traditions dis- meant different things to different people. From
cussed in this volume. Indeed, thcorists working almost their first contact with family study, stu-
in the area have consciously “borrowed” from dents wUl have been introduced to the idea of
other theories over the years in order to glean the “family life cycle stages”—probably the classic
best of what those other theories had to offer. It is eight stages usually attributed to Evelyn Duvall
distinctive, however, in one important way. This (1957).1 Despite all of the criticism of this basic
can be stated in no better way than by quoting set of stages over the years, family development
one of the modern founders of the theory, Reuben remains in many minds this elementary descrip-
HUI, and his collaborator, Paul Mattessich: tive cataloging of the family over its history. How­
ever, some family theorists have dug deeper and,
Family development . . . has uniquely pioneered the
effort to describe and cxplain the processes of true to the spirit of both Paul Glick’s (1947, 1955,
changc in families. Family time—the scqucnce of 1957) and Evelyn Duvall’s work, have gained an
stages precipitated internally by the demands of fam- analytical understanding of the changing charac-
ily members (e g., biological, psychological, and so- teristics of families as they move through these
cial nceds) and externaily by the larger society (c.g., stages. Other scholars have begun to delve system-
soeial expectations and ccological constraints)—is atically into the potential that family development
the most significant focal point of the family dcvel-
theory has for longitudinal understanding of the
opment perspective (Mattessich & Hill, 1987, p.
437) interrelationships and processes among several
levels of family analysis—individual, dyadic,
This chapter will focus on how the incorporation group, and societal. Multilevel analysis is a theme
of historica! and developmental processes into that has been present in the approach for a consid-
family theory has given those working in the area erable period, but only recently has it received
both special challenges and exciting promises of renewed and concentrated attention. As will be-
greater explanatory power.
Over the years the theoretical tradition that
1 Fully ten years earlier, Paul Click (1947) had published
the first analysis of census raaterials in which he divided
Roy H. Rodgers and James M. White • University of the family cycle into seven stages. A year later, Duvall and
British Columbia, School of Family and Nutritiona) Sciences, Hill (1948) used a seven-stage division in a report on the
Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada V6T 1W5. work of a committee at the National Conference on Family
Sourcebook of Family Theories and Methods: A Contextual Life. By the time of the first publication ot Family Develop­
Approach. Edited by P.G. Boss, W.J. Dohcrty, R I-aRossa, ment, Duvall (1957) had split the second stage, childbear-
^ R- Schumm, & S.K. Steinmetz. New York: Plenum Press, ing families, into two distinct stages: families with infants
New York, 1993. and families with preschool children.

225
226 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%0 CHAl’TER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 227

come clear, we think that this latter view of family many of the competing theories about families tion can be made with complete accuracy. Only is the notion of stage of the family life cycle. Some
development thcory is the one that promises to Furthermore, we think its explanatory power can ignorance and measurement error prevent com­ developmental scholars, perhaps more focused on
produce the most insight into family behavior. now be demonstrated in several important areas plete understanding of a phenomenon. On the empirical description than on logical adequacy,
“Family development” has also had a number First, however, we want to examine what we con- other hand, the stochastic view holds that, even if developed criteria for stages that allowed for
of descriptlve modifiers; perspective, analytical sider to be the basis for the current lack of confi- all values were known, prediction still would be “fuzzy” boundaries between stages or what were
approach, conceptual framework, and, of course, dence in the explanatory potential of develop. only probabilistic. From this perspective, the sometimes called “overlapping” stages. Family
theory. Family social scientists have disagreed as mental theory as opposed to mere description of world changes in a manner that involves no eter- stages were justly criticized for not supplying cat-
to whether it should be considered a theory, with family behavior over the family career. The nal and immutable equations—only probabilities. egories that were mutually exclusive and ex-
all the attendant characteristics related to explana- grounds for these doubts seem to lie in certain The deterministic assumptions led the early haustive of the possible family forms, such as sin-
tory power and the like, or simply a useful de- basic assumptions of the theory. theorists to the mistaken view that if certain con- gle-parent families. A dynamic stochastic explana-
scriptive framework. In 1973, Burr expressed se­ ditions and tasks were met in a stage, then the tion of family development is impossible unless
rieus reservations about the theoretical standing family would successfully move to the next “nor- the variables (stages) are precisely defined.
of family development: “At the present time the tnative” stage. This created the dual claims that These four assumptions have shaped a domi­
Basic Assumptions nant part of the worldview that is largely “taken
theoretical ideas that have been generaled in the stages and developmental tasks had causal elficacy
developmental approach have been minimal and and that there is a correct and successful way to for granted” in the existing statements of the theo­
As a theory receives critical attention from
only a small number of concepts in this frame­ researchers and scholars, its implicit assumptions proceed. Thus, determinism was to makc claims ry. They have given rise to some of the best known
work have been used in these theoretical ideas” become more plainly exposed. For the theory of regarding causality that bordered on moral righ- and simultaneously most problematic ideas in the
(p. 218). Throughout the decade, several critics family development, we see four critical the­ teousness. This led some scholars to reject the theory. For example, the assumptions regarding
(Nock, 1979; Schram, 1979; Spanier et al., 1979; oretical assumptions that seem to us to have mis- theory as more value-laden in character than so­ teleology and determinism are tied to notions
Trost, 1974, 1977) continued to raise questions— directed the theory down what have proven to be cial sclentific. As Mattessich and Hill (1987) point such as “family developmental tasks,” which we
though there were certainly responses to these blind avenues of formulation. These assumptions out, the empirical work tied to the theory has think must be critically reexamined. We are not at
critics (Klein & Aldous, 1979)! Then, in 1980, are related to (1) teleology, (2) determinism, produced rather low and unimpressive correla- all sure that there is an inherent set of these that
Holman and Burr explicitly stated that the family (3) levels of analysis, and (4) logical criteria. tions. On the other hand, the aspects of the theory the family must master at each stage in the family
career. This is not to say that a given set of stage
development approach should be labeled a From the outset the notion of family develop­ I that could be seen as value-laden have evoked circumstances will not create certain relatively
“minor” approach because it had fallen into disuse ment was infused with teleological assumptions. much criticism from other scholars,
in the previous decade. While in 1987, Mattessich Perhaps it was only natural that the influence from A third misleading assumption is that the indi­ common family patterns that the theory may be
and Hill (p. 456) responded with a spirited de- child developmental psychology led theorists to vidual is the ultimate reality to which theory must called on to explain. Furthermore, on the basis of
fense against this and other attacks, they them- assume that the process of family development address itself and establish its relevance. Yet, from knowledge about such common patterns, we
selves consistently referred to family development had some end or goal. After all, child development the beginning, family developmental theory was a think the theory should also be able to predict the
as a “perspective” and to its “unfinished” state. seemed to be marked by increasing levels of differ- multilevel theory concerned with individuals, rc- probabilities for the transitions between family
Their own chapter appears to do very little to- entiation both morally and cognitively. Thus, Hill lationships, the family group, and the institution of stages, But, does this require the further conclu-
ward further theoretical development beyond that and Mattessich define the process of family devel­ the family. However, it was very difficult to avoid sion that there are specified “tasks” to be mas-
accomplished in their 1979 publication (Hill & opment as a process of “progressive structural dif- confusing these distinct levels of analysis. Some- tered before the family may move on “successful­
Mattessich, 1979). We can only conclude at this ferentiation” (1979, p. 174). The fact that many times a process such as individual development ly” to that next stage? From our perspective such a
writing (1990) that little has changed in the de­ individual life course theorists are abandoning the was presumed aulomatically to have effects on the conclusion implies notions of “success” and
cade of the 1980s. family. Often it was not clear which processes and “failure” that go well beyond social scientific
teleological assumption in their field should alert
In the past we have shared many of the crit­ family developmental theorists in this regard. It is concepts were aimed at the individual and which boundaries.
ics’ doubts. Neither would we have been particu- difflcult to imagine a family group that begins, were aimed at the family. For example, family We sense that the theory as it now stands is
larly dismayed had the family development ap­ grows, shrinks, and ends being explained by some stress was supposed to be measured by question­ immobilized in a kind of theoretical gridlock. The
proach been proven incapable of the kind of notion of final purpose without appealing to high- naire scales measuring individual stress (Hill & major reconceptualization we propose is based on
explanatory power scholars expect from a strong er-order metaphysical principles. The invocation Rodgers, 1964). Now, in hindsight, it seems quite a nonteleological, stochastic, and dynamic the­
theory.2 *However,
*** we will hold that, with some of such a metaphysical goal would be incompati- apparent that processes occurring at one levcl oretical formulation that requires multilevel analy­
revisions in conceptualization, family develop­ ble with the tenets of Science as we understand may not be equivalent to processes at another sis based on logically and methodologically sound
ment is indeed as well formulated a theory as them. I level. So, for example, the individual development principles. We are aware that what we are propos-
process should not be assumed to be identical to ing will be seen as quite controversial by some.
Goal orientation is closely associated with
2Indeed, the first author of this chapter anticipated that a or necessarily have an effect on the development However, we find the current state of theory
some deterministic assumptions found in some
vigorous exploration of the approach might indeed lead to of the group. building in family development to be unaccept-
such an outcomc: “It is possible, of course, that when all of
earlier versions of family development theory, as
The last theoretical assumption that we think able. Before presenting the reconceptualization,
the pieces [of the puzzle] have been put into place, there contrasted with stochastic assumptions. A deter­
was implicit in early family development theory' is however, we want to set the stage by describing
will not be a picture at all. It may be that the theory does ministic assumption is guided by the view that if
that theoretical concepts need not meet strict log­ the early historical setting and some of the early
not explain family behavior in the way that it purports to” the values of all the relevant variables are known
(Rodgers, 1973, p. 249). ical criteria. The clearest example of this problem roots of family developmental theory.
in any equation predicting family behavior, predic-
228 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1960 CHARTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 229

Origins and Initial Sociocultural were many benefits for behavioral Science theory from these several different disciplines because sophistication of the theory were under way,
Milieu and research methods. At the end of the war in (frey did not ordinarily see each other at their own meanwhUe, the original publication and the sever­
1945, the United States began the process of re- disciphnary scholarly meetings.5 Before systemat- al revisions of Duvall’s (1957) book made the
turning to “normal.” Thousands of military per. ic famUy development theory buüding began in basic ideas of famüy development a familiar ap­
Depression, War, and Recovery:
sonnel, most of them men who had been “draft- the 1950s (chieUy by sociologists), therefore, proach to thousands of undergraduate students of
The 1930s and 1940s S some important foundations had been laid. the family across North America.
ed,” returned home to marry, produce children
Like much of the rest of modern social Sci­ take up previously held or new jobs, and in many There were several bridging events in the We divide the conceptual history of the theo­
ence, the seeds of family development theory cases to begin or return to college and university.4 postwar years that in effect brought to a close the ry into two distinct eras. First, the time period
were sown in the Great Depression of the 1930s, The “GI Bill” for assistance with educational pur- primitive period of family development thinking from 1951 to 1980 contains the original statement
the ground having been prepared even before by suits, as well as the “GI Loan” program for home Wi and foretold a more sophisticated approach, and elaboration of the concepts in works such as
% namely, Duvall’s (1946) article on conceptions of those by Duvall (1957), HUI and Rodgers (1964),
the early pioneers of social and psychological purchases, were designed to ease the strain of ■
thought.3 Social scientists of that era in the United these experiences for many. AU of this had a major : parenthood, Rachel Ann Elder’s (1947) M.A. the­ Rodgers (1962, 1964, 1973), Aldous (1978), HUI
States lived in the midst of a great natural social impact on the economy of the country in the form
iS|g: sis on traditional and developmental conceptions and Mattessich (1979), and Mattessich and HUI
experiment—the “New Deal” of the Franklin De- of major demands for consumer goods and of fatherhood, Glick’s (1947) article on the family (1987).7 *Most of the authors of this era shared a
lano Roosevelt Administration. It was the time of housing. cycle, Duvall and Hill’s (1948) report to the Na­ common frame of reference and assumptions. This
the NRA, WPA, PWA, TVA, and CCC. (These ini- And, of course, the norms of the industrial era tional Conference on Family Life, and Hill’s phase of the theory could be viewed as the consol-
tials, in order, stand for the National Recovery Act, nuclear family unit that emphasized the role of ||
(1949) study of wartime family separation and idation of the framework, as well as a time when
the Works Progress Administration, the Public provider for the husband and of homemaker for reunification. HiU’s (1951) report on the inter- critics were especially vocal.
iii Then, in the 1980s, a number of develop-
Works Administration, the Tennessee Yalley Au- the wife were in full control. Thus, while many disciplinary workshop on research in marriage
thority, and the Civilian Conservation Corps.) So- women had engaged in gainful employment dur­ and the family in a sense marked the beginning of ments—methodological advances in the social
ciologists, often funded by government grants, ing wartime, as well as during the preceding De­ the new era. Our arbitrary dividing line, therefore, Sciences, new definitions of some very basic terms
studied the impact of the Depression on the popu- pression years, a return to “normal” meant an em- is 1951. such as development, as well as some pointed cri-
lation (Angell, 1936; Cavan & Ranck, 1938; phasis on these more traditional roles. AU of this Soon after completing the Families Under tiques (Holman & Burr, 1980; Scanzoni, 1988;
Koraarovsky, 1940; Koos, 1946). There was, as “normality” was not without its strains in the fami­ Stress research, but before its publication in 1949, Scanzoni et al, 1989)—have prompted a reex-
well, a host of programs assoclated with the De­ ly and in many other areas of the society. Social Reuben HUI moved from lowa State University to amination of several aspects of the theory. In the
partment of Agriculture designed to sustain rural scientists who had been part of the müitary effort
* the University of North Carolina where he estab- discussion to follow, we wül attempt to bring the
life during this difficult time that, besides the gen- returned to the colleges and universities to teach lished a series of ongoing graduale seminars in various early statements of the theory and these
eral economie problems, also included several and do research. They did not delay long in family theory building. Family development theo­ more recent developments together in a systemat-
years of severe drought—the “dust bowl” years. It launching examinations of these postwar condi- ry held a prominent place in these seminars that ic restatement.
was in this period that Agricultural Experiment tions. It was the beginning of what would become continued after HUI moved to the University of
Stations at many land-grant universities began the a modern explosion in social Science research. Minnesota in 1957 and until his retirement. It was
program of social scientific research that con- And, it was the beginning of a new sophistication r in these seminars that many of the basic concep-
tual issues were addressed and the early modern Theoretical Reformulation
tinues to this day. Indeed, it is in papers published in both theory and method of which famüy devel­
out of Agricultural Experiment Station research opment theory would prove to be a major formulation of family development theory was
forged.6 As these intense efforts to improve the The graduale seminars directed by HUI at the
that the terms “family life cycle” and “family de­ beneficiary.
Universities of North Carolina and Minnesota con-
velopment” flrst appear (Blackwell, 1942; Dun-
5 sciously explored the melding of the symbolic in­
can, 1941; Kirkpatrick et al, 1934; Lively, 1932; 5This is also certainly one of the reasons that these scholars
Intellectual Foundations of the bandeel together with others a little over 50 years ago to
teractionist, structurc-functional, social System,
Loomis, 1934, 1936; Loomis & Hamilton, 1936;
Developmental Perspective hold the fitst National Conference on Family Relations. For and human development theoretical perspectives.
Nelson, 1955; Sorokin et al, 1931). I
IliïT4 more on the history and development of the NCFR, see An explicit conceptual framework was being pur-
With the onset of World War II, traumatic as ii Walters and Jewson (1988). sued and a number of theoretical and meth­
A number of the scholars who have contrib-
that experience was in many respects, the econo- «The seminars were highly productive, not only for ideas odological issues were identifled that have con­
uted to family development theory were not fami­
my of the United States began to turn around. 11 about family development theory, but for genera) theory tinued to demand the attention of developmental
ly sociologists—indeed, they were not so-
During the war, social scientists were enlisted to building as well. And, or course, a number of still active
theorists. It remained for Rodgers (1962, 1964),
ciologists at all! Psychologists (academie and family scientists participated in these seminars over the
assist in many aspects of the war mission, both in serving as a kind of recorder and reporter of those
clinical), economists, demographers, historians,
and out of uniform. While these activities held the
and human development scholars have had impor­
Ii years and went on to make major contributions to family
theory building. We will not attempt to list them all, since
immediate objective of defeating the enemy, there
tant influence. Much of the early work originated I we are sure to commit a number of major sins of omission.
However, in chronological order, the names of Alvin Katz, 7Whilc it was published in 1987, we would place the chap-
3Other chapters in this volume present in detail these early in seminars or workshops attended by scholars
foundations. Aside from these, we think some of the better Richard Simpson, Roy H. Rodgers, Donald Hansen, Joan ter by Mattessich and Hill among those basic statements of
treatments—some recent and some older—include 4Lest we forget, they also returned to divorce in significant Aldous, Wesley Burr, David Klein, and Paul Mattessich re the developmental theory that we have placed in the ‘'ear­
Adams (1988), Broderick (1988), Christensen (1964), numbers. The year 1946 produced peaks in marriage, fer- quire specific mention because each of them has contrib- ly period” of theory building. Indeed, it appears to us to be
Glick (1988), Komarovsky and Wallet (1945), Nye tility, and divorce statistics higher than ever reported to Wed to family development theory in one or more direct a systematic restatement of the theory as it had stood since
(1988), and Thomas and Wilcox (1987). that point in history by the U.S. Census Bureau. ways. the 1970s without any major theoretical revision.
230 PAKT V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-I96o chapter 10 FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 231
seminar discussions, to make them more widely A fmal factor is that, 20 years later, methodologiCaj system nature of the family (Waller & Hill, 1951, tions. “Is a relationship within the family group
available in published form.8 and scientlfic sophistication has generally in. p 25)- In His dissertation, Rodgers drew on the properiy the subject matter of the theory of family
The seminars and early writers had labored creased our awareness of what is demanded for a seminar discussions that continued to wrestle development?” “Is an individual family member’s
over the issue of the sources of change in family series of statements to “explain” rather than de­ ^.jth the system characteristics of the family, es- growth and maturation properiy within the do-
careers. Part of the problem was that development scribe phenomena. pecially the issue of the degree to which families main of the theory?” The answer to these ques-
was understood to mean all change in the family. One other reason—and we think a compel- were open or closed systems (Rodgers, 1964, p. tions is essential to the understanding and the ap-
It included normative and role changes, and, in ling one—for pursuing a revision of the theory at 264). Hill and Mattessich (1979, p. 174) ad- plication of the theory.
addition, included physical maturation, emergent this time is the call by some scholars for a paradig­ dressed the developmental nature of families by One reason that ambiguities remain is that
interaction effects [interacting personalities or Al- matic shift (Scanzoni, 1988; Scanzoni et al., 1989) setting out a separate definition of family develop- the theory actually encompasses many levels of
dous’ (1978, p. 81) idea of “morphogenic” family Indeed, we agrce with those critiques focusing on ment. Aldous, perhaps wisely, avoided the explicit analysis. A level of analysis refers to the genera!
change], and many other such changes. Conse- the inadequacy of family development theory to definition of the family, dcferring to the descrip- construct for units of analysis. Thus a level of anal­
quently, the theory had confused very different incorporate ethnic, racial, and gender dilferences nve listing of the system characteristics of families ysis is the more general and abstract construct for
levels of analysis—the individual, the relationship, as well as its failure to embody the full variability set out by Hill in 1971: interdependence, selective a particular set of units of analysis. There are at
the group, and the institution of marriage and the of family forms. Certainly, Mattessich and Hill boundary maintenance, modification of structurc least four levels of analysis relevant in family de­
family. A theoretical discussion aimed at explicat- (1987, pp. 461—465) recognized these and other (abifity to adapt to change), and task performance velopment: the individual family member, family
ing the process of change in the family System valid concerns as well. We also agree regrettably (Aldous, 1978, pp. 26-27). Similarly, Mattessich relationships, the family group, and the institu­
demands a full discussion of changes at each level with Holman and Burr (1980) that the theory has and Hill (1987, p. 441) skirt the definitional issue tion of the family.9 Table 1 may assist in separating
of analysis. Another problematic element was that proved to be of only “minor” importance among by repeating these fout systemic characteristics. these levels and gives some examples of the con­
the theory did not carefully describe the nature of those theories used by researchers in recent years. Sufflce it to say that developmental theory in this cepts appropriate for each level.
developmental change as opposed to other types However, we see these critiques as testimony to early period carried as a central focus the impact While this table demonstrates that the theory
of changes within the family, individual, or institu­ the logical problems of the theory. We do not see of past history, as well as future expectations, on of family development is a multileveled theory, it
tion. So the process itself remained elusive and them as supplying sufficiënt cause to abandon the the family. Further, it dealt with the impact of the does not show the coherent body of concepts that
vague simply because it was not precisely defined construct of the “family” nor to focus exclusively developmental nature of its members, as well as the theory uses to address these four levels of
and identified. on the construct of “personal relationships” as the the developmental characteristics of the family as analysis. The principal concept for explaining the
Beyond these issues, several influences solution to the problems with the study of the a group. In this respect, it appears to be unique behavior of individual family members as well as a
emerged in the 1980s, There was an increased family (Scanzoni et ai, 1989). We reiterate, rela­ among the theoretical approaches extant in family family group is the concept of norm. We would
interest among scholars in event analysis. Event tionships represent only one among several levels Science. emphasize as we begin this discussion that the
analyses have often resulted in empirical findings of analysis in family theory. Thus, we see these While continuing to struggle with the defini­ theory is intended to explain both normative be­
that may be analyzed in terms very similar to critiques as a challenge to which we must respond tional issue, developmental theory traditionally havior and behavior that deviates from the institu­
those of developmental theory. This has led to the if family development theory is to remain a vital has been fairly clear about the components of a tional norms of marriage and the family.
obvious and, we think, productive question of the element in family scholarship. definition of a family. First, the family is a social
relationship between the theory and this type of In the discussion to follow, thcn, the rccon- group—a fairly noncontroversial idea. Second, a
analysis. Another factor is that some of the original ceptualization of the theory is divided into five family social group is part of the institution of Static Concepts
concepts have been so amply discussed and de- parts. First, we redefine the family concept and set marriage and the family (Rodgers, 1973. pp. 11— Given that they were drawn from among the
bated that we are now more aware of the implica- out the idea of levels of analysis. Second, we rest- 16). A family’s rolcs and role relationships are long-standing concepts in behavioral science, it
tions of certain formulations compared to others. ate what we regard as the static concepts in the constructed by institutional norms. Each social should not be surprising that certain basic con­
theory. Third, we reformulate what we identify as system has a somewhat different set of institu­
cepts detailed by Rodgers (1962, 1973) have sur-
8As a participant in the seminars at both universities from the dynamic concepts in the theory. Fourth, we tional norms framing these family relationships.
vived to the present. Despite being concepts that
1955 to 1959, Rodgers’s 1962 dissertation (supervised by respecify the process of development. Finally, we And, even some of the norms are relatively univer-
Hill) and the 1964 Journal article that arose from it served are in daily use by sociologists, there are a variety
provide cxamples of theoretical propositions de- sal, such as the incest taboo. In view of these con- of definitions used for them, depending on
as a consolidation and report of the work of the seminars
rived from the theory. siderations, we think that the initial ingredients of whether they are used in a social psychological or
up to that point, along with his own formulation and ex-
tension of it. The chapter with Hill on family development
a reasonable definition of the family should in- social structural context. In defining these con­
in the Christensen Handbook (1964) gave an opportunity cludc (1) the sector of social lifc that is organized, cepts, developmental theory was attempting to
to synthesize and develop the theoretical work in more Family (2) the institutional nature of organizing norms, emphasize the structural aspect of the family. The
detail as it stood at that time. It must be emphasized, there- ar|d (3) the nature of the group being organized. graduale seminars at North Carolina turned to
fore, that in these publications Rodgers was heavily indebt- The seminars had struggled with the concept On the basis of these criteria, White (1991, p. 7) “one of their own” for two of these conceptual
ed to the work of the seminars. Among his contributions of family as it should be defined developmentally has suggcsted the following basic definition of the
were more clearly stated labels for concepts, formalized definitions (Bates, 1956).
They began with Burgess’s classic symbolic in­ family: “A family is an intergenerational social
definitions, and documentation of the sources of the ideas
teractionist definition of the family as “a unity of group organized and governed by social norms 9While Scanzoni and his colleagues find the concept of rela­
with which the seminars had been struggling. Many of
these sources, of course, were not published in journals or interacting personalities” (Burgess, 1926). Hill tegarding descent and afflnity, reproduction, and tionship adequate for the analysis of the family, we find
books, hut were available only in mimeographed “working had carried this central idea a bit further in his •He nurturant socialization of the young.” How- that it is more fruitfiil to view relationships as only one of
papers” or other documents with limited circulation. revision of Waller’s family text by introducing the ever, this definition still leaves unanswered ques- several levels of analysis that must be considered.
232 PART V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1960 CHARTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 233
Table 1. I.cvels of Analysis analysis of aggregate behaviors using institutional implications of such a view for family develop- the conjunction of two or more norms from differ­
and Example Concepts" norms and deviations from institutional norms as rnent theory. ent institutions. Cross-institutional norms are nec-
explanatory concepts (e.g., Hogan, 1978) does Types of Norms. There are several different essarily process norms. There are many examples
Measures and not fit very well into Rodgers’s concept.11 Most types of norms, Since mies can be “made up” by of cross-institutional norms, for example, “finish
Level of units of social groups, we may find norms that are speciflc
event analyses rely on institutional norms to ex- your education before you start a job” and “get a
analysis observation Concepts
plain aggregate behavior (e.g., Morgan & Rindfuss, and relatively uhique to one particular social good job before you get married.” These cross-
Individual Individual family Marital status 1985). However, what is needed is a return to the group. For example, the Jones family might have institutional norms establish the necessary articu-
members traditional notion of norm (Davis, 1949; Tinton, created a mie that all children must be in bed at iation between the various institutional individual
Relationships Minimum unit is Consensus 1936). eight o’clock, For the most part, however, social and family careers. This complex weave of norms
the dyad (e.g., The traditional concept of norm encom- norms of interest to social Science are more gener- between institutions is essential if social insti­
cohabitation) al and less idiosyncratic.12 *This
* type of more gen- tutions are not to pile up expectations on indi-
passes both social expectations and behavior. Fol-
Group Minimum unit is a Cohesion, stability
lowing Bierstedt (1957, pp. 140-145), we define eral norm can either be an institutional norm or a viduals and families all at one time, Rather, those
relationship
regulated by a social norm as a social rule for the behavior of an cross-institutional norm. individuals who finish their education, get a job,
social norms of incumbent of a social position. Such social rules Rodgers (1973) followed Bierstedt’s (1957, get married, and then have children, spread out
marriage and may prohibit, permit, prefer, or prescribe a specif- pp. 298—306) definition of a social institution as a the normative demands of the various institutions
family ic behavior or set of behaviors for incumbents of a set of social norms regulating a relatively coherent over a manageable period of time. Cross-insti­
Institution Unit is aggregate Institutional norms social position. For example, the position of “fa­ sector of social life. Some of the sectors of social tutional norms change over time (cohort) and
behavior regulating life that are usually viewed as social institutions by gender. White’s (1991) research has shown
ther” in North American culture is associated with
(raarriages and marriage and
the rule that incumbents are to provide for their are polity, education, religion, work, and family. that although the modal sequencing patterns for
families) family
offspring. This norm has the two dimensions of Each of these institutions is composed of a set of men and women are presently the same for the
«Adapted from White (1988, Table 1). behavior and expectation. Many social scientists norms that provide guidance and direction for be­ events of “first job, first marriage, and first child,”
have mistakenly come to believe that the only real havior in that area of social life. this was not the case prior to 1939 when wo-
dimension of norms is the expectational dimen­ There are two types of norms within an in­ men’s modal path was to get a job after marriage
Norm
sion (Marini, 1984). However, we would point out stitution. Each institution contains norms that are and children. Women have experienced immense
A norm is “a patterned or commonly held that the essence of a rule is that it be followed by static in character. These static norms regulate the change in cross-institutional sequencing of norms
behavior expectation. A learned response, held in most people. Indeed, a social expectation is as behavior and expectations within an age grouping between work and family, whereas the norms for
common by members of a group” (Bates, 1956, p. much founded on our observation of behavioral or stage. For example, the norm regarding marital men have been relatively slab! e.'3
314). Thus, norms are the basic structural build­ regularities as it is on “should” or “ought” dimen­ fldelity is relatively unchanging throughout mar-
ing blocks for all groups, including the family sion of mies. Returning to the example of provider riage. There are also static norms that concern Role
group. norms for fathers, if fathers behaviorally defaulted behavior at one point in time, such as for one age
or stage, for example, children may not have driv- Again, the early theorists turned to Bates,
This deflnition caused some problems for the on this expectation in great numbers, it would
ing licenses. who defined a role as “a part of a social position
early theorists. Rodgers (1962, 1973) notcd that soon cease to be an expectation even though
The second type of norm within an institu­ consisting of a more or less integrated or related
common usage of the social role concept con- some persons would religiously ding to the no­
tion that father “should” behave in such a way. tion is what we call process norms. Process norms subset of social norms which is distinguishable
tained the two dimensions of (1) a social expecta­
regulate the timing and sequencing of expecta­ from other sets of norms forming the same posi­
tion and (2) behavior. His approach was to divide Indeed, this view, along with the empirical work
of Modell (1980), suggests to us that changes in tions and behavior. Indeed, these process norms tion” (Bates, 1956, p. 314). As we have noted,
normative role analyses into these two dimen­
set the expected order for family events and according to this formulation, roles are sets of ex­
sions, preferring to call the behavioral dimension social norms largely come about as a result of
aggregate changes in behavior preceding aggre­ stages. The expectation that marriage comes be- pectations for behavior (prescribed, permitted,
“role behavior.” However, the idea of role perfor­
gate changes in expectations. Later, we discuss the fore children is such a norm. This norm may be so preferred, or prohibited) that go together, not a
mance contained in Rodgers’s term “role behav­
taken for granted in our society that we see it set of behaviors. Bates’s speciflcation provided fur-
ior” was most appropriate for the individual level
most clearly when it is contrasted with societies ther difficulty for the theory, which was not read-
of analysis.10 11
The resurgence of interest in the notc that this was not an issue of deviance, but one of
that do not share such a norm (e.g., Trobriand ily apparent at that time. It led to a general ap­
variation in meeting behavioral expectations. proach that took the view that an actor could
10Rodgers focused on a problem that vexed the develop- In specifying and extending the conceptual frame- Islanders, Kaingang of Brazil), Such process norms
establish the normative order for family develop­ occupy only one position in a group, but that posi­
mental approach and with which Bates had not dealt. The work, Rodgers turned to a then recently published work
role concept was often used to mean both the structural by Neal Gross and his colleagues (1958), who defined the ment. tion contained a cluster of roles. It has become
expectations and the actual behavior. It was clear that concept as follows: “An actual performance of an incum­ Cross-institutional norms are constructed from apparent that such a conceptualization makes it
actors did not always exactly meet the expectations set bent of a position which can be referred to as an expecta­ difficult to meet several important requirements
for them in their various roles. Indeed, anyone observing tion for an incumbent of that position” (p. 64). for a logically defensible theoretical model. We
the way in which the role of father was played out by 11 Marini (1984 ) provides a detailed critique of the research 12It is for this reason that we did not include as basic con­
various actors in any given society could not help but see on institutional norms that would include the perspective cepts of the theory Aldous’s use of Turner’s (1962) con­ 13See White (1987) for further discussion of measurement
somewhat different behaviors, while at the same time rec- taken by the theory of family development. White (1988) cept of “role making" (Aldous, 1978, pp. 59-60) or her issues and his attempt to develop a quasi-metric scale for
ognizing that all were playing that role. It is important to has responded to this critique. idea of “family morphogenesis” (p. 81). sequence conformity and deviance.
234 PARTY FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%0
CHARTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 235

prefer, then, a somewhat more straightforward location of an actor or class of actors in a system of cept than that of the family life cycle stages. Even could be in only one stage at a given time (mutual
defmition for the social role concept. relationships.” This deflnition raises the question in the early years of the seminars, the debate exclusivity). The implicit value orientation that
A social role is defined as all the norms at- of whether the term “position” is (1) a location in focused on at least three aspects of the idea: (1) resided in the idea of the “normal” family life cy­
tached to a given social position. Continuing with a social structure or ( 2 ) a set of roles. Sometimes whether the term “cycle” was applicable to the cle led scholars to ignore many family forms.16
an earlier example, the social position of “hus- the two meanings do not conflict, However, when fafflUy history, (2) whether the term “stage” im- This in turn led to a lack of exhaustiveness in the
band” has many norms attached to it. Some of we turn to cross-cultural research, there are fairly plied a predetermined and invariant progression, stages. That is, the stages did not exhaust the pos­
these norms are static norms, such as prescribing clear examples of conflict. One example may be and (3) the criteria for selecting an appropriate sible family forms but ignored certain forms such
holding a job while other norms are process seen in some matrilineal societies where the so­ set of stages. These clements are not as discrete as as single parents and cohabitation. This lack is, of
norms, such as “finish your education before you cial role of father is played by the incumbent of we have stated them, but are actually quite course, a transparent weakness of stage concep-
get married.” And some of the norms are stage- the position we might designate as mother’s intertwined. tions when applied to cross-cultural settings. One
graded, such as the different expectations on brother, rather than by the biological father, This Though the cyclical assumption carried with consequence of this was that many scholars saw
wives with children versus wives without chil- example offers complications for the original defi- it the comfort of a predictablc and regular pattern the theory as wanting the requisite generality and
dren. At any one particular time, all of the norms nition used by developmentalists. to family histories, there was simply too much variety for effective cross-cultural research.
attached by the culture to a social position in a In fact, when we turn to examples in the evidence that families varied widely in the paths We could add that there has been a rather

IPfPPPf
particular social structure compose the role for study of kinship, other problems emerge. Both de- that they took. Thus, just as the human develop- general failure to tie the stages developed to any
that position.14 scriptive and analytic studies of kinship (Schusky, ment theorists have adopted the term “life systematic theoretical foundation. We are not
We are often tempted to discuss family roles 1965; White, 1963) suggest that we can and do course” to deal with the experience of individuals, aware of a set of family stages that has been deline-
such as the husband role as though it were one discuss structure and position independently of increasingly family development theorists have ated on the basis of qualitatively distinct role
consistent role over time, However, from our pre- roles played by incumbents. For instance, the adopted “career” in preference to “cycle.” The structures and normative content. Nor have the
vious discussion of norms, it is apparent that this is position of “husband” can be identifled by its rela- idea of predetermination and invariance in stages many events used to indicate stage transitions
not the case. Norms and, by extension, the roles tional location in a dyadic social structure. The simply did not fit well with the view of develop­ been systematically linked to conceptions of
they compose, change over time. The norms and position of husband is a male connected by an mental theory that the present is both a conse- stages. Indeed, since the early work by Glick
roles change with the age of the incumbent (age- affinal relationship to a female, The role of hus­ quence of what has gone before and what is antici- (1947), the assumption has been that one particu­
graded) and the interactional structure of the fam­ band may change from one set of cultural norms pated for the future. What the content of a given lar event demarcates one particular stage, rather
ily (stage-graded). An incumbent of a husband to another. And within a culture it may change stage will be under such conditions could not be than several different stages. The theory has failed
role immersed in a family structure where chil­ over time. However, comparative cross-cultural predetermined but became a consequence of pre- to effectively tie these diverse ideas together.17 *
dren are present has to deal with the articulation study would be impossible if we could not define vious career expcriences. Rodgers had struggled When these critiques of stage schema are
of other norms and expectations associated with position independently from the normatively with this idea but found it frustrating when trying
16Such a view was certainly pro-marriage, pro-natal, pro-
the position of father. Thus, the role of husband structured role. to put it into operation for research. In 1973, he
nuclear family, tended toward a class and ethnic bias, and
changes some of its normative content over time Therefore, a position can be defined as a suggested a possible solution to this problem by failed to recognize divorce, “premature” deaths of chil­
whüe other norms regarding this position are rela- point or location within a particular type of social referring to some “new” statistical operations that dren and adults, remarriage, stepfamilies, or unemploy-
tively invariant, for example, the North American structure. For the study of the family, the social were beginning to appcar, namely, stochastic ana- ment and other work life variations—not to mention the
norms about raarital fidelity and monogamy. The structure in which positions are located is that of lytical techniques (Rodgers, 1973, pp. 253— clearly North American bias that it held. This may well
254).1,5 Since that time, statistical analysis of the- have been due to the period and context in which the
changes in normative content are tied to changes kinship. Family positions are defined in rela­
oretically relevant data has appeared (Morgan & theory was initially formulated. We are aware. of course,
in the interactional structure of the family group tionship to other positions on several dimensions: of the efïorts of Aldous (1978, pp. 86-93 ) and later of Hill
and, hence, to stages of the family. gender, generation, and affinal or consanguineal Rindfuss, 1985; Teachman & Polonko, 1984), but
(1986) to set out stages for “nuclear” and “nonnuclear"
relations. So, for example, the position of a hus­ llttle progress has been made in tying this liter- families. In Aldous’s formulation for “single-parent fami­
Position band is given as a male affinally related to a female ature to the theory of family development. This is lies of divorced women,” the return to the work force is
of approximately the same generation. principally due to the fact that the necessary rc- used as a critical role transition. She presents no set of
As we have just seen, the term “position” had conceptualization in the theory has laggcd behind stages for the single mother who does not return to work,
been used by developmental scholars to mean all methodological progress. though she proposes that deaths of aging parents or resi-
the roles for an individual at a point in time. As we Stage dential moves might serve as critical transitions for them.
The third issue of appropriate criteria for a
These suggestions fit well with our contention that cross-
noted earlier, however, one of the sources for this Aldous (1978) has defined the stage concept set of stages involved several aspects in the car- generational and cross-institutional norms are important
deflnition (Gross et al., 1958) demonstrates the as follows: lier years. Some scholars were willing to tolerate family transitional events. For those who remarry, Aldous
ambiguity in the term by defining position as “the “fuzzy” or “overlapping” boundaries for stages, suggests that “. . . the applicable nuclear family stages
A stage is a division within the lifetime of a family
14Readers should note that this revised conceptualization that is distinctive enough from those that precede thus sacrificing the logical criterion that a family can be reintroduced as guides." Given Fig. 2 and the dis­
effectively removes the idea that there are a cluster of and follow it to constitute a separate period. It pre- cussion that accompanies it, we would tend to see the
roles contained in one social position occupied by an supposes qualitative changes so readily discernible 15 The sources for these embryonic ideas for statistical mod­ analytical problem somewhat dlfferently. Her own discus­
actor at one point in time, Instead, we are proposing that that earlier interaction patterns cluster together in els that might make sense for family developmental stage sion indicates her dissatisfaction with the stages devel­
there are a number of positions that an actor occupies, clear distinction from later phenomena. (p. 80) analysis were the “game tree model” that Magrabi and oped for precisely the two reasons we have discussed:
each with its own role composed of culturally defined Marshall had publishcd in 1965 and the use of “Markov lack of exclusivity and lack of exhaustiveness.
norms. Thus, the concept of role cluster is misleading. It Over the years there has probably been no more Chain” analysis, which was only beginning to appcar in 17Cf. Aldous (1978, pp. 83-93) and Klein et al. (1979), for
is not included in the reformulation of the theory. troublesome and controversial, yet enduring, con­ hc literature at that time. more on the problem of sets of stages.
236 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1960
CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 237
summarized, it becomes clear that there are three lieve that the connection is based on three as-
criteria we should require of a set of family stages: sumptions. First, the positions and relations be-
Time
tween positions (afflnal and consanguineal)
1. The set should be exhaustive and exclusive.
2. The set should be tied to the theory.
compose a family structure with qualitatively dif.
ferent patterns of interaction based on the as-
Event
3. The set should have cross-cultural applicabil-
sumption that additions and deletions of members
ity. cohabitation f A O
are critical variables for interaction. For example
The theoretical definition of the family facilitates when the second child is added to a family, jt
the construction of stages. Recall that the family is becomes possible for sibling interaction to be pre­
defmed as a social group regulated by the norms sent. A second assumption is that interaction in a
of the institution of marriage and the family. In­ common domicile is different from interaction be-
deed, most social groups that endure over time tween family members not sharing a common
are regulated by some set of institutional norms. domicile. Interacting with family members out-
What is unusual about the norms regulating the side the domicile is just as important to establish- birth Ist child
family is that these are the only institutional ing the uniqueness of stages as is interaction with-
norms that apply to afflnal and consanguineal rela- in a common domicile. The third assumption is
tionships. The family, then, is a unique form of that changes in family structure are accompanied
social group because of the types of relationships by transition events. In many societies these
that create its group structure. events are recognized as “rites of passage,” such as birth 2nd child
The implications for the theory of family de- the marriage ceremony. As structures become
velopment are that family group structure can be more frequent in a population and, hence, more
used to delineate a set of stages. For example, normative (Modell, 1980), the events attached to
common kinship diagrams (Schusky, 1965) can the beginning and end of these stages become divorce
readily be used to diagram various family forms. more widely acknowledged. So, as cohabitation
Such diagrams have the distinct drawback that it is becomes more widely accepted as a premarital
not easy to separate who is “in” or “out” of the stage of family formation, it can be expected that
household. This is a basic distinction for our own the transition event of “moving day” could be­
culture in terms of “launching” but also for many come more commonly acknowledged as some-
other cultures that do not practice neolocality. In thing akin to a “rite of passage.”
addition, family processes such as divorce and If stages are formulated as suggested, how do geradH
separation continue to be family relationships they meet the criteria laid out at the beginning of
(Ahrons & Rodgers, 1987) and do not stop just this discussion on stages? This formulation of fami­ | • consanguineal relation
because some members are “out” of the house­ ly stages is tied to the theory of family develop­ ■- • affinal (marital)
hold. We can thus add to our structural diagrams ment by three assumptions regarding the kind of A • male
parameters that make interaction within the O • fcmale
the dimension of household.18 It becomes impor­
* • divorce
tant whether one is in or out of the household from group qualitatively distinct. Since the structures
a perspective of potential transitions. The set of are based on the positions and relations in the
stages would include some of those depicted in group, family stages are mutually exclusive. That IO • domicile
Figure 1. The formulation of stages in Figure 1 is, a family containing the positions of a mother
appears to meet the criteria of cross-cultural appli- consanguineally related to a daughter is not the
cability, and they could be generaled as exclusive same as any other structure. This formulation of Figure 10-1. Family stages and events [adapted from White (1991, Table 11.1, p. 222)].
and exhaustive for any flnite set of members. stages can be exhaustive of all possible stages.19 * *
How are the structures in Figure 1 connected Last, the criteria of cross-cultural applicability of
with the theory of family development? We be- the stages appears to have been met. There is lit-
tle, if any, specific normative content to this for­ set of stages. Rather, these stages focus on the norms of fldelity and monogaray are attached to
18In a personal communication after revlewing an early mulation that would result in a culturally biased positions that may occur in all cultures and to this position may vary from culture to culture.
draft of this chapter, Paul Glick pointed out that our use which each culture may attach their own cultural
of “household” here is not equivalent to the way the U.S. 19However, a computer would be needed to generale all of norms to construct their own cultural roles.
Census Bureau uses the term. We are referring, of course, Event
the possible stages, even if the stages to be produced Hence, the position of husband may be defmed as
only to a domicile occupied by members of a family af- were restricted to a relatively small number of positions. a male affinally attached to a female marked by the Developmental scholars have used events as
finally and/or consanguinally related. The Census Bureau For most researchers, this probably means a judicious beginning event of a wedding and the ending measures for family transitions. For example, the
includes in the term “household” anyone living in a domi­ placing of many stages in a residual category of “other
cile, related or not. stages.” Doxng so, nonetheless, insures exhaustiveness.
event of death or divorce. However, whether the event of the birth of the first child separates the
238 PART V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURLNG 1946-196o

marital dyad from the new family. However, sel- Notion of the Family Career ever, the event that marks the transition is treated riage has lasted, the greater the potential amount
dom have scholars treated the idea of event as 35 a point in time. Even though all of our dynamic of time for the marriage to experience any given
anything other than an “operationalization” of the We come, at last, to the capstone concept jn
the earlier formulations of family development concepts are concerned with families over time, stage. From a methodological point of view, these
stage. We believe that events are indeed opera- in the final analysis we measure points in time and measures cannot be considered to be independent
tionalizations, hut that the linkage between events theory. The view of Bernard Farber (1961) that
the family was a set of “mutually contingent ca- infer continuity between those points. from one another. More specifically, this presents
and stages has theoretical as well as empirical im- The theoretical importance of family transi­ problems in simultaneously separating out their
portance. Returning to Figure 1, it can be seen that reers” along with the revision and formal state­
ment by Rodgers of several other concepts pro- tions is that they are regulated by the process individual influences (Glenn, 1977; Tuma & Hann-
events are important clements in the diagram of norms (as opposed to static norms) of the institu- an, 1984).
stages and are inextricably tied to the notion of vided an extensive conceptual foundation, h was a
logica! step for Rodgers to formulate the idea of tion of marriage and family. The static norms regu- Timing as Normative. There is an impor­
stage. White (1991) cites Allison’s deflnition of an late what goes on inside a particular stage whereas tant measure used in developmental studies that
event: family career. Just as positions had carcers com-
posed of the sequential linking of roles (role clus­ the process norms regulate transitions between relates to all three levels of analysis: family, rela­
ters in the older formulation), there was a similar stages.21 tionship, or individual. It is whether the unit of
. . . an event consists of some qualitative change that
occurs at a specific point in time. One would not linking of role complexes (Rodgers, 1962, p. 43) There are several different subtypes of pro­ analysis is “on time.”22 *It is extremely important
ordinarily use the term "event" to describe a gradual However, given the reconceptualization thus cess norms. One type of process norm regulatcs to note that this is not really a measure of time or
change in some quantitative variable. The change far, it seems apparent that it would be more appro- the sequence or order in which events or stages chronology but is a measure of following timing
must consist of a relatively Sharp disjunction be­
priate to redefine this concept by substituting the should be traversed by individuals, relationships, norms. A timing norm is one that States that when
tween what precedes and what follows. (Allison, and families, Another type of process norm regu- an individual, relationship, or family is at a certain
1984, p. 9)
term “family stages” for the term “role complex­
es.” Consequently, family career bccomes the se­ lates the timing of events and stages. There are age, particular events or accomplishments are
quential linking of family stages over the life histo- two forms of timing norms—those that are based both expected and behaviorally followed in the
White goes on to say: “This deflnition of event on age of an individual, relationship, or family, and society. So the notion of “on time” and “off time”
clearly has many similarities to the deflnition of ry of the family system. We thus avoid the
confusion that might be created by directly equat- those based on the duration (interval or period) is part of the concept of timing norms rather than
stage. These similarities suggest that events are of time within a specific stage for an individual, a measure of time.
the transition points between stages” (1991, p. ing the family structure as depicted by sets of be-
haviors (role complexes) with the structure de­ relationship, or family. Each of these constructs Age Timing. Age is both the simplest mea­
42).
picted by sets of positions (stages). In addition, merits a more detailed discussion. sure of time and the most confusing. The confu­
But, let us be cautious. The commonsense sion results from the common misperception that
meaning of “event” could lead us astray. There are family career becomes a concept that can be used
cross-culturally without carrying society specific Timing only individuals have the attribute of age. Every
many events that most certainly have an impact on individual has a beginning, but then so do rela­
individuals and families—wars, depressions, earth- normative content. Comparative diagrams similar Timing must be viewed as a general concept.
to those presented in Figure 1, then, could be tionships and families. The event that marks the
quakes, illnesses, sudden wealth, and so on. These Indeed, we think that in the study of family and beginning event for the individual is birth. The
are not events that have developmental implica- produced for differing societies. This would assist individuals, the term “timing” should be replaced
in understanding the similarities and differences in events that mark the beginning of a relationship
tions. A developmental event carries with it the by the more precise types of timing. Timing in include meeting an attractive person (daling rela­
implication that there will be qualitatively differ­ family development between two or more general refers to one of the many ways that we can
cultures. tionship) and the birth of a child (parental and,
ent normative expectations in the role content of locale an individual, relationship, or group in perhaps, sibling relationships). The event that
family relationships as a result of the event. For time. marks the beginning of the family group, rather
example, when two peoplc marry (an event), Dynamic Concepts Timing is a multidimensional notion. Are than the marital dyad, is the birth of the first child.
there are family institutional norms about changes these dimensions independent? For the most part So families, relationships, and individuals all can
in the role content of their relationship after the Transitions they are not. For example, dimensions such as age be described by their age. Individual age, for ex­
wedding, On the other hand, there is no similar of a marriage (marital cohort) and the duration of ample, is often measured by birth cohort, whereas
set of normative expectations about a couple who The concept of family transitions20 combines a marital stage are related. The longer the mar-
the concepts of stage and event and time. A transi­ marital age is measured by marriage cohort. Fur-
wins the lottery. A number of possible role rela­ thermore, we can cross levels of analysis and talk
tionships could result from such an event, but tion occurs when a family moves from one 2lln a highly stimulating analysis of the social psychology
qualitatively distinct stage to another stage. The of intergenerational relations, Hagestad (1981, pp. 19-
about the ages for different relationships and indi­
winning the lottery does not initiale a normatively T viduals in the family. And an especially important
deflned stage. Thus, says White, “A stage is a nec- stages represent intervals or periods of time. How- 20) identifics the important fact that family transitions
often have intergenerational effects. “Marriage in one crossover for event analysis is that we can talk
essary condition for there being an event” (1991, I gencration creates in-laws in another. Parenthood ere- about the age of the family in which an individual
p. 43). In other words, the kind of event that con­ 20The concept of transitions has been a part of the family 1 f ates grandparenthood. Voluntary childlessness may is a member even though that individual might
cerns us is an event that marks a transition be­ developmental approach for a long time. The seminar create involuntary grandchildlessness." Clearly there is
participants were aware of the work of the Rapoports not have been born when the family began.
tween two stages containing qualitatively different more involved than the vested intcrests of the individual
even before they published their two influential articles or relationship participants in many family transitions.
norms and, without the stages, the event would (Rapoport, 1964; Rapoport & Rapoport, 1964). And, of
have no developmental signiflcance. For this rea- Nearly ten years later this appears to continue to be an 22Bernice Neugarten (Neugarten et al, 1965; Neugarten &
course, Aldous (1978) used it as central in her discussion. onderresearehed area of family careers (Though it Datan, 1973) introduced the idea of being “on-time” and
son, we choose to be more specific and call such We think it deserves an explicit and central place in our should be noted that Hagestad would probably prefer “off-time” in the life cycle and produced some insightful
developmental events transitional events. reconceptualization. the term “family lineages”!) analyses of their consequences.
240 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-19g0 CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 241
Event and Stage Sequences. Event and stage mental, there is a specified normative order to the end23 and, sometimes, the beginning of another cess whereby stages of family life are sequenced so
sequencing is another kind of family development sequence of stages and events, First comes love stage- S°, for example, the birth of the second that the probability of any stage is determined by the
normative timing. And, again, it has family process child in a family marks a change in group struc- time duration in the previous stage. (1991, p. 42)
then comes marriage, then comes Suzie with a
implications. The order of events and stages has baby carriage. First one completes one’s educa- pjj-e, a new sibling relationship begins, and often a This definition, as compared with the Mat-
very important family consequences. Marriage —*> tion, then one gets a job, then one gets married cross-sex parental relationship begins for one of tessich and Hill definition quoted earlier, makes it
birth of child —-> divorce is different in family sig- then one has a child. There are important implica­ (jie parents. This event also marks the end of the quite clear what precipitates change in the family
nificance from birth ^ marriage —> divorce or tions to the idea of normative order. We shall dis- only-child family. New norms are added along career. And it distinguishes family changes that are
marriage —» divorce —-> birth. Although events sig- cuss these in greater detail below, with the new position, So, although stage duration developmental from those that are consequences
nal the beginning and end of a family or rela- Event and stage sequence are also measures is a timing measure, it also carries a normative of other kinds of events. For example, only some
tionship stage, events alone cannot be used as a of time. An individual, relationship, or family can­ element. of the adaptations “to recurring life stresses” of
sufficiënt indicator for a stage. This is simply be- not experience stages or events without the pas­ Part of this normative element is the expecta- the family system referred to by Mattessich and
cause the same event might mark the beginning of sage of time. Since stages are usually measured as tion that a stage will endurc for a period of time Hill would be family developmental according to
quite different family stages. For example, divorce the period between two events, stage sequences before which the transitional event and its follow­ White’s definition. But others would not qualify.24 *
is an often-used event. However, the family or rela- can be viewed as the theoretical inference front ing stage is inappropriate and unlikely and beyond This is not to say that these are any less significant
tionship stage that it marks as a beginning varies event sequences. This brings up an interesting and which the current stage is increasingly inappropri­ in the dynamics of the family. It is to say that
according to the family or relationship stage prior researchable dimension to family development. ate and unlikely. That is, the duration in a given family development theory has theoretical bound-
to the event (e.g,, the presence of children). There are possibly three effects that might be ana- stage determines the probability of a given transi­ aries that limit its power to explain family career
Family developmental sequencing becomes lyzed in a transition. There is the unique effect of ii' tion event and, of course, the following stage. So,
patterns. Confusing variables that are not family
further complicated by cross-institutional nor­ the event regardless of the stage from which the for Bill and Suzie there are expectations about developmental with those that are only introducés
mative sequences. Thus, expectations that one transition is occurring or the resulting stage. This how long the K-I-S-S-I-N-G will go on before they error into the analysis.
will finish school and get a job before marrying unique contribution can only be analyzed as sepa­ declare their love for each other. And, of course,
and/or having a baby involves combining se­ rate from the stage of origin and destination by 1 those expectations involve both there being too
quencing norms that are not family developmental searching for common variancc across stages of brief a time as well as too long a time. And there is
The Process of Development
ones with sequencing norms that are. One of the origin and destination. There would also be sepa- then a period expected after the declaration of
problems in family development theory has been rable effects for the stage of origin and for the love before the marriage, again with short and There is general concurrence that the theory
the failure to distinguish between various kinds of stage of destination. Thus, for example, the analy- long limits, Finally, there is a minimum and max­ of family development is concerned with how
timing. ;
sis of the effects of divorce frcquently confounds 11 imum period of time expected from marriage to families change over time. Indeed, one advantage
The concept of sequence is a long-standing three distinct clements: a divorce may be analyzed the baby carriage. and strength of the theory when compared to
one in the theory. However, only recently has the as (1) the effect of the event of divorce on the Noticc that not only does the duration of the other theories about the family is its focus on fami­
distinctively normative nature of developmental family regardless of the stage in which it occurs or stage change the probabilities of a given event, but ly change. However, this strength has also been a
sequences been emphasized. Let us return to the the stage to which the family moves after divorce; also it changes the probabilities of alternative pos- major weakness of the theory. Developmental the-
example of the couple winning the lottery. There (2) the effect of the specific previous stage on the « sible events. Thus, we might speculate (and our orists have been negligent in pointing out the pre-
was nothing in the normative characteristics of divorced family regardless of the destination stage; speculation is subject to empirical verlfication) cise type of change on which the theory focuses
the stage that the couple occupied before winning and (3) the effect of the specific destination stage that the longer the being in love stage endures and discriminating that type of change (develop­
the lottery that would predict the event. Nor was on the divorced family regardless of the stage of beyond a certain optimum time, the less likely mental change) from the many other forms of
there anything about either the stage or the event origin. In the First case the question for analysis is, that the event marriage will take place, and the change that take place in the family. This has led to
that would predict a following stage. Thus, the 'What characteristics do all divorced families more likely that one of the alternative events— the misleading perception that developmental
event was not dependent on either the preceding have in common?” In the second case the ques­ break-up, moving in together, or birth of first
stage or the following stage. tion might be, “What do all divorced families who child—will occur. Note that each of these events 24This distinction is particularly important since a nuraber
Developmental stage dependency has two cl­ divorced with one infant in the household have in fakes the couple into quite different next family of family processes have been characterized as being “de­
ements. First, there is the normative component of common regardless of whether they moved to career stages. velopmental,” which in fact may not be so. Rodgers
(Ahrons & Rodgers, 1987; Rodgers, 1987), for example,
what a given stage implies about the event that joint custody, father custody, mother custody, co- White summarizes the relationships between
has argued that the separation, divorce, remarriage pro­
follows and about the stage that will follow the habitation with a new partner, etc ?” In the third events, stages, sequences, and duration this way; cess is a developmental one. In making this argument, he
event; that is, the sequence of stages and events. case the question could be, “What do all divorced Norms construct relatively unique and homoge- has attempted to incorporate his ideas into those of Mc-
The old playground rhyme says it well: families who moved to cohabiting with a new neous periods in family life (stages), bounded by Cubbin and Patterson (1983) concerning the impact of
partner after divorce have in common, regardless events. . . . The concept of a career, whether family stress on the family. Both he and McCubbin and Patterson
Bill and Suzie sitting in a tree, argue that this is a developmental process. With this defi­
of the stage in which they were prior to the di­ or individual, entails a sequence of events (or stages)
K-I-S-S-I-N-G. over time. . . . Thus, family development is the pro- nition, it will now be possible to return to those formula-
vorce?” As far as we know, such an analysis has not
First comes love, then comes marriage, tions and sort out which familial consequences of stress
be done. 23Time of measurement might artificially tnmeate or “right
then comes Suzie with a baby carriage. are in fact developmental and which are not. A recent
Stage üuration. The duration of a stage is censor” duration in a stage. That is, at the time of data book edited by Klein and Aldous (1988) deals in consid-
This implies both normative sequences and transi- measured by the duration of time between an gathering, a stage may not have been completed. For a erable detail with the joining of family development and
tional events. Therefore, in order to be develop­ event that begins the stage and one that marks the forther discussion, see Tuma and Hannan (1984). family stress theory.

■■f
242 PART V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%0 CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 243
theory was responsible for explaining all forms of particular type of process that is dependent on “family development” and for our later discussion However, it is quite possible to discuss adaptive
change in the family. Of course, when it failed both stage and the duration of time spent in a to distinguish two basic kinds of change. All changes for an individual, relationship, or family
to do so, some scholars feit the theory was in­ stage. This definition of development is both clear change is either systematic change or random without recourse to population ecology. For the
adequate. This section identifies developmental and precise. Furthermore, it is complemented by change. Systematic change has a pattern or reg- theory of family development, adaptational
change and some other types of changes that take more recent work on “semi-Markov” models ularity to it, whereas random change does not. change is most useful in explaining why and how
place in families. However, Featherman did not go on to a specific Within systematic change it is possible to dis­ the current stages of family development are not
application of his definition to the process of famp tinguish at least two other forms of family change the same stages observed three centuries ago and,
Defining the Process ly development nor did he cite these mathe- besides family developmental change; matura- perhaps, not the same found in other social Sys­
matical models as possible models for the process tional change and adaptational change. tems today. In other words, adaptation of the in-
Deflning the process of development has not White (1991) attempts to tie several themes Maturational changes are contained within stitution of marriage and the family to the changes
been an easy task for developmentalists. After the together. The process is a probabilistic or the substance of the organism and as such are in other institutions, such as work and education,
early phase of thought about the process of devel­ stochastic process.26 This means that the process properly labeled “ontogenetic” change. Matura- account for some of the changes in the norms
opment (Aldous, 1978; Magrabi & Marshall, 1965; may contain some dependencies, but even if au tion, since it is ontogenetic in nature, does not governing family development.
Rodgers, 1973), subsequent work began to focus these dependencies were known, the process seem very applicable to the family group. It is Finally, we should briefly characterize ran­
on the array of models of the process. Klein, would still not be strictly determined. Second, the tnuch more applicable at the individual level of dom change. A random change exists when any
Borne, Jache, and Sederberg (1979) suggest three exact family stage occupied by a family affects the analysis. The notion of maturation even at the in­ conditional probability for an event or stage is the
alternative versions of the developmental process, probability of their transition to any specific next dividual level is ambiguous in that it contains the same as the unconditional probability. In other
They suggest it could be a discrete stage process, a stage (discrete stage). Thus, if a young family has ideas of duration dependence and age depen- words, we can detect no systematic character to
process based on a transition period, or a continu- one child, being in this stage affects the proba- dence. For example, we might say that a child who this form of change. It should be emphasized that
ous dynamic process. Although Klein and his col- bility of a move to a second child or a divorce and masters a “conservation of energy task” (such as a random process is quite different from a
leagues did not expressly develop the notion that so on. And, last, the duration of time spent in a discerning that the amount of water poured be- stochastic process such as development. All of the
the process was stochastic rather than determin- stage affects the probability of a transition to an- tween two glasses of unequal size is nonetheless sources of variation in a stochastic process may
istic, nonetheless that theme runs throughout other stage. Perhaps this is most clearly illustrated the same quantity of water) has matured. How­ not be identified but, nonetheless, the process is
their discussion.25 Finally, however, in 1984, by the example of couples in first marriages and ever, we could mean either of three different systematic. A random process simply has no order
White and Reid identified the process as being the probability of their having a child. The longer things here. We could mean that the total history or systematic character.
similar to a discrete-stage, discrete-time Markov they are married, the greater the probability of of the child from the day of birth is tied to the Having presented the reconceptualization of
process. However, their work was incomplete. having a child, until a threshold point is reached transition. Or, we could mean that some subset the theory of family development in some detail,
First, they only dealt with the first of the three after which the longer the marriage, the less the (but not all) of previous States explain the transi­ we turn next to a presentation of some of the
models developed by Klein and his colleagues, probability of having a child. This is what is meant tion. Or, we could mean that the transition is due theoretical propositions that we see generaled
Second, and perhaps more important, the notion by the duration in a stage partially determining to the duration of time spent in the immediately from the new formulation.
of time making discrete jumps of equal duration the probabilities of a transition. These three points prior stage (such as Piaget’s “preoperational”
for all families clearly did not fit with what we are what we mean by the process of family devel­ stage).
know about family transitions. opment. However, it remains to differentiate this This last meaning is equivalent to the process Examples of Theoretical Propositions
Earlier we noted the Hill and Mattessich form of developmental change from other types of of development for the individual since a transi­
(1979) definition of the process of development. change in families. tion is stage and duration dependent. So that we To some extent, theoretical propositions are
Recall that their definition contained the idea that do not confuse development as a process with derivations from the definltions and axioms (as-
family development is a “process of Progressive Other Types of Change maturation, we will treat maturation as referring sumptions) of a theory. In addition to derivations,
structural differentiation and transformation over only to the other two meanings. These other two a theory also contains some statements of em-
the family’s history” (1979, p. 174). The notion of Not all family change is family development. meanings of maturation are captured in the con- pirical regularities as propositions. In this section
structural differentiation went largely undeflned. It is important for both the clarity of the concept structs of the individual’s chronological age (all we attempt to identify some of the major deflni-
Rather, the Hill and Mattessich discussion bor- history) and some of the individual’s experience tions, axioms, and propositions of the theory of
rowed heavily from the field of developmental 26Whitc uses the work on the semi-Markov models (Col- (subset of history). These two, however, are not family development. We have already encoun-
psychology and, as such, entered into a perilous eman, 1981; Tuma & Hannan, 1984) to incorporatc these
completely distinct from each other, since both tered a number of definltions for essential con­
liaison with concepts such as “ontogenetic deter- themes into a systematic view of the process of dcvclop-
ment in families. This view includes the stage as a discrete are related by the underlying dimension of time. cepts. It is now time to place these in the context
mination.” In some ways, the Hill and Mattessich state, the duration in a stage as a transition period, and the Nevertheless, we need not confuse these forms of of the entire theoretical structure. Although the
definition denies the decades of thought leading continuous transition rate from one stage to another as a maturation with the process of development. propositions in Table 2 are by no means ex-
to the conclusion that the process is a nondeter- continuous dynamic process. This orientation does not Adaptational change occurs when a family, re- haustive of the ones we can generale, they are
ministic one. Indeed, Featherman (1985) sug- contain the notion of “Progressive structural differentia­ lationship, or individual changes so as to bring among the most basic propositions in the theory.
gested to developmental scholars in both so- tion” proposed by Hill and Mattessich, however. The gen- In Table 2, an axiom refers to a proposition
itself into alignment with its environment. In pop-
ciology and psychology that development is a eral model is that is assumed to be true. A derived proposition
ulation ecology, “adaptation” is one of the two
25For a fulier discussion of these alternative models, see q/ft) = Um ^ J (Coleman, 1981, P- 9) Processes (adaptation and mutation) by which follows from definitions and axioms, Propositions
Mattessich and Hill (1987. pp. 463-465). uatural selection takes place for a population. that are neither definitions, axioms, or derived
244 PART V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DUR1NG 1946-1%0 CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 245
Table 2. Some Defmitions, Axioms, and Table 2. {Continued) 0f analysis on the basis of the application of in­ rather than a simply descriptive one. Thus, we
Derived Propositions from the Theory of stitutional norms to those lower levels of analysis. satisfy another of our criteria for the restated theo­
Family Development normative demands and, in conforming There are many other propositions that fit ry, And, as we have observed, this places very ex-
to one institution’s set of norms,
jjicely into the theory. For example, the em- pllcit limits on what developmental theory can
deviate from the norms in another
Definitions pirically based propositions cited by Burr and his and cannot say about divorce in the family career.
institution (strain).
D l. A family stage is a qualitative periüd in the collcagues (Burr, 1973; Burr et al., 1979) regard- Divorce is more than an experience of two
A.2.2. Contradictory timing and sequencing
iife of a family with lts own unique group
norms for family stages lead to greater ing ease of role transitions could be consistently individuals in a relationship. It must be examined
structure.
D.2. Transition events are separating points
deviation from the normative paths. derived from this theory, since roles change with at all four of the levels of analysis, In addition, the
A.2.3- Systematic individual and group family stage. And the work by Pearlin and Schooi­ dependent variable to be explained, divorce, is
between family stages.
deviance places pressure on an er (1978) and Menaghan ( 1983) suggest that the different at each level of analysis. Divorce for the
D.3. The institution of marriagc and the family
institution to adapt or align itself with
contains all the norms regulating this effects of anticipatory socialization should be in- individual level poses the question, “Have you ex­
the sequencing and timing norms of
particular area of social life. cludcd in the theory. The propositions in this perienced a divorce?” For the relationship (dyad)
other institutions.
D.4. A position is a location or a point in a social table are illustrative of the type and extent of pos- level the question is, “Has the marital relationship
Propositions
structure; a family position is a location or
P. 1. Family development is stage dependent sible derivations from the theory', This illustration split up?” For the group level the question ad-
point in a kinship structure,
D.5. A norm is a social rule that has the two
because there exists institutional sequencing is a starting point, not a finishing one. dressed is, “Has divorce taken place in this fami­
norms. (D.l, 2, 3, 8; A.l) While we cannot present research to demon- ly?” (versus a previous family of procreation, such
dimensions of a social expectation and
P.2. Role relationships within the family change
behavior. strate the strength of our reconccptualization, we as the flrst marriage). For the institutional level
with the family stage. (D.l, 5, 6,)
D.6. A role is coraposed of all of the norms
P.3. Family development is duration dependent
feel obligated, nevertheless, to provide some indi- one asks, “What norms and roles apply to indi­
attached to a specific position. cation of how we envision the application of the viduals, relationships, and families who have expe-
because there exists institutional timing
D.7. A timing norm is a processual norm for when
norms. (D.l, 3, 7; A.1) revised theory Space prohibits a detailed discus- rienced divorce?” (normative expectations). But
an event or stage is to be experienced by an
individual, relationship, or family group. (This
P.4. Role relationships develop over time, in part, sion of all of the many aspccts of the family career institutional level questions also include ones
as a function of family stages. (D. 1, 4, 5, 6, 7, that are revealed by the theoretical formulation. about aggregate data in a society such as, “What is
is in general measured by comparing the age
8; P. 2) Nevertheless, recalling the criteria that guided our the divorce rate among childless couples?” (nor­
and stage expectations and behavior for the
P.5. The normative demands of any given
individual, relationship, and family to revision—a nonteleological, stochastic, and dy- mative behavior).
institution must be in line with
establish whether the unit is "on-time” or namic model allowing multilevel analysis of mutu-
the maturation of the individual. (D.7, 8, 9;
“off-time.”) ally exclusivc and exhaustive family career Transitional Events and Stages
A.2, A.2.1)
D.8. A sequencing norm is a processual norm for
P6. The normative demands of any given stages—we will attempt to sketch an approach to
the order in which events and stages are to Our point of departure in tracing this devel­
be experienced by an individual, relationship,
institution must be in line with the stage of a specific sequence of family career stages that
the family, otherwise the family is strained. opmental sequence is the family stage that pre-
or family. (This is measured by the will show' what we intend to accomplish.
(D.7, 8, 9; A.2, A.2.2, A.2.3) cedes the transitional event leading to divorce.
conformity or deviance for a sequence of
P7. The sum total of normative demands for all Our concern about mutually exclusive stage cate-
events or stages from the modal sequence.) The Divorce Developmental
D.9. Other institutions are composed of the norms institutions at any one point in time cannot gories arises at once. While divorce applies to
regulating specific areas of social life such as overload the capacity of individuals or groups Sequence: An Analytical Sketch only one relationship—the marital relationship—
work, rclighion, education, polity, etc. without creating social deviance (cross- it may occur in a number of family stages. Figure 2
D.10. The conjunction of one institution s timing normative strain). (A.2, A.2.1, A.2.2, A.2.3; Since institutional procedures for the sever-
presents some divorce family stage sequences.
norms with another institution’s are called D.9, 10, 11) ance of the marital bond are so nearly universal,
P8. Institutional normative adaptation is preceded There could be others, for example, those associ-
cross-institutional timing norms. divorce (or its equivalent) while not popular is
by systematic behavioral deviance. (A.2, A.2.1, ated with divorce in second or subsequent raar-
D. 11. The conjunction of one institution’s normative. This is so in both senscs—as an expec­
sequencing norms with another institution’s A.2.3; D.12) (Modell, 1980) riages or in other plurality patterns.
tation and as a behavior. Thus, even where there
are called cross-institutional sequencing There are three transitional events that come
exist variations on the theme that marriage should
norms. to mind immediately as relevant to the divorce
continue “until death do us part,” there also exist
D, 12. Institutional normative adaptation is when developmental sequence; marital separation, rec-
the norms of one institution are brought into propositions are empirical propositions based on explicit normative structures for the dissolution of
onciliation, and divorce. The key point to notice
alignment and articulation with the norms of both an empirical regularity and logical consisten- marriage. Divorce may not be prescribed or even
at this juncture is that each stage following a tran­
some other institution(s). cy with the theory. There are few such empirical preferred, but neither is it gcnerally prohibited.
sitional event represents a different family struc­
Axioms propositions stated since the goal here is to pre­ Indeed, divorce is an excellent example of a nor­
A.l. The process of family development is
ture than the one preceding the transitional event.
sent the most basic propositions of the theory that mative structure that permits a certain outcome
modeled by a semi-Markov model (see Note Essentially all other aspects of the process are as-
are necessarily mainly definitions, axioms, and de­ under clearly understood normative conditions.
26). sociated with one or more of the levels of analysis
rived propositions. In addition, readers should We think the explanation of the cause of di­
A.2. When an institution’s timing and sequencing to which we now turn.
norms do not articulate with those of other take special note of the level of analysis for which vorce—in an individual relationship or in a soci-
institutions (cross-institutional), then: the proposition is intended as appropriate. Deriva- ety-—takes a secondary place to an explanation of
how the family moves through the family stage Institutional Level
A.2.1. Individuals experience contradictory tions may move from one level to another, but this
is usually a rcsult of a major premise about institu­ sequences related to divorce. We emphasize that Recall that the institution of marriage and the
{continued) tions and there being deductions to lower levels 'his sketch will take a stochastic probability form, family contains process and static norms about
Bi:
f CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 247

a seminar directed by the


farnily life. Some of these norms are antithetical to may well be cumulative so that the long-term ef­
■P divorce such as “until death do us part.” Other fect is later marital disruption, as suggested by
■r
Mptv less formalized norms contain expectations about Hogan (1978), Morgan and Rindfuss (1985), and
dje reasonable amount of time before having chil- White (1987).
m f
dren or the reasonable amount of time to stay

i wdth an alcoholic spouse. These norms supply tim­


ing expectations given contingencies in the fami-
Group Level

Figure 10-2. Some examples of separation and divorce stage sequences. [This flgure was developed independendy as a result of discussions in
B ' ly. Often, complex sets of these norms must be The structural aspects of the role relation-
constructed in order to understand divorce. For ships are succinctly captured in the structural dia­
example, should one get divorced (a generally un- gram of farnily stages set out above. First, there is
f:
l|
favorable outcome) if one’s spouse is a chronic
(duration) alcoholic, a child abuser, and no longer
a farnily provider? These contingency norms are
not just one stage from which all divorces ema-
nate. All farnily stages where there is a marital
relationship have some probability of divorce. We
what all farnily members appeal to in justifying (as think the probability depends, in part, on the ex­
m *
IJl well as interpreting) divorce to others, that is, that act stage and the duration in that stage. Second,
it is indeed a normative and expected event. This there is not just one stage that follows the event of
discussion suggests that under some conditions a divorce. Rather, divorce as a farnily event may
3ÊSS divorce is an expectation and a behavioral pattern. change the structure of the farnily in a myriad of
i Indeed, normative deviance supplies an cffec- ways. For example, one farnily may practice joint
tive explanation for divorce as an aggregate phe- custody and another sole custody. Recall in the
nomenon. The sequencing and timing of farnily, discussion of relationships that such stage struc-
relationship, or individual stages might be off-time tures indicate the degree to which certain norms

I
I
: £ k
or out of sequence due to either a random event
or prolonged duration in stage. For example, Mor­
'■ gan and Rindfuss (1985) report that the sequenc­
and roles may be followed. Furthermore, the
norms that apply to the incumbents in each stage
are largely responsible for the relationship he­
ing of conception, birth, and wedding has an effect rween divorce and stage variables. For example,
on later marital disruptions. In this case, the se­ the norms in a farnily who have launched their
I: quencing of these events has both an immediate
nonnormative (deviance) effect suggested by the
children, but are not yet reinforced by the grand-
parental roles, are somewhat similar to the struc­
| norms against out-of-wedlock births and a longer- ture of the early marital dyad. However, there are
term effect of throwing off other farnily, rela­ process norms that reinforce the view that this is
t
authors. For a similar approach, see Eichler (1988, Fig. 4, p. 29)1

oo
r tionship, and individual stage sequences and tim­
ing later in life.
Another important aspect to farnily norms is
K the effect of cross-institutional norms. Sometimes
indeed a transitional stage for the farnily and con-
tinued interaction with the children may serve to
further reinforce both the old farnily roles as well
as promise the ascendancy of the grandparental
I a group or individual may find that the norms roles. Thus, the process norms may in part con­
; ; from one institution contradict the norms from struct a more stable dyad than in early marriage
15 another institution, such as the expectation that because they are more fully immersed in the fami-
iï.
children come after a few years of marriage and ly normative context and farnily history.
the expectation that a prolonged educational
commitment and a First job be completed before
Relationship Level
having children. In such cases, satisfying one set of
expectations is counter to satisfying the other set. It is worth recalling that the analysis is
Indeed, where such contrary cross-institutional focused on events (divorce and separation) rather
norms are the case, we would expect a greater than stages. Divorce, like separation or reconcilia-
number of divorces. Furthermore, it might also be tion, is an event that is a transition point from one
IS mat cross-institutional timing norms delay the stage to another. At the relationship level of analy­
I■ M
S' 3 timing of farnily stages or occupational career sis, these events mark the transition from one
13 ; 5m stages, thus putting the farnily, relationship, or in­ stage to another for the marital relationship. The
dividual out of synchrony (off-time) with other duration in the particular marital relationship is
! eross-institutional or institutional demands. The related to the event of divorce in that the proba­
T effect of such off-time farnily or individual careers bility for a divorce is greatest during the early
l: I

m 246
|
I
248 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%0
CHAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 249

years of marriage. However, this fact, although as- tially for the mother—son, mother—daughter ment, history, and experience. So, for example, tal approach as providing important insights for
sociated with individual measures such as the mar- father-son, father—daughter, and sibling relation­ the ages of the children may assist in understand- their work. We believe that our reformulation can
ital satisfaction of the individuals or individual re­ ships. We can deal with all of these simultaneously mg their individual feelings about the separation, continue to do so; indeed, it does so with consid-
sources, is not explained by these factors at the with the family stage (group level). However, it is reconciliation, and divorce transitions, since erably more precision and potential insight. We
dyadic relationship level. Rather, what the high also possible to analyze the stage changes for each something will be known of their cognitive, emo- would recommend a general approach of the fol­
divorce rate for shorter-duration marriages sug- dyad, triad, and so on up to level of the family tional, and socia) developmental characteristics. It lowing kind.
gests is that there is something about the particu- group, The identification of coalitions with the will also help explain feelings of parents vis a vis We have emphasized that all transitions are
lar relationship stage of marriage from which divorcing father or with the mother shed light on their children’s responses to these events. And, of not family developmental transitions. Thus, at the
these people are exiting. The marital relationship the changes in interaction in these relationships. course. if the ages of the individual parents are outset it seems important to us for the practi-
added to the data, the explanatory ability is ex- tioner to determine whether the “presenting
has stages as does the family group. However, the The ability of incumbents in the various role rela­
panded. It would make a difference, presumably, if problem” is in fact one that falls within the con-
identification of these stages of marriage has been tionships to interact in ways that follow the norms
less emphasized by scholars than those of the fam­ for these relationships is affected by the degree of the parents were 19 and 18 years of age and their fines of family development. That is, they should
ily group. In part, this has been due to a rcliance physical access (domicile). Thus, custody and ac- children were 2 and 1 compared with parents begin by looking for either a developmental tran­
on static marital typologies rather than dynamic cess enter as structural variables into these dyadic who were 45 and 44 with children 18 and 16. sitional event or family stage as the context within
These kinds of variables are the stuff of indi­ which the problem can be located. Having done
analyses. and triadic relationships and, in part, structure
vidual psychological theory and practice more this, three basic questions appear to us to follow
We cannot fully describe the marital stages. how anomie these relationships become in post-
However, we can at least characterize these early divorce relationship stages. than they are of a social psychological or so- from developmental theory:
marriages. One possible way of depicting early ciological understanding. The kinds of cxplana-
1. Is the event or stage out of sequence?
marriage as a relationship stage is as the qualita- tions available at the individual level that are rele­
Individual Level 2. Is the event or stage off-time (either in terms
tively distinct period between the events of the vant to family development theory appear to us to
of duration—too short or too long—or
wedding and the birth or adoption of the first The principal concepts for analyzing divorce be quite limited. This may only be because we are
being early or late)?
child. Early marriage would be a stage delineated at the individual level of analysis from the the- not competent in the field of psychology. We are
3. Is there some cross-institutional misalign-
by structural variables and qualitatively distinct oretical perspective of family development are the aware, of course, that the thcrapeutic professional
ment involved in the event or stage
interactional variables. The early marriage stage is individual’s perception of his or her role enact- community has spent a great deal more effort in
circumstance?
a dyad. It may be argued [following Caplow ment, perception of the spouse’s role enactment, thinking through the conceptual and treatment
(1968) and others] that the dyad is inherently and pcrceptions of norms favoring divorce and approaches to these maners. Consequently, they And, of course, the practitioner must ask at what
unstable. Since there is no possibility for coali- those antithetical to divorce. These variables con- are in a much better position to suggest explana- level or levels of analysis the “problem” is being
tions, only negotiations can resolve disputes. So tain many bidden normative dimensions, such as tions of this behavior than are we. In that regard, exhibited. We are quite aware that there are other
the first factor predisposing early marriages to di­ the duration of time one will tolerate an abusive we would note there has been increasing interest implications for the applied professions to our re­
vorce and separation is the structure of this rela­ relationship or the duration of time one will toler­ in family development theory in that field, es- formulation. We shall be quite anxious to see what
tionship stage, ate the perception that the relationship is un- pecially in the clinical branch. Writers such as Car­ sorts of thinking in these communities our work
A second factor is the complex set of norms gratifying. Many such analyses have already been ter and McGoldrick (1988), Combrinck-Graham may precipitate.
applicable to the relationship at this stage. The completed under the rubric of event transitions (1985), Golan (1983), and most recently Falicov
relationship in North America is expected to be and marital satisfaction (e g., Belsky & Rovine, (1988) have used family eyele ideas to address Summary
romantic, yet traditional role relationships are 1990; Belsky et al., 1985; Menaghan, 1983, 1989) psychotherapeutic issues—and not only at the in­
clearly defined by the society. In addition, the nor- and individual life course contingencies (Aldous, dividual level. Falicov’s (1988, pp. 3—51) attempt The preceding sketch does not attempt to
to integrale family sociological and family thera- address all the variables that might explain di­
mative content for this marital stage requires neo- 1978). Such analyses are typificd by their exam-
locality and contains a strong preference that it ination of variables over the individual’s life peutic approaches to family development is es- vorce at the various levels of analysis. This sketch
lead to having children. In the past few decades, course or a sequence of individual events not ncc- pecially stimulating. Her discussion, along with does attempt to identify some of the ways that the
these norms have been effectively challenged by cssarily shared by the other spouse. Many of these chapters by other authors, promises to make more theory of family development would explain di­
changes in other institutions such as education variables might explain why an individual reaches therapists aware of this approach to family under­ vorce at each level. The theory can provide the
standing. Our reading of that book, however, ieads most complete explanation when all of these lev­
and work. The result of this challenge has meant a decision to separate or divorce a spouse.
In order to locate our family member more us to observe that there are a number of confu- els are tied together in a complete picture. The
that the most structurally vulnerable marital stage
has also lost much of its normative buttressing. In prccisely in the family context, a piece of indi­ sions in the levels of analysis that we believe will present sketch does not do this but should suggest
not assist the comprehension of this complex some of the richness that a multileveled stochastic
effect, for many early marriages the relationship vidual Information assists us: the ages of the chil­
process. theory can provide family scholars.
state approached anomie. Whether or not this is dren (as contrasted with the age of a relationship
While we recognizc our expertise in the ther-
cohort specific or a lasting change is yet to be or duration of a family stage). The children’s ages
will assist us in explaining a number of individual apeutic and family life education areas is severely
determined.
A good many divorces occur in marriages where responses of family members to the transitional
lirnited, we have some suggestions for practi- Conclusion
fioners in both of these communities who may
there are other sets of relationships so that the events of interest. Note, however, that these re­
view with some dismay our reconceptualization, We said at the outset that we believed family
event of the divorce represents a change of stage sponses are characteristics less associated with
Many of them have come to view the devclopmen- development was in a state of gridlock. In the past
not only for the marital relationship but poten- family development than with individual develop-
250 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%() CHARTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 251
the theory of family development did not supply largely responsible for the ease or stress which observatiens for interobserver reliability as we for change that are exogenous to the scope of the
the contemporary family scholar with a systematic individuals, relationships, and families encounter would do with any other two observers of a theory. In the end, we believe that trading global
set of ideas that could be used to analyze and when following normative paths and transitions phenomenon. applicability for explanatory power is good scien­
cxplain family developmental processes. Two con­ The systematic behavioral nonconformity to pro- In the past, many scholars have viewed the tiflc strategy.
sistent problems have plagued research uslng a cessual or static norms by a suffïciently large ag- operationalization of family stages as being largely All of these changes provide family develop­
family development perspective. One is that the gregate of people brings about changes in the ex- the choice of the researcher (Rodgers, 1973). This mental scholars with challenges. However, the ul-
resulting correlations with dependent variables pectations about positions, roles, relationships has led to a multitude of stage conceptions lacking timate challenge is to determine if today’s family
are modest at best (Mattessich & Hill, 1987). The and family stages. Hence, family development is a true comparability and frustrating the accumula- scholars are prepared to put the same effort into
second problem has been that the theory failed to process that is regulated by the norms within the tion of flndings (e.g., four stages in Olson et al, family development theory as were those early
offer any theoretical deductions or predictive institution of the family but is affected by the artic­ 1988; five in Anderson et al, 1983; and seven for scholars who so carefully cultivated and nurtured
power and, hence, explanatory power. Further, in ulation between family and other social insti­ Spanier et al, 1979). This also means that we nev- the ideas that we continue to believe can bear
the last two decades the theory of family develop­ tutions. er know whether variance between flndings is due much explanatory fruit. We are optimistic.
ment, in addition to its traditional confusion with With the revisions we propose, we think that to methodological artifacts or to some non-
child development ideas, became confused with the family development framework meets the cri­ methodologlcal effect. Some important reasons for Acknowledgments. The authors gratefiilly ac-
several other time-oriented approaches such as in- teria of a social scientiflc theory. We have taken using the proposed stage conception include: knowledge the critical comments on an earlier
dividual life course, event history analyses, and considerable care to provide a consistent set of version of this chapter from students in the Family
cohort analyses. definitions on which to build the basic assump- 1. The presence or absence of a family position
Development Seminar at the University of British
More importantly, however, what compels us tions of the theory. Decades of critiques have sen- helps us deduce the roles and norms that
Columbia as wek as the comments from anony-
to believe that the criticisms can no longer be sitized us to the implications of certain assump- may be operating within a stage (clearly, if
mous reviewers. We would also like to acknowl-
ignored is the more recent suggestion of Scanzoni tions of the older theory, such as those of a there is no incumbent in a family position,
edge the encouragement and support we received
and his colleagues (Scanzoni, 1988; Scanzoni et al, teleological and deterministic nature. The result­ dien the norms, roles, and relationships at-
from the editors of this volume and speciflcally
1989) that the study of the “family” as a group or ing assumptions and derivative propositions are at tached to that position are not opera-
from the editor with whom we worked most
institution be revlsed as the study of personal or least clear and disconfirmable. Most importantly, tional).27
closely, William Doherty. Finally, we would like to
close relationships. Although these authors envi- we have identifled a mathematical model as iso- 2. These stages are not only comparable be­
thank our wives, Maria and Robin, who serve as
sion a “developmental” perspective on primary morphic with our theoretical notion of family de­ tween researchers but are applicable cross-
both gentle critics and stalwart supporters.
relationships, they see the family development ap- velopment. The stage conception we suggest is culturally.
proach as essentially useless. In many respects, we both exhaustive and exclusive and therefore can 3. This stage conception avoids the pitfall of
agree with their critique of these concepts, but be used in testing the model of family develop­ assuming that one event indicates one stage
believe that the solution they propose essentially (cf. Fig. 2 for a clear demonstration of this). References
ment. The next step is for researchers to establish
throws out the baby with the bathwater. Our revi- the parameters of this model and to carefully ex- This reconceptualization on flrst impression Adams, B. N. (1988). Fifty years of family research: What
sion attempts to address these issues without sacri- amine the claim that we can predict the proba- may appear to be complex and unnecessarily de- does it mean? Journal of Marriage and the Family, 50,
ficing some of the rudimentary insights contained bilities for stage transitions. tailed. However, the process that we are attempt- 5-17.
in the original family development approach. Empirically, there is much to be done. How­ ing to model is complex and requires a detailed Ahrons, C, R., & Rodgers, R. H. (1987). Divorcedfamilies: A
Substantively, the rcvised theory suggests ever, it is important that theoretical propositions multidisciplinary developmental view. New York:
formulation to capture it. The model does not pre­
that not all family change is developmental. In are correctly operationalized. First, it is necessary Norton.
sent a precisely determined world moving for- Aldous, J. (1978). Family careers: Developmental change
addition, change needs to be viewed in substan- that the unit of observation correspond to the ap- ward in a lockstep march that can be easily ap- in families. New York: Wiley.
tially different ways at each level of analysis: the propriate level of analysis in the theory. The family prehended. At the same time, the reconceptualiza­ Allison, P. D. (1984). Event history analysis: Regression for
individual, the relationship, the family group, and level offers some difficulties. We do not recom- tion is somewhat more modest in its claims. It longitudinal event data Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
the institution of the family. Indeed, the structures mend the approach that in some way sums indi­ does not offer an explanation for all family group, Anderson. S. A., Russell, C. S., & Schumm, W. R. (1983).
of each of these levels are distinctly different. Fam­ vidual family members’ scores into a family score relationship, and member behavior, but prin- Perceived marital quality and family life-cycle categories;
ily development is deflned as the process where (Wakers et al., 1984; White, 1984), Although A further analysis. Journal of Marriage and the Family,
cipally directs attention to the process of family
the probability of a transition to a family stage such approaches may be predictive of occur- 45, 127-139.
development. It is recognized in the reconcep­ Angell, R. C. (1936). Thefamily encounters the depression.
depends on both the current stage and the dura- rences to family members, these predictions have tualization that there are other types and sources New York; Scribner’s.
tion of time spent in that stage. Family develop­ the weakness of being the result of individual Bates, F. L. (1956). Position, role and status: A reformulation
ment is stage dependent because there are institu- scores composing the summative score (multi- 27Boss’s (Boss, 1980a,b, 1983, 1987; Boss & Greenberg, of concepts, Social Farces, 34, 313-321.
tional sequencing norms. The process is duration colinearity) and common living conditions of fam­ 1984) analyses with regard to “psychological presence” Belsky, J., & Rovine, M. (1990). Patterns of marital change
dependent because there are institutional timing ily members (spuriousness). Individual histories and “psychological absence,” for example, are enhanced across the transition to parenthood: Pregnancy to three
norms. These processual norms change over time are often used as proxies for family histories (Bur- by this conceptualization. We should be able to deter- years poslpartum. Journal of Marriage and the Family,
mine more clearly which aspects of family stress under 52, 5-19.
to align themselves with the processual norms in ch, 1985; Sweet et al, 1988). We think it is wise to
such circumstances are truiy a developmental conse- Belsky, J., Spanier, G. B., & Rovine, M. (1983). Stability and
other institutions. The degree of articulation with- use at least two family members as “reporters” on quence and which are the consequence of other vari­ change in marriage across the transition to parenthood.
in this cross-institutional normative fabric is the family’s career and assess their retrospective ables. In addition, see Menaghan (1989). Journal of Marriage and the Family, 45, 567-577.
254 PART V FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1%0 CRAPTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 255
Spanier, G. B., Sauer, W., & Larzelere, R. (1979). An em- Walters,)., & Jewson, R, (1988). National Council on Fam
pirical evaluation of the family life cycle. Journal ofMar- ily Relations: A fifty year history: 1938-1987. St. Pau|
riage and the Family, 41, 27—38. MN; National Council on Family Relations.
Sweet, L, Bumpass, L, & Call, V. (1988). The design and Walters, L. H., Pittman, J„ & Norrell, J. E. (1984). Develop.
content of the National Survey of Families and House-
holds. Madison: University of Wisconsin, Center for De-
ment of a quantitative measure of a family ffom self-rc APPLICATION
ports of family members. Journal of Family Issues 5
mography and Ecology. 497-514.
Teachman, J. D., & Polonko, K. A. (1984). Out of sequence: White, H. C. (1963). An anatomy of kinship. Englewood
The timing of marriage following a premarital birth. Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Social Forces, 63, 245-260. White, J. M. (1984). Not the sum of its parts. Journal of
Thomas, D. L, & Wilcox, J. E. (1987). The rise of family
theory. In M, B. Sussman & S. K. Steinmetz (Eds.),
Family Issues, 5, 515-518.
White, J. M. (1987), Researching developmental careers-
Family Development Theory as
Handbook of marriage and the family (pp, 81-102).
New York: Plenum.
Trost,), (1974). The family life cycle—An impossibie con­
The career conformity scs\c. Journal ofFamily Issues 8
306-318, Revlsed by Rodgers and White
White, J. M. (1988, November). Problems with the nor-
cept? International Journal of Sociology of the Family,
4, 37-47.
mative model offamily development. Paper presented
at the Annual Meetings of the National Council on Family
ImpSications for Practice
Trost, J. (1977). The family life cycle; A problematic con­ Relations, Theory Construction and Methodology Work­
cept. In J. Cuisenier (Ed.), The family life cycle in Euro- shop. Philadelphia, PA.
pean societies (pp. 467-481). The Hague: Mouton. White,). M. (1991), Dynamics offamily development: The Candyce S. Russel!
Tuma, N. B., & Hannan, M. T. (1984). Social dynamics. New theory offamily development. New York; Guilford.
York: Academie Press. White, ). M., & Reid, N. (1984, October). Modeling the
Turner, R. H. (1962). Role-taking: Process vs. certainty. In A. family career: Theoretical and methodological issues in
M. Rosé (Ed.), Human behavior and social process (pp. the application of stochastic models to the developmen­
20—40). Boston; Houghton-Mifflin. tal theory of the family. Paper presented at the Annual Rodgers and White have described the impact of family development theory on em-
Wallet, W., & Hill, R. (1951). The family: A dynamic in- Meetings of the National Council on Family Relations. San
terpretation (rev. ed.). New York: Dryden Press.
pirical research to date as “minimal.” Admittedly, the percent of variance in dependent
Francisco, CA.
variables explained by the family life cycle concept has not been impressive, generally
less than 10%. Yet practitioners have used concepts from the family development
approach to normalize stressful family expehence and to think about continuity and
change across time. Developmental concepts have an innate appeal to clients and
offer an acceptable alternative frame for many problems in family relationships (Carter
& McGoldrick, 1989; Falicov, 1988).
Themes of continuity and discontinuity across time offer a context for forgiveness
(we aren’t the only ones who have faced this) and for hopefulness (development
involves “ups” as well as “downs”). Yet frequently the stressful transitions with which
applied family professionals are most concerned do not appear in the classic family life
cycle categories, especially transitions involving separation, divorce, and the incorpor-
tion of adult children (and possibly their children) into the household of the family of
origin. Nor are the significant “players" always the ones identified in the earlier version
of family development theory.
The revision of family development theory offered by Rodgers and White allows
for variations in family life that more closely parallel the experiences of a culturally
diverse population. The genogram-type notation used by Rodgers and White is a
familiar one to family therapists (e.g., McGoldrick & Gearson, 1985). By focusing on
both household and kinship ties, this notation system allows us to identify such im­
portant players as stepparents, noncustodial parents, and former spouses. However,
the expehence of family therapists regarding the significant role frequently played
by “nonevolved grandmothers,” fictive kin, and boyfriends (Boyd-Franklin, 1980;
McGoldrick & Carter, 1982) would point to the usefulness of expanding the notation
system to three generations and to including persons who function in important ways
within the family even though they may not live in one household or be related by blood
or marriage.

Candyce S. Russell • Department of Human Development and Family Studies, Kansas State
University, Manhattan, Kansas 66506.
256 PART V • FAMILY THEORIES AND METHODS EMERGING DURING 1946-1960 CHARTER 10 • FAMILY DEVELOPMENT THEORY 257
The earlier focus on stages and developmental tasks has given way to a focus on for family life educators than for family therapists, though it is rarely easy for any
transitions and transitional events that, regardless of institutional norms, may occur in helper. Clients come to family therapists because something has gone wrong; some-
11 ï
an unspecified order. Rodgers’ and White’s revision of family deveiopment theory one in the family has a symptom and/or relationships have become unsatisfying.
suggests a shift to a less deterministic understanding of famiiy deveiopment. They These families have learned something about the unpredictability of life. They know
have introduced the concept of “stochastic processes” to the family deveiopment that even though they work hard and are well-intentioned, things may not turn out as
model. Bateson (1972) defines a stochastic process as a sequence of events that 1 they wish. Family life educators serve a different population—one that has yet to define
combine a “random component with a selective process, so that only certain out- and own a problem. The clients of family life educators are interested in preparing for
comes of the random are allowed to endure” (p. 253). In this instance, what is “selec­ the future. The clients of family life educators want to believe in predictability. They
tive” is contribuled by that which family deveiopment theory attempts to explain and want to believe that they can plan for a specific outcome, if only they work hard enough
predict: transitions and transitional events. at it.
Using this new theory of family deveiopment, certain variables, such as years Helping inexperienced couples and families to accept a realistic level of unpredict­
married and age of the partners, may help us predict the likelihood of some transition ability in family life may be the biggest challenge of the family life educator using
occurring. Family therapist Combrinck-Graham (1985, 1988) suggests that the family Rodgers’s and White’s reformulation of family deveiopment theory. It will mean replac-
spirals through a pattern of centripetal and centrifugal movement. Furthermore, when ing the comfort provided by a finite list of “developmental tasks” to accomplish with an
three generations are included in that picture, the coincidence of transitions (such as appreciation for the challenge inherent in confronting a number of hurdles that are both
adolescence, midlife reevaluation, and retirement) suggests some commonality similar to and different from those confronted by other families. Family life educators
across the generations within one family system. The constraints offered by the simul- will need to work first on shifting the expectations of clients and then will need to focus
taneous “spiraling” in the three-generational system may be an additional factor that on those relationship skills that will assist partners in working toward temporary end
presses toward and helps to select the timing of a new transition in family life. points that are difficult to define. This puts the family life educator in a position of
The work of Rodgers and White suggests that variables such as the ones de- offering less in the way of content but more in the way of “expectational set” and
scribed above may play a role in timing transitions and transitional events. However, it problem-solving skills. Any model of family deveiopment that accepts a large degree of
would appear that Rodgers and White are less likely to try to predict the specific unpredictability will confront the practitioner with the limits of his or her own ability to
outcome of a family transition. Inherent in this shift is an acceptance of a certain level help. It will confront each of us with our tendency to “overfunction” as helpers and will
I ;
of unpredictability in family life that wilt not be unfamiliar to family therapists (e.g., force us to find ways to shift the locus of responsibility to our dient families.
Boscolo, et al., 1987; Hoffman, 1990; White & Epston, 1990). This shift from a focus on ïi j|# I
sequencing to a focus on timing suggests an increasing interest in understanding the
process that eventuates in any one of several outcomes. 1. References
To date, applied professionals working from the family deveiopment approach |
f i.
have been much more likely to take their cues from the age of children in the family
than to think about the process that evolves from being a couple of “x” years’ duration
|l: Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of the mind. New York: Ballantine Books.
Boscolo, L, Ceechin, G., Hoffman, L, & Penn, P. (1987). Milan systemic family therapy: Conversations
or that evolves from being an intergenerational family group that is coexperiencing les s in theory and practice. New York; Basic Books.
certain life challenges. Family deveiopment theory has not really had the tools to study H
H I:
Boyd-Franklin, N. (1990). Empowering black families. Presentation af annual meeting of the American
deveiopment within marriage or the intergenerational system in a way that does not Association for Marriage and Family Therapy, Washington, D.C., October.
overfocus on the maturation of children. Hopefully, future research inspired by family Carter, B., & McGoldrick, M. (1989). The changing family life cycle: A framework for famiiy therapy.
Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
deveiopment theory will help us to understand more about the process of change in
Wk Combrinck-Graham, L. (1985). A developmental model for family systems. Family Process, 24(2), 139-
marriage and family groups that is not necessarily dependen! on the age of children but 150.
is developmental in nature. Combrinck-Graham, L, (1988). Adolescent sexuality in the family life spiral. In C. Falicov (Ed.), Family
'
Rodgers and White are clear that the level of analysis in family deveiopment : transitions: Continuity and change over the life cycle (pp. 107-131). New York: Guilford.
theory is not the individual, but the relationship. The Creative use of family deveiop­ Falicov, C. (1988). Family transitions: Continuity and change over the life cycle. New York: Guilford.
ment theory together with family systems theory may help us make progress toward
|1 Hoffman, L. (1990). Constructing realities: An art of lenses. Family Process, 29(1), 1-12.
af: McGoldrick, M., & Carter, B. (1982). The famiiy life cycle. In F. Walsh (Ed.), Normal family processes
understanding more about the relationship process involved in developmental change.
(chap. 7). New York; Guilford.
By integrating famiiy deveiopment theory and systems theory, we may be able to McGoldrick, M., & Gearson, R. (1985). Genograms in family assessment. New York: Norton.
understand more about symptoms as attempts to “jump start,” “slow down,” or other- Russell, C. (1988). Symptoms as regulators of distance and change. Journal of Psychotherapy and the
wise regulate the process of developmental change within the system (e.g., Carter & Family, 4(1-2), 79-91.
i
;
McGoldrick, 1989; Falicov, 1988; Russell, 1988).
The shift to a less deterministic, more stochastic model of family deveiopment will
assist the family life professional in assuming the role of consultant and resisting a
tendency to anticipate a specific sequence in the deveiopment of marriages and fami­

| White, M., & Epston, D. (1990). Uterate means to therapeutic ends. New York: Norton,

I
lies. The helper becomes an expert on the process of negotiating transitions, but is
less oriented toward a specific outcome. The family practitioner thereby assumes a
role that is respectful of the family within its own developmental and cultural context.
Increasing acceptance for a certain level of unpredictability may be more difficult

You might also like