You are on page 1of 17

Personality and Social Psychology Review Copyright © 1999 by

1999, Vol. 3, No. 3, 193 209 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

Moral Disengagement in the Perpetration of Inhumanities


Albert Bandura
Department of Psychology
Stanford University

Moral agency is manifested in both the power to refrain from behaving inhumanely
and the proactive power to behave humanely. Moral agency is embedded in a broader
sociocognitive self theory encompassing self-organizing, proactive, self-reflective,
andself-regulatory mechanisms rooted in personal standards linked to self-sanctions.
The self-regulatory mechanisms governing moral conduct do not come into play un-
less they are activated, and there are many psychosocial maneuvers by which moral
self-sanctions are selectively disengaged from inhumane conduct. The moral disen-

gagement may center on the cognitive restructuring of inhumane conduct into a be-
nign or worthy one by moral justification, sanitizing language, and advantageous
comparison; disavowal ofa sense ofpersonal agency by diffusion or displacement of
responsibility; disregarding or minimizing the injurious effects of one 's actions; and
attribution ofblame to, and dehumanization of those who are victimized. Many inhu-
manities operate through a supportive network oflegitimate enterprises run by other-
wise considerate people who contribute to destructive activities by disconnected sub-
division offunctions and diffusion of responsibility. Given the many mechanisms for
disengaging moral control, civilized life requires, in addition to humane personal
standards, safeguards built into social systems that uphold compassionate behavior
and renounce cruelty.

The disengagement of moral self-sanctions from confined mainly to cognitions about morality. An
inhumane conduct is a growing human problem at agentic theory specifies the mechanisms by which
both individual and collective levels. In a recent book people come to live in accordance with moral stan-
entitled Everybody Does It, Gabor (1994) docu- dards. In social cognitive theory (Bandura, 1986,
mented the pervasiveness of moral disengagement in 1991), moral reasoning is translated into actions
all walks of life. Psychological theories of morality through self-regulatory mechanisms rooted in moral
focus heavily on moral thought to the neglect of standards and self-sanctions by which moral agency
moral conduct. People suffer from the wrongs done is exercised. The moral self is thus embedded in a
to them regardless of how perpetrators might justify broader, sociocognitive self theory encompassing
their inhumane actions. The regulation of humane self-organizing, proactive, self-reflective, and self-
conduct involves much more than moral reasoning. A regulative mechanisms. These self-referent processes
complete theory of moral agency must link moral provide the motivational as well as the cognitive reg-
knowledge and reasoning to moral action. This re- ulators of moral conduct.
quires an agentic theory of morality rather than one In early phases of development, conduct is largely
regulated by external dictates and social sanctions. In
Preparation of this article was supported by grants from the Grant the course of socialization, people adopt moral stan-
Foundation and the Spencer Foundation. dards that serve as guides and as major bases for
A major portion of this article was presented as the Karen Stone self-sanctions regarding moral conduct. In this
Memorial Lecture, Harvard University, April 1996. self-regulatory process, people monitor their conduct
Some sections of this article include revised, updated, and ex-
panded material from the book Social Foundations of Thought and and the conditions under which it occurs, judge it in
Action: A Social Cognitive Theory, 1986, Prentice-Hall; and the relation to their moral standards and perceived cir-
chapter entitled Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement in W. Reich cumstances, and regulate their actions by the conse-
(Ed.), Origins of Terrorism: Psychologies, Ideologies, Theologies, quences they apply to themselves. They do things
States ofMind, 1990, Cambridge University Press.
Requests for reprints should be sent to Albert Bandura, Depart- that give them satisfaction and build their sense of
ment of Psychology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305- self-worth. They refrain from behaving in ways that
2130. E-mail: bandura(psych.stanford.edu. violate their moral standards, because such conduct

193
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

will bring self-condemnation. The constraint of nega- maneuvers by which moral self-sanctions can be dis-
tive self-sanctions for conduct that violates one's engaged from inhumane conduct. Selective activation
moral standards and the support of positive and disengagement of personal control permit differ-
self-sanctions for conduct faithful to personal moral ent types of conduct by persons with the same moral
standards operate anticipatorily. In the face of situa- standards under different circumstances. Figure 1
tional inducements to behave in inhumane ways, peo- shows the points in the process of internal control at
ple can choose to behave otherwise by exerting which moral self-censure can be disengaged from
self-influence. Self-sanctions keep conduct in line reprehensible conduct. The disengagement may cen-
with personal standards. It is through the ongoing ex- ter on (a) the reconstrual of the conduct itself so it is
ercise of self-influence that moral conduct is moti- not viewed as immoral, (b) the operation of the
vated and regulated. This capacity for self-influence agency of action so that the perpetrators can mini-
gives meaning to moral agency. Self-sanctions mark mize their role in causing harm, (c) the consequences
the presence of moral oughts. that flow from actions, or (d) how the victims of mal-
The exercise of moral agency has dual as- treatment are regarded by devaluing them as human
pects-inhibitive and proactive. The inhibitive form is beings and blaming them for what is being done to
manifested in the power to refrain from behaving inhu- them. The sections that follow document how each of
manely. Theproactive form ofmorality is expressed in these types of moral disengagement functions in the
the power to behave humanely. In the latter case, indi- perpetration of inhumanities.
viduals invest their sense of self-worth so strongly in
humane convictions and social obligations that they
act against what they regard as unjust or immoral even Moral Justification
though their actions may incur heavy personal costs.
Failure to do what is right would incur self-devaluation One set of disengagement practices operates on the
costs. In this higher order morality, people do good cognitive reconstruction of the behavior itself. People
things as well as refrain from doing bad things. Rorty's do not ordinarily engage in harmful conduct until they
(1993) analysis of the moral self in terms of a so- have justified to themselves the morality of their ac-
cial-practice morality is another example of a theory tions. In this process ofmoral justification, detrimental
that highlights proactive morality rooted in social obli- conduct is made personally and socially acceptable by
gation rather than just the morality of inhibition. portraying it as serving socially worthy or moral pur-
Moral standards do not operate invariantly as in- poses. People then can act on a moral imperative and
ternal regulators of conduct, however. Self-regulatory preserve their view of themselves as moral agents
mechanisms do not come into play unless they are ac- while inflicting harm on others. Regional variations in
tivated, and there are many social and psychological the social sanctioning and use of violent means are pre-
................................ ................................

: MORAL JUSTIFICATION MINIMIZING, IGNORING, DEHUMANIZATION


: PALLIATIVE COMPARISON: : OR MISCONSTRUING THE : : ATTRIBUTION OF BLAME :
EUPHEMISTIC LABELING CONSEQUENCES
.............. .
..........
:. ...

:...........~~~~~.. . .. . . . . . ..

-~UN~A

..........................................

.............................................

DISPLACEMENT OF RESPONSIBILITY
DIFFUSION OF RESPONSIBILITY
................................................

Figure 1. Mechanism through which moral self-sanctions are selectively activated and disengaged from detrimental behavior at different
points in the self-regulatory process. From Social Foundations of Thought andAction: A Social Cognitive Theory (p. 376), by A. Bandura,
1986, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Copyright 1986 by Prentice Hall. Reprinted with permission.

194
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

dictable from moral justifications rooted in a ties lose much of their repugnancy. Soldiers "waste"
subcultural code of honor (Cohen & Nisbett, 1994). people rather than kill them. Bombing missions are
Rapid radical shifts in destructive behavior through described as "servicing the target," in the likeness of
moral justification are most strikingly revealed in mili- a public utility. The attacks become "clean, surgical
tary conduct (Kelman, 1973; Skeyhill, 1928). The con- strikes," arousing imagery of curative activities. The
version of socialized people into dedicated fighters is civilians whom the bombs kill are linguistically con-
achieved not by altering their personality structures, verted to "collateral damage." In an effort to sanitize
aggressive drives, or moral standards. Rather, it is ac- state executions, a U.S. senator proclaimed, "capital
complished by cognitively redefining the morality of punishment is our society's recognition of the sanc-
killing so that it can be done free from self-censure. tity of human life." This memorable verbal sanitiza-
Through moral justification of violent means, people tion won him the uncoveted third-place award in the
see themselves as fighting ruthless oppressors, protect- national Doublespeak competition.
ing their cherished values, preserving world peace, Sanitizing euphemisms also are used extensively in
saving humanity from subjugation, or honoring their unpleasant activities that people do from time to time.
country's commitments. Just war tenets were devised In the language of some government agencies, people
to specify when the use of violent force is morally jus- are not fired, they are given a "career alternative en-
tified. However, given people's dexterous facility for hancement," as though they were receiving a promo-
justifying violent means, all kinds of inhumanities get tion. Being "disfellowshipped" is getting one's self
clothed in moral wrappings. fired by the Baptists. In the Watergate hearings, lies
Voltaire put it well when he said, "Those who can became "a different version ofthe facts." An "involun-
make you believe absurdities can make you commit tary conversion of a 727" is a plain old airplane crash.
atrocities." Over the centuries, much destructive con- The television industry produces and markets some of
duct has been perpetrated by ordinary, decent people in the most brutal forms of human cruelty under the sani-
the name of righteous ideologies, religious principles, tized labels of "action and adventure" programming.
and nationalistic imperatives (Kramer, 1990; Rapoport The acid rain that is killing our lakes and forests is
& Alexander, 1982; Reich, 1990). Widespread ethnic merely "atmospheric deposition of anthropogenically
wars are producing atrocities of appalling proportions. derived substances." The nuclear power industry has
When viewed from divergent perspectives, the same created its own specialized set of euphemisms for the
violent acts are different things to different people. It is injurious effects of nuclear mishaps. An explosion be-
often proclaimed in conflicts of power that one group's comes an "energetic disassembly." A reactor accident
terroristic activity is another group's liberation move- is a "normal aberration."
ment fought by heroic fighters. This is why moral ap- The agentless passive style in depicting events
peals against violence usually fall on deaf ears. serves as another linguistic tool for creating the ap-
Adversaries sanctify their own militant actions but pearance that reprehensible acts are the work of name-
condemn those of their antagonists as barbarity mas- less forces rather than of people (Bolinger, 1982). It is
querading as outrageous moral reasoning. Each side as though people are moved mechanically but are not
feels morally superior to the other. really the agents of their own acts. Even inanimate ob-
jects are sometimes turned into agents. Here is a driver
explaining to police how he managed to demolish a
Euphemistic Labeling telephone pole: "The telephone pole was approaching.
I was attempting to swerve out ofits way when it struck
Language shapes thought patterns on which ac- my front end."
tions are based. Activities can take on very different The specialized jargon of a legitimate enterprise is
appearances depending on what they are called. Not also misused to lend respectability to an illegitimate
surprisingly, euphemistic language is widely used to one. In the vocabulary of the lawbreakers in Nixon's
make harmful conduct respectable and to reduce per- administration, criminal conspiracy became a "game
sonal responsibility for it. Euphemizing is an injuri- plan," and the conspirators were "team players," like
ous weapon. People behave much more cruelly when the best of sportsmen. They eLevated the word cor-
assaultive actions are verbally sanitized than when ruption to new heights in the service of criminal
they are called aggression (Diener, Dineen, Endresen, conduct.
Beaman, & Fraser, 1975).
In an insightful analysis of the language of
nonresponsibility, Gambino (1973) identified the dif- Advantageous Comparison
ferent varieties of euphemisms. One form relies on
sanitizing language. By camouflaging pernicious ac- Advantageous comparison is another way of mak-
tivities in innocent or sanitizing parlance, the activi- ing harmful conduct look good. How behavior is

195
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

viewed is colored by what it is compared against. By advocated a more interventionist course of action
exploiting the contrast principle, reprehensible acts when the international crisis was likened to another
can be made righteous. Terrorists see their behavior as Munich, representing political appeasement of Nazi
acts of selfless martyrdom by comparing them with Germany, than when it was likened to another Viet-
widespread cruelties inflicted on the people with nam, representing a disastrous military entanglement.
whom they identify. The more flagrant the contrasting Gilovich added a new twist to Santayana's adage that
inhumanities, the more likely it is that one's own de- those who forget the past are condemned to repeat it:
structive conduct will appear benevolent. For example, Those who see unwarranted likeness to the past are dis-
the massive destruction in Vietnam was minimized by posed to misapply its lessons.
portraying the American military intervention as sav- Cognitive restructuring of harmful conduct through
ing the populace from Communist enslavement. moral justifications, sanitizing language, and exonerat-
Expedient historical comparison also serves ing comparisons, taken together, is the most powerful
self-exonerating purposes. For example, apologists for set of psychological mechanisms for disengaging
the lawlessness of political figures they support cite moral control. Investing harmful conduct with high
transgressions by past rival administrations as vindica- moral purpose not only eliminates self-censure, but it
tions. Adapters of violent means are quick to point out engages self-approval in the service of destructive ex-
that democracies, such as those of France and the ploits. What was once morally condemnable becomes
United States, were achieved through violence against a source of self-valuation. Functionaries work hard to
oppressive rule. become proficient at them and take pride in their de-
Exonerating comparison relies heavily on moral structive accomplishments.
justification by utilitarian standards. The task of mak-
ing violence morally acceptable from a utilitarian per-
spective is facilitated by two sets of judgments. First, Displacement of Responsibility
nonviolent options are judged to be ineffective to
achieve desired changes, thus removing them from Moral control operates most strongly when people
consideration. Second, utilitarian analyses using ad- acknowledge that they cause harm by their detrimen-
vantageous comparisons with actual or anticipated tal actions. The second set of disengagement prac-
threats by one's adversaries affirm that one's injurious tices operates by obscuring or minimizing the
actions will prevent more human suffering than they agentive role in the harm one causes. People will be-
cause. The utilitarian cost-benefit calculus, however, have in ways they typically repudiate if a legitimate
can be quite slippery in specific applications. The fu- authority accepts responsibility for the effects of their
ture contains many uncertainties and ambiguities. Hu- conduct (Diener, 1977; Milgram, 1974). Under dis-
man predictive judgment is, therefore, subject to a lot placed responsibility, they view their actions as stem-
of biases (Nisbett & Ross, 1980). As a result, calcula- ming from the dictates of authorities; they do not feel
tions of long-term human costs and benefits are often personally responsible for the actions. Because they
suspect. There is much subjectivity in estimating the are not the actual agent of their actions, they are
gravity of potential threats. Moreover, violence is of- spared self-condemning reactions.
ten used as a weapon against small threats on the Self-exemption from gross inhumanities by dis-
grounds that they will escalate and spread to where placement of responsibility is most gruesomely re-
they will take a heavy toll on human suffering if left vealed in socially sanctioned mass executions. Nazi
unchecked. The frequently invoked "domino effect" prison commandants and their staffs divested them-
reflects this type of escalative projection concerning selves of personal responsibility for their unprece-
the likely course of events. Judgment of gravity justi- dented inhumanities (Andrus, 1969). They claimed
fies choice of options, but preference for violent op- they were simply carrying out orders. Self-exonerating
tions often biases judgment of gravity. obedience to horrific orders is similarly evident in mil-
Assessments of conflicting realities and the best itary atrocities, such as the My Lai massacre (Kelman
means to deal with them can be flawed by biasing so- & Hamilton, 1989).
cial processes as well as by inferential errors from un- In psychological studies of disengagement of moral
certain information. The information on which control by displacement of responsibility, authorities
judgments are made may be tainted by the policy bi- explicitly authorize injurious actions and hold them-
ases of those gathering and interpreting it (March, selves responsible for the harm caused by their follow-
1982). The use of superficial similarities in the framing ers. For example, Milgram (1974) got people to
of issues can distort judgment of the justification of vi- escalate their level of aggression by commanding them
olent means (Gilovich, 1981). For example, in judging to do so and telling them that he took full responsibility
how the United States should respond to a totalitarian for the consequences oftheir actions. As shown in Fig-
threat toward a small nation by another country, people ure 2, the greater the legitimacy and closeness of the

196
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

o 70
7
CD)Cl)w
10 _
z 50
w
5
w
o 40-
z
w
0
a: 30-
w
a.

20 -

10 0

AUTHORITY AUTHORITY AUTHORITY NON-AUTHORITY AUTHORITY CONFLICTING


COMMANDS COMMANDS COMMANDS COMMANDS COMMANDS AUTHORITIES
+ DIRECTLY REMOTELY + COMMAND
COMPLIANT DEFIANT
PEERS PEERS

Figure 2. Percentage of people fully obedient to injurious commands as a function of the legitimization and closeness of the authority issu-
ing the commands. This figure is plotted from data from Experiments 5,7,13,15,17, and 18 from Obedience toAuthority: An Experimental
View, by S. Milgram, 1974, New York: Harper & Row. Copyright 1974 by HarperCollins, Publishers. Adapted with permission.

authority issuing injurious commands, the higher the do not find out what they do not want to know. Im-
level of obedient aggression. plicit agreements, insulating social arrangements, and
The sanctioning of harmful conduct in everyday authorization by indirection are used to leave the
life differs in two important ways from the direct au- higher echelons unblamable.
thorizing system examined by Milgram (1974). Re- When harmful practices are publicized, they are of-
sponsibility is rarely assumed that openly. Only ficially dismissed as only isolated incidents arising
obtuse authorities would leave themselves accusable from misunderstandings of what had been authorized,
of authorizing harmful acts. They usually invite and or the blame is assigned to subordinates, who are por-
support harmful conduct in insidious ways for per- trayed as misguided or overzealous. Investigators who
sonal and social reasons. Through surreptitious sanc- go looking for incriminating records of authorization
tioning practices, they can shield themselves from display naivete about the insidious ways that perni-
social condemnation should the courses of action go cious practices usually are sanctioned and carried out.
awry. They also have to live with themselves. Sanc- One finds decisional arrangements of foggy
tioning by indirection enables them to protect against nonresponsibility rather than incriminating traces of
loss of self-respect for authorizing human cruelty. smoking guns.
In detrimental schemes, authorities act in ways There is another basic difference from the direct au-
that keep themselves intentionally uninformed. As thorizing system. Obedient functionaries do not cast
our secretary of state instructed a presidential advisor off all responsibility for their behavior as if they were
in the Iran-Contra affair, "Just tell me what I need to mindless extensions of others. If they disowned all re-
know." Authorities do not go looking for evidence of sponsibility, they would perform their duties only
wrongdoing. Obvious questions that would reveal in- when told to do so. It requires a strong sense of respon-
criminating information remain unasked, so officials sibility, rooted in ideology, to be a good functionary. It

197
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

is, therefore, important to distinguish between two lev- vided a discerning analysis of the different ways in
els of responsibility: duty to one's superiors and ac- which a sense of personal agency gets obscured by dif-
countability for the effects of one's actions. The best fusing personal accountability. There are several ways
functionaries are those who honor their obligations to of doing it. A sense of responsibility can be diffused,
authorities but feel no personal responsibility for the and thereby diminished, by division of labor. Most en-
harm they cause. They work dutifully to be good at terprises require the services of many people, each per-
their evildoing. Followers who disowned responsibil- forming subdivided jobs that seem harmless in
ity, without being bound by a sense of duty, would be themselves. After activities become routinized into de-
quite unreliable in performing their duties when the au- tached subfunctions, people shift their attention from
thorities are not around. the morality of what they are doing to the operational
Goldhagen (1996) documented that many of the details and efficiency of their specific job.
perpetrators in the German genocide infantry were Group decision making is another common prac-
more than willing executioners. Disengagement prac- tice that gets otherwise considerate people to behave
tices operate within sociopolitical structures that shape inhumanely. When everyone is responsible, no one
their expression and affect their prevalence. Cultural really feels responsible. Social organizations go to
hatreds create low thresholds for the disengagement of great lengths to devise mechanisms for obscuring re-
moral self-sanctions. Inhumanities toward human be- sponsibility for decisions that will affect others ad-
ings cast in devalued categories and invested with vile versely. Collective action is still another expedient
attributes become not only permissible but righteously for weakening moral control (Zimbardo, 1995). Any
approvable. harm done by a group can always be attributed
largely to the behavior of others (Bandura, Under-
wood, & Fromson, 1975). Figure 3 shows the level of
Diffusion of Responsibility harm inflicted on others on repeated occasions de-
pending on whether it was done as a group or indi-
The exercise of moral control is also weakened vidually. People act more cruelly under group
when personal agency is obscured by diffusing respon- responsibility than when they hold themselves per-
sibility for detrimental behavior. Kelman (1973) pro- sonally accountable for their actions.

6T

CD)
CO)
z
w 4
z

2 3
-J
-lJ
S . GROUP RESPONSIBILITY
2 -

0---o INDIVIDUAL o

IL I I
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
OCCASIONS

Figure 3. Level of punitiveness by individuals under conditions in which severity of their


punitiveness was determined personally or jointly by a group. Occasions represent succes-
sive times at which punitive sanctions could be applied. From "Disinhibition of Aggression
Through Diffusion of Responsibility and Dehumanization of Victims," by A. Bandura, B.
Underwood, & M. E. Fromson, 1975, Journal of Research in Personality, 9, p. 260. Copy-
right 1975 by Academic Press. Reprinted with permission.

198
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

Disregard or Distortion of tims' pain becomes more evident and personalized


Consequences (Milgram, 1974). Even a high sense of personal re-
sponsibility is a weak restrainer of injurious conduct
Additional ways of weakening moral control oper- when aggressors do not see the harm they inflict on
ate by disregarding or distorting the effects of one's ac- their victims (Tilker, 1970).
tions. When people pursue activities that are harmful to A Pulitzer prize was awarded for a powerful
others for reasons of personal gain or social pressure, photograph that captured the anguished cries of a
they avoid facing the harm they cause, or they mini- girl whose clothes were burned off by the napalm
mize it. If minimization does not work, the evidence of bombing of her village in Vietnam. This single hu-
harm can be discredited. As long as the harmful results manization of inflicted destruction probably did
of one's conduct are ignored, minimized, distorted, or more to turn the American public against the war
disbelieved, there is little reason for self-censure to be than the countless reports filed by journalists. The
activated. military now bans cameras and journalists from bat-
It is easier to harm others when their suffering is tlefield areas to block disturbing images of death
not visible and when injurious actions are physically and destruction.
and temporally remote from their effects. Our death Most organizations involve hierarchical chains of
technologies have become highly lethal and deper- command in which superiors formulate plans and in-
sonalized. We are now in the era of faceless warfare, termediaries transmit them to functionaries who then
in which mass destruction is delivered remotely with carry them out. The farther removed individuals are
deadly accuracy by computer and laser-controlled from the destructive end results, the weaker is the re-
systems. When people can see and hear the suffering straining power of injurious effects. Disengagement
they cause, vicariously aroused distress and of moral control is easiest for the intermediaries in a
self-censure serve as self-restrainers (Bandura, 1992). hierarchical system-they neither bear responsibility
As shown in Figure 4, people are less compliant to for the decisions nor do they carry them out and face
the injurious commands of authorities when the vic- the harm being inflicted (Kilham & Mann, 1974).

70

60 H

a:U)im
wCD
CO
cL 50 _
H

z
w 40 H
LLI

co
0
z 30 _
w
w
0-

20 _

a
REMOTE HEARS SEES AND HEARS DIRECT
INFLICTION SUFFERING SUFFERING INFLICTION
OF SUFFERING OF REMOTE OF REMOTE OF SUFFERING
INFLICTION INFLICTION

Figure 4. Percentage of people fully obedient to injurious commands issued by an author-


ity as the victim's suffering becomes more evident and personalized. This figure is plotted
from data from Experiments 1 through 4 from Obedience to Authority: An Experimental
View, by S. Milgram, 1974, New York: Harper & Row. Copyright 1974 by HarperCollins
Publishers. Adapted with permission.

199
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

Dehumanization terms. Unknown to the supervisors, the administered


shocks were never delivered to the recipients. Dehu-
The final set of disengagement practices operates manized individuals were treated more punitively
on the recipients of detrimental acts. The strength of than those who had been invested with human
moral self-censure depends partly on how the perpe- qualities (Bandura et al., 1975). Figure 5 depicts the
trators view the people they mistreat. Correlative in- power of dehumanization to promote human
terpersonal experiences during formative years, in punitiveness.
which people experience joys and suffer pain to- Combining diffused responsibility with dehuman-
gether, create the foundation for empathic respon- ization greatly escalates the level of punitiveness. In
siveness to the plight of others (Bandura, 1986). To contrast, personalization of responsibility and hu-
perceive another in terms of common humanity acti- manization of others together have a powerful
vates empathetic emotional reactions through per- self-restraining effect (Figure 6). The supervisor's
ceived similarity and a sense of social obligation self-regulatory evaluative reactions to performing a
(Bandura, 1992; McHugo, Smith, & Lanzetta, 1982). punitive role differed markedly across the different
The joys and suffering of those with whom one iden- disengagement conditions. Those who assumed per-
tifies are more vicariously arousing than are those of sonal responsibility for their actions with humanized
strangers or of individuals who have been divested of individuals rarely expressed self-exonerative justifi-
human qualities. It is, therefore, difficult to mistreat cations and uniformly disavowed punitive sanctions.
humanized persons without suffering personal dis- By contrast, when performers were divested of hu-
tress and self-condemnation. manness and punished collectively, the supervisors
Self-censure for cruel conduct can be disengaged by often voiced exonerative justifications for punitive
stripping people of human qualities. Once dehuman- sanctions and were disinclined to condemn their use.
ized, they are no longer viewed as persons with feel- This is especially true when punitive sanctions were
ings, hopes, and concerns but as subhuman objects dysfunctionally applied in increasing intensities that
(Keen, 1986; Kelman, 1973). They are portrayed as impaired rather then improved group performance.
mindless "savages," "gooks," and other despicable Self-exonerators behaved more harshly than do
wretches. If dispossessing one's foes of humanness self-disapprovers of punitive actions.
does not weaken self-censure, it can be eliminated by Many conditions of contemporary life are condu-
attributing demonic or bestial qualities to them. They cive to impersonalization and dehumanization (Ber-
become "satanic fiends," "degenerates," and other bes- nard, Ottenberg, & Redl, 1965). Bureaucratization,
tial creatures. It is easier to brutalize people when they automation, urbanization, and high geographical mo-
are viewed as low animal forms, as when Greek tortur- bility lead people to relate to each other in anonymous,
ers referred to their victims as "worms" (Gibson & impersonal ways. In addition, social practices that di-
Haritos-Fatouros, 1986). vide people into ingroup and outgroup members pro-
During wartime, nations cast their enemies in the duce human estrangement that fosters dehumanization.
most dehumanized, demonic, and bestial images to Strangers can be more easily depersonalized than can
make it easier to kill them (Ivie, 1980). The process acquaintances.
of dehumanization is an essential ingredient in the Under certain conditions, wielding institutional
perpetration of inhumanities. Levi (1987) reported an power changes the power holders in ways that are con-
incident in which a Nazi camp commandant was ducive to dehumanization. This happens when persons
asked why the Nazis went to such extreme lengths to in positions of authority have coercive power over oth-
degrade their victims, whom they were going to kill ers with few safeguards to constrain their behavior.
anyway. The commandant chillingly explained that it Power holders come to devalue those over whom they
was not a matter of purposeless cruelty. Rather, the wield control (Kipnis, 1974). Even college students,
victims had to be degraded to the level of subhuman who had been randomly assigned to serve as either in-
objects so that those who operated the gas chambers mates or guards, when given unilateral power in a sim-
would be less burdened by distress. ulated prison, quickly come to treat their charges in
In experimental studies of the perniciousness of degrading, tyrannical ways (Haney, Banks, &
the combined effect of dehumanization and a dimin- Zimbardo, 1973).
ished sense of personal responsibility, a supervisory The findings from research on the different mecha-
team was given the power to punish a group of prob- nisms of moral disengagement are in accord with the
lem solvers with varying intensities of electric shock historical chronicle of human atrocities: It requires
for deficient performances (Bandura et al., 1975). conducive social conditions rather than monstrous
The punishment was administered either personally people to produce atrocious deeds. Given appropriate
or collectively to the performing recipients character- social conditions, decent, ordinary people can be led to
ized in either humanistic, animalistic, or neutral do extraordinarily cruel things.

200
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
8

7_

6
CD
(n
w
Z5
w

z 4 U! .M,, . . -
D F- .
U.'
U-
L.
0
ill3 "-.3..
w-j / C -"
NRO_ /
21 i.f
cr- _-l
ofw

-@ DEHUMANIZED
-
..NEUTRAL
O---O HUMANIZED
I -f Ie
-~~~~~~~ I,
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
OCCASIONS
Figure 5. Level of punitiveness on repeated occasions toward people characterized in humanized
terms, not personalized with any characterization (neutral), or portrayed in dehumanized terms.
From "Disinhibition of Aggression Through Diffusion of Responsibility and Dehumanization of
Victims," by A. Bandura, B. Underwood, & M. E. Fromson, 1975, Journal ofResearch in Personal-
ity, 9, p. 260. Copyright 1975 by Academic Press. Reprinted with permission.

7
0-. GROUP RESPONSIBILITY
o---o INDIVIDUAL RESPONSIBILITY

(0
Ul)
w
5
z
w

z
D 4
a-
U-
0
-j
w

HUMAN IZED NEUTRAL DEHUMANIZED

Figure 6. Level of punitiveness as a function of diffusion of responsibility and


dehumanization of the recipients. From "Disinhibition of Aggression Through
Diffusion of Responsibility and Dehumanization of Victims," by A. Bandura, B.
Underwood, & M. E. Fromson, 1975, Journal of Research in Personality, 9, p.
264. Copyright 1975 by Academic Press. Reprinted with permission.

201
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

Power of Humanization The emphasis on obedient aggression is under-


standable considering the prevalence of people's in-
Psychological theorizing and research tends to em- humanities to one another. However, the power of
phasize how easy it is to bring out the worst in people humanization to counteract cruel conduct also has
through dehumanization and other self-exonerative considerable social import. People's recognition of
means. The sensational negative findings receive the the social linkage of their lives and their vested inter-
greatest attention. For example, Milgram's (1974) re- est in each other's welfare help to support actions that
search on obedient aggression is widely cited as evi- instill them with a sense of community. The affirma-
dence that good people can be talked into performing tion of common humanity can bring out the best in
cruel deeds. What is rarely noted is the equally strik- others.
ing evidence that most people refuse to behave cru- The My Lai massacre graphically illustrates the
elly, even under unrelenting authoritarian commands, dual aspects of moral agency. An American platoon,
if the situation is personalized by having them inflict led by Lieutenant William Calley, massacred 500
pain by direct personal action rather than remotely Vietnamese women, children, and elderly men. In-
and if they see the suffering they cause (Bandura et sightful analyses have documented how moral
al., 1975; Milgram, 1974). Even when punitive sanc- self-sanctions were disengaged from the brutal col-
tions are the only means available and they are highly lective conduct (Kelman & Hamilton, 1989). A cere-
functional in producing desired results, those exercis- mony, 30 years in coming, was held at the Vietnam
ing that power cannot get themselves to behave puni- Veteran's Memorial honoring extraordinary heroism
tively toward humanized individuals (see Figure 7). of prosocial morality (Zganjar, 1998). The moral
In contrast, when punitive sanctions are dysfunctional courage that was honored testifies to the remarkable
because they usually fail to produce results, power of humanization. Hugh Thompson, a young
punitiveness is precipitously escalated toward dehu- helicopter pilot, swooped down over the village of
manized individuals. The failure of degraded individ- My Lai on a search- and-destroy mission as the mas-
uals to change in response to punitive treatment is sacre was occurring. He spotted an injured girl,
taken as further evidence of their culpability that jus- marked the spot with a smoke signal, and radioed for
tifies intensified punitiveness toward them. help. Much to his horror, he saw a soldier flip her

8 *-* DEHUMANIZED
- .... NEUTRAL
o--o HUMANIZED

ww
cn
co
z 6

I-
z
0~

ww
LL4
-J

-J

ioj( %W x

LI
,~~~~~~~~~I
2 4 6 8 O 10 % r

FUNCTIONAL
OCCASIONS

Figure 7. Level of punitive sanctions imposed on repeated occasions as a result ofdehumanization ofthe
recipients and the effectiveness of the punitive actions. Under the functional condition, punishment con-
sistently produced improved performances; under the dysfunctional condition, punishment usually
gave rise to performance failures. From "Disinhibition of Aggression Through Diffusion of Responsibil-
ity and Dehumanization of Victims," by A. Bandura, B. Underwood, & M. E. Fromson, 1975, Journal of
Research in Personality, 9, p. 264. Copyright 1975 by Academic Press. Reprinted with permission.

202
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

over and spray her with a round of fire. On seeing the ism. Once the protective relationship was initiated,
human carnage in an irrigation ditch and soldiers fir- the development of social bonds heightened the force
ing into the bodies, he realized that he was in the of empathic concern and moral obligation.
midst of a massacre.
He was moved to proactive moral action by the Attribution of Blame
sight of a terrified woman with a baby in her arms
and a child clinging to her leg. As he explained his Blaming one's adversaries or circumstances is still
sense of common humanity, "These people were another expedient that can serve self-exonerative pur-
looking at me for help and there is no way I could poses. In this process, people view themselves as fault-
turn by back on them." He told the commanding offi- less victims driven to injurious conduct by forcible
cer to help him remove the remaining villagers. The provocation. Punitive conduct is, thus, seen as ajustifi-
officer replied that "The only help they'll get is a able defensive reaction to belligerent provocations.
hand grenade." Thompson moved his helicopter in Conflictful transactions typically involve reciprocally
the line of fire and commanded his gunner to fire on escalative acts. One can select from the chain of events
his approaching countrymen if they tried to harm the a defensive act by the adversary and portray it as initi-
villagers. He radioed the accompanying gunships for ating provocation. Victims then get blamed for bring-
help and together they airlifted the remaining dozen ing suffering on themselves. Self-exoneration is also
villagers to safety. He flew back to the irrigation achievable by viewing one's harmful conduct as
ditch where they found and rescued a 2-year-old boy forced by compelling circumstances rather than as a
still clinging to his dead mother. Thompson described personal decision. By fixing the blame on others or on
his empathetic human linkage: "I had a son at home circumstances, not only are one's own injurious ac-
about the same age." tions excusable, but one even can feel self-righteous in
Proactive moral action is regulated in large part by the process.
resolute engagement of the mechanisms of moral Justified abuse can have more devastating human
agency. In the exercise of proactive morality, people consequences than acknowledged cruelty. Mistreat-
act in the name of humane principles when social cir- ment that is not clothed in righteousness makes the per-
cumstances dictate expedient, transgressive, and det- petrator rather than the victim blameworthy. However,
rimental conduct. They disavow use of valued social when victims are convincingly blamed for their plight,
ends to justify destructive means. They sacrifice their they eventually may come to believe the degrading
well-being for their convictions. They take personal characterizations of themselves (Hallie, 1971). Exon-
responsibility for the consequences of their actions. erated inhumanity is, thus, more likely to instill
They remain sensitive to the suffering of others. self-contempt in victims than inhumanity that does not
Finally, they see human commonalities rather than attempt to justify itself. Seeing victims suffer maltreat-
distance themselves from others or divest them of hu- ment for which they are held partially responsible
man qualities. leads observers to denigrate them (Lerner & Miller,
Social psychology often emphasizes the power of 1978). The devaluation and indignation aroused by as-
the situation over the individual. In the case of re- cribed culpability provides further moral justification
markable moral courage, the individual triumphs as a for even greater maltreatment.
moral agent over compelling situational pressures to
behave otherwise. Such moral heroism is most strik-
ingly documented in rescuers who risked their lives, Gradualistic Moral Disengagement
often over prolonged periods fraught with extreme
danger, to save from the Holocaust persecuted Jews Disengagement practices will not instantly trans-
with whom they had no prior acquaintance and had form considerate persons into cruel ones. Rather, the
nothing material or social to gain by doing so (Oliner change is achieved by gradual disengagement of
& Oliner, 1988; Stein, 1988). Humanization can self-censure. People may not even recognize the
rouse empathic sentiments and a strong sense of so- changes they are undergoing. Initially, they perform
cial obligation linked to evaluative self-sanctions that milder aggressive acts they can tolerate with some
motivate humane actions on others' behalf at a sacri- discomfort. After their self-reproof has been dimin-
fice of one's self-interest or even at one's own peril ished through repeated enactments, the level of ruth-
(Bandura, 1986). In the case of the rescuers, a reso- lessness increases, until eventually acts originally
lute personal obligation for the welfare of persecuted regarded as abhorrent can be performed with little
individuals overrode self-concern despite the grave personal anguish or self-censure. Inhumane practices
risks and heavy burdens the extended protective care become thoughtlessly routinized.
entailed. Rescuers viewed their behavior as a human The gradual disengagement of morality is illus-
duty rather than as extraordinary acts of moral hero- trated by a prison guard who assisted in the execution

203
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

of convicts by gassing. Putting people to death re- Terpil became a weapons merchant after he fell
quires subdivision of the task to get someone to do it. from grace at the Central Intelligence Agency. He
The guard's role was limited to strapping the legs to masked his death operations in the euphemisms of a
the death chair. This spared him the image of execu- legitimate business fulfilling "consumer needs," un-
tioner: "I never pulled the trigger. I wasn't the execu- der the sanitized name Intercontinental Technology.
tioner" (Marine, 1990), he explained. Executioners To spare himself any self-censure for contributing to
require heavy use of euphemisms as well. The guard human atrocities, he actively avoided knowledge of
received $35 extra for each execution. In a linguistic the purposes to which his weapons would be put. "I
rechristening of deathly gassing as benevolent caring, don't ever want to know that," he said. When asked
he remarked "That was a lot of money for whether he was ever haunted by any thoughts about
baby-sitting." He described the changes he had un- the human suffering his deathly wares might cause,
dergone over the course of 126 executions as follows: he explained that a weapons dealer cannot afford to
"It never bothered me, when I was down at their legs think about human consequences: "If I really thought
strapping them in. But after I'd get home, I'd think about the consequences all the time, I certainly
about it. But then it would go away. And then, at last, wouldn't have been in this business. You have to
it was just another job." Haney (1997) presented a blank it off."
systematic analysis of the way in which capital trials Probes for any signs of self-reproach only brought
are structured to enlist the various mechanisms of self-exonerative comparisons. When asked if he felt
moral disengagement. This enables jurors to sentence any qualms about supplying torture equipment to
a human being to death. Executions have become Ugandan president Idi Amin, Terpil replied with jus-
routinized to the point in which there are no longer tification by advantageous comparison. As he put it
any vigils or media coverage at the midnight execu-
tions. Societal executions are now not only out of I'm sure that the people from Dow Chemical didn't
sight but out of mind. think of the consequences of selling napalm. If they
Sprinzak (1986, 1990) showed that terrorists, did, they wouldn't be working at the factory. I doubt
whether on the political left or right, evolve gradually very much if they'd feel any more responsible for the
ultimate use than I did for my equipment.
rather than set out to become radicals. The process of
radicalization involves a gradual disengagement of
moral sanctions from violent conduct. It begins with When pressed about the atrocities committed at Amin's
torture chambers, Terpil repeated his depersonalized
prosocial efforts to change particular social policies
and opposition to officials, who are intent on keeping view: "I do not get wrapped up emotionally with the
things as they are. Embittering failures to accomplish country. I regard myself basically as neutral, and com-
social change and hostile confrontations with authori- mercial." To give legitimacy to his "private practice,"
ties and police lead to growing disillusionment and he claimed that he aided British and American covert
alienation from the whole system. Escalating battles operations abroad as well.
What began as a psychological analysis of the op-
culminate in terrorists' efforts to destroy the system
and its dehumanized rulers. erator of a death industry ended unexpectedly in an
international network of supporting legitimate enter-
prises run by upstanding, conscientious people. The
merchandising of terrorism is not accomplished by a
Moral Disengagement in the few unsavory individuals. It requires a worldwide
Merchandising of Deathly Wares network of reputable, high-level members of society
who contribute to the deathly enterprise by insulating
So far, I have described the different mechanisms of fractionation of the operations and displacement and
moral disengagement individually. In the transactions diffusion of responsibility. One group manufactures
of everyday life, they operate in concert within a the tools of destruction. Others amass the arsenals for
sociostructural context to promote inhumanities. This legitimate sale. Others operate storage centers for
is well illustrated in the analyses by Thomas (1982) of them. Others procure export and import licenses to
the activities of an American weapons dealer named move the deathly wares among different countries.
Terpil. He supplied despots with weapons, assassina- Others obtain spurious end-user certificates that get
tion equipment, and the latest in terrorist technology. the weaponry to embargoed nations through circu-
This case is especially informative because it shows itous routes, and still others ship the lethal wares. The
vividly that those who trade in human destruction do cogs in this worldwide network include weapons
not do it alone. They depend heavily on the moral dis- manufacturers; former government officials with po-
engagement of a network of reputable agents manag- litical ties; former diplomatic, military, and intelli-
ing respectable enterprises. gence officers who provide valuable diplomatic skills

204
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

and contacts; and weapons merchants and shippers laws that block states from regulating tobacco prod-
operating legitimate businesses. By fragmenting and ucts and their advertising (Lynch & Bonnie, 1994;
dispersing subfunctions of the enterprise, the various Public Citizen Health Research Group, 1993); U.S.
contributors see themselves as decent, legitimate trade representatives threatening sanctions against
practitioners of their trade rather than as parties to countries that erect barriers against the importation of
deathly operations. U.S. cigarettes; and even president Carter firing his
Even producers of the television program 60 Min- head of the Department of Health, Education and
utes contributed to Terpil's coffers ("CBS Paid 2 Fu- Welfare for refusing to back off on the regulation of
gitives," 1983). Terpil skipped bail to a foreign tobacco products.
sanctuary after he was caught selling assassination The gun industry provides another example of
equipment to an undercover FBI agent. He was tried moral disengagement in the business arena. As sales
in absentia. The government attorney confronted the for low caliber guns stagnated, the gun industry
lead reporter of the program about a payment of shifted their production to weapons of increasing
$12,000 to an intermediary for an interview with the lethality (Butterfield, 1999; Diaz, 1999). The new
fugitive Terpil. The reporter pleaded innocence generation of pistols is faster firing semiautomatics
through various disengagement maneuvers. with larger magazines to hold more bullets of higher
Disengagement of moral control mechanisms has caliber that magnify their killing power. Victims now
been examined most extensively in military and polit- suffer more gunshot wounds of greater severity and
ical violence. However, it is by no means confined to higher likelihood of death. To protect themselves
extraordinary circumstances. Quite to the contrary, against being outgunned, the police, in turn, are
such mechanisms operate in everyday situations in switching from revolvers to semiautomatic pistols us-
which decent people routinely perform activities that ing more lethal ammunition in the deadly escalation.
bring them profits and other benefits at injurious An executive of a trade group representing gun man-
costs to others. Self-exonerations are needed to neu- ufacturers justifies the production change through ad-
tralize self-censure and to preserve self-esteem. For vantageous comparison with normal business
example, certain industries cause harmful effects on a practices that trivialize the lethality of the product
large scale, either by the nature of their products or (Butterfield, 1999). "Just like the fashion industry,
the environmental toxification and degradation their the firearms industry likes to encourage new products
operations produce. Disregarding or minimizing inju- to get people to buy its products." Through social jus-
rious consequences, or discrediting the evidence for tification, he invests the more deadly weapons with
them, is a widely used disengagement practice. For worthy self-protective purposes: "If the gun has more
years, the tobacco industry, whose products kill more stopping power, it is a more effective weapon." An-
than 400,000 Americans annually (McGinnis & other exonerative device absolves the gun industry of
Foege, 1993), disputed the view that nicotine is ad- responsibilty for the criminal use of the lethal semi-
dictive and that smoking is a major contributor to automatic pistils they design and market:
lung cancer.
The vast supporting cast contributing to the pro- We design weapons, not for the bad guys, but for the
motion of this deadly product includes talented chem- good guys. If criminals happen to get their hands on a
ists discovering ammonia as a means to increase the gun, it is not the manufacturer's fault. The problem is,
nicotine kick by speeding the body's absorption of you can't design a product and insure who is going to
nicotine (Meier, 1998a); inventive biotech research- get it.
ers genetically engineering a tobacco seed that dou-
bles the addictive nicotine content of tobacco plants A law suit for negligent marketing and distribution
(Meier, 1998c); creative advertisers targeting young practices won by New York City against gun manufac-
age groups with merchandising and advertising turers charged that they oversupply stores in Southern
schemes depicting smoking as a sign of youthful states with lax gun laws, with knowledge that the weap-
hipness, modernity, freedom, and women's liberation ons are bought and resold to juveniles and criminals in
(Dedman, 1998; Lynch & Bonnie, 1994; Meier, cities with tough gun laws.
1998b); ingenious officials in a subsidiary of a major Much work remains to be done in analyzing the par-
tobacco company engaging in an elaborate interna- ticular forms that moral disengagement practices take
tional cigarette smuggling operation to evade excise at industry-wide levels and the justificatory exonera-
taxes (Drew, 1998); popular movie actors agreeing to tions and social arrangements that facilitate their use.
smoke in their movies for a hefty fee; legislators with As indicated in the previous examples and other analy-
bountiful tobacco campaign contributions exempting ses of industry-wide moral disengagement (Bandura,
nicotine from drug legislation even though it is the 1973), injurious corporate practices require a large net-
most addictive substance, and passing preemption work ofotherwise considerate people doing jobs draw-

205
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

ing on their expertise and social influence in the ceived grievances and vengeful retaliation, all of
service of a detrimental enterprise through selective which are conducive to aggression and antisocial
moral disengagement. Edmund Burke's aphorism that conduct. The higher the moral disengagement and the
"The only thing necessary for the triumph of evil is for weaker the perceived self-efficacy to resist peer pres-
good men to do nothing" needs a companion adage that sure for transgressive activities, the heavier the in-
"The triumph of evil requires a lot of good people do- volvement in antisocial conduct (Kwak & Bandura,
ing a bit of it in a morally disengaged way with indif- 1998). Gender differences in moral disengagement do
ference to the human suffering they collectively not exist in the earlier years, but before long, boys
cause." become more facile moral disengagers than do girls.
Institutionalized discrimination of devalued sub- Moral development typically is studied in terms of
groups in societies takes a heavy toll on its victims. It abstract principles ofmorality. Adolescents who differ
requires social justification, attributions of blame, de- in delinquent conduct do not necessarily differ in ab-
humanization, impersonalized agencies to carry out stract moral values. Most everyone is virtuous at the
the discriminatory practices, and inattention to the in- abstract level. Amorphous abstractions obscure the dy-
jurious effects they cause. Ideologies of male domina- namic processes governing the selective disengage-
tion, dehumanization, ascription of blame, and ment of moral self-sanctions. It is in the ease of moral
distortion of injurious consequences also play a heavy disengagement under the conditionals of life that the
role in sexual abuse of women (Bandura, 1986; Burt, differences lie. Among adolescents, facile moral
1980; Sanday, 1997). disengagers display higher levels of violence, theft,
and other forms of antisocial conduct than do those
who bring moral self-sanctions to bear on their conduct
Development of Moral Disengagement (Elliott & Rhinehart, 1995). Proneness to moral disen-
gagement predicts both felony and misdemeanor as-
Advances in the measurement of moral disengage- saults and thefts, regardless of age, sex, race, religious
ment hold promise of furthering our understanding of affiliation, and social class. This predictive generality
how this aspect of morality develops and influences attests to the pervading role of self-regulatory mecha-
the courses lives take. Developmental research shows nisms in detrimental conduct. Moral engagement
that moral disengagement already is operating even against destructive means can be enhanced in children
in the early years of life (Bandura, Barbaranelli, by peer modeling and the espousal of peaceable solu-
Caprara, & Pastorelli, 1996). It contributes to social tions to human conflicts (McAlister, Ama, Barroro,
discordance in ways that are likely to lead down dis- Peters, & Kelder, 1999).
social paths. Figure 8 presents the direct and medi-
ated paths of influence of proclivity for moral Interplay of Personal and
disengagement on delinquent conduct (Bandura et al., Social Sanctions
1996). High moral disengagers are less troubled by
anticipatory feelings of guilt over injurious conduct, The self-regulation of morality is not entirely an
are less prosocial, and prone to ruminate about per- intrapsychic matter, as rationalists might lead one to
.22

Figure 8. Contribution of moral disengagement to the multivariate determination of delinquent behavior. All paths of influence are sig-
nificant atp < .05 or less. From "Mechanisms of Moral Disengagement in the Exercise of Moral Agency," by A. Bandura, C. Barbaranelli,
G. V. Caprara, and C. Pastorelli, 1996,Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology, 71, p.370. Copyright 1996 by the American Psycho-
logical Association. Reprinted by permission of the publisher.

206
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT

believe. People do not operate as autonomous moral terplay of personal, behavioral, and environmental
agents impervious to the social realities in which they influences.
are immersed. Moral agency is socially situated and
exercised in particularized ways depending on the life
conditions under which people transact their affairs. Concluding Remarks
Social cognitive theory, therefore, adopts an
interactionist perspective to morality. Moral actions The massive threats to human welfare stem mainly
are the products of the reciprocal interplay of personal from deliberate acts of principle rather than from unre-
and social influences. Conflicts arise between self strained acts of impulse. In the insightful words of C.
sanctions and social sanctions when individuals are so- P. Snow, "More hideous crimes have been committed
cially punished for courses of action they regard as in the name of obedience than in the name of rebel-
right and just. Principled dissenters and nonconform- lion." Ideological resort to destructiveness is of great-
ists often find themselves in this predicament. Some est social concern but, ironically, it is the most ignored
sacrifice their welfare for their convictions. People in psychological analyses of people's inhumanities to-
also commonly experience conflicts in which they are ward each other. Given the many psychological de-
socially pressured to engage in conduct that violates vices for disengaging moral control, societies cannot
their moral standards. Responses to such moral dilem- rely entirely on individuals to deter human cruelty.
mas are determined by the relative strength of self Civilized life requires, in addition to humane personal
sanctions and social sanctions and the conditional ap- codes, effective social safeguards against the misuse of
plication of moral standards. power for exploitative and destructive purposes.
Sociostructural theories and psychological theories Monolithic sociopolitical systems that exercise
often are regarded as rival conceptions of human be- tight control over institutional and communications
havior or as representing different levels of causation. systems can wield greater power of moral disengage-
Human behavior cannot be fully understood solely in ment than can pluralistic systems that represent di-
terms of social structural factors or psychological fac- verse perspectives, interests, and concerns. Political
tors. A full understanding requires an integrated per- diversity and institutional protection of dissent allow
spective in which social influences operate through challenges to suspect moral appeals. Healthy skepti-
psychological mechanisms to produce behavior ef- cism toward moral pretensions puts a further check
fects (Bandura, 1997). Some of the moral disengage- on the misuse of morality for inhumane purposes.
ment practices, such as diffusion and displacement of Limited public access to the media has been a major
responsibility, are rooted in the organizational and obstacle to reciprocal influence on detrimental social
authority structures of societal systems. The ideologi- policies and practices. The evolving telecommunica-
cal orientations of societies shape the form of moral tions technologies are transforming the mode of
justifications, sanction detrimental practices, and in- sociopolitical influence (Bandura, 1997). Interactive
fluence which members of society tend to be cast into communication through the Internet provides vast op-
devalued groups. These sociostructural practices cre- portunities for participatory debates that transcend
ate conditions conducive to moral disengagement. time, place, and national boundaries about issues of
However, people are producers as well as products of social concern. Mobilization of collective influence
social systems. Social structures-which are devised against injurious social policies via the Internet can
to organize, guide, and regulate human affairs-are be swift, wide-reaching, and free of monopolistic so-
created by human activity. Moreover, within the rule cial control. But the Internet is a double-edged tool.
structures, there is personal variation in their interpre- Internet freelancers, of course, can use this unfiltered
tation, adoption, enforcement, circumvention, or ac- and unfettered political forum to mobilize support for
tive opposition (Burus & Dietz, in press). detrimental social practices as well as for humane
As noted previously, social cognitive theory avoids ones.
a dualism between social structure and personal Some of the efforts at change must be directed at
agency (Bandura, 1986, 1997). Sociostructural influ- institutional practices that insulate the higher eche-
ences affect action via self-regulatory mechanisms op- lons from accountability for the detrimental policies
erating through a set of subfunctions. Neither over which they preside. Discourses that cloak inhu-
situational imperatives (Milgram, 1974) nor vile dis- mane activities in sanitizing language should be
positions (Gillespie, 1971) provide a wholly adequate stripped of their euphemistic cover. Some of the
explanation of human malevolence. In social cognitive moral disengagement is in the service of profit rather
theory, both sociostructural and personal determinants than political purposes. Corporate practices that have
operate interdependently within a unified causal struc- injurious human effects must be monitored, subjected
ture in the perpetration of inhumanities. Unusual forms to negative sanctions, and widely publicized to enlist
of malevolence are typically the product of a unique in- the public support needed to change them. Regardless

207
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
BANDURA

of whether inhumane practices are institutional, orga- Gabor, T. (1994). Everybody does it: Crime by the public. Toronto,
Canada: University of Toronto Press.
nizational, or individual, it should be made difficult Gambino, R. (1973, November/December). Watergate lingo: A lan-
for people to remove humanity from their conduct. guage of non-responsibility. Freedom at Issue, 22, 7-9, 15-17.
Gibson, J. T., & Haritos-Fatouros, M. (1986, November). The educa-
tion of a torturer. Psychology Today, 50-58.
References Gillespie, W. H. (1971). Aggression and instinct theory. Interna-
tional Journal of Psycho-analysis, 52, 155-160.
Andrus, B. C. (I1969). The infamous ofNuremberg. London: Fravin.
Gilovich, T. (I1981). Seeing the past in the present: The effect of asso-
ciations to familiar events on judgments and decisions. Journal
Bandura, A. (I1973). Aggression: A social learning analysis. ofPersonality and Social Psychology, 40, 797-808.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Goldhagen, D. J. (1996). Hitler's willing executioners: Ordinary
Bandura, A. (1986). Socialfoundations of thought and action: A so- Germans and the holocaust. New York: Knopf.
cial cognitive theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Hallie, P. P. (1971). Justification and rebellion. In N. Sanford & C.
Bandura, A. (I1991). Social cognitive theory of moral thought and ac- Comstock (Eds.), Sanctions for evil (pp. 247-263). San Fran-
tion. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Handbook of cisco: Jossey-Bass.
moral behavior and development: Theory, research and appli- Haney, C. (1997). Violence and the capital jury: Mechanisms of
cations (Vol. 1, pp. 71-129). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum moral disengagement and the impulse to condemn to death.
Associates, Inc. Stanford Law Review, 49, 1447-1486.
Bandura, A. (1992). Social cognitive theory of social referencing. In Haney, C., Banks W. C., & Zimbardo, P. G. (1973). Interpersonal dy-
S. Feinman (Ed.), Social referencingand the social construction namics in a simulatedprison. InternationalJournal ofCriminol-
of reality in infancy (pp. 175-208). New York: Plenum. ogy & Penology, 1, 69-97.
Bandura, A. (1997). Self-efficacy: The exercise of control. New Ivie, R. L. (I1980). Images of savagery in American justifications for
York: Freeman. war. Communication Monographs, 47, 270-294.
Bandura, A., Barbaranelli, C., Caprara, G. V., & Pastorelli, C. (I1996). Keen, S. (1986). Faces of the enemy. New York: Harper & Row.
Mechanisms of moral disengagement in the exercise of moral Kelman, H. C. (1973). Violence without moral restraint: Reflections
agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, on the dehumanization of victims and victimizers. Journal of
364-374. Social Issues, 29, 25-61.
Bandura, A., Underwood, B., & Fromson, M. E. (1975). Kelman, H. C., & Hamilton, V. L. (1989). Crimes of obedience: To-
Disinhibition of aggression through diffusion of responsibility ward a social psychology of authority and responsibility. New
and dehumanization of victims. Journal ofResearch in Person- Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
ality, 9, 253-269. Kilham, W., & Mann, L. (1974). Level of destructive obedience as a
Bernard, V., Ottenberg, P., & Redl, F. (1965). Dehumanization: A function of transmitter and executant roles in the Milgram obe-
composite psychological defense in relation to modern war. In dience paradigm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol-
M. Schwebel (Ed.), Behavioral science and human survival (pp. ogy, 29, 696-702.
64-82). Palo Alto, CA: Science and Behavior Books. (Ed.), Per-
Kipnis, D. (1974). The powerholders. In J. T. TedeschiAldine.
Bollinger, D. (1982). Language: The loaded weapon. London: spectives on social power (pp. 82-122). Chicago:
Longman. Kramer, M. (1990). The moral logic ofHizballah. In W. Reich (Ed.),
Burt, M. R. (1980). Cultural myths and support for rape. Journal of Origins of terrorism: Psychologies, ideologies, theologies,
Personality and Social Psychology, 38, 217-230. states ofmind (pp. 131-157). Cambridge, England: Cambridge
Burus, T. R., & Dietz, T. (in press). Human agency and evolutionary University Press.
processes: Institutional dynamics and social revolution. In B. Kwak, K., & Bandura, A. (1998). Role ofperceived self-efficacy and
Wittrock (Ed.), Agency in social theory. Thousand Oaks, CA: moral disengagement in antisocial conduct. Unpublished
Sage. manuscript, Osan College, Seoul, South Korea.
Butterfield, M. (1999, February 14). To rejuvenate gun sales, critics Lerner, M. J., & Miller, D. T. (1978). Just world research and the attri-
say, industry started making more powerful pistols. New York bution process: Looking back and ahead. Psychological Bulle-
Times: International, p. 16. tin, 85, 1030-1051.
CBS reportedly paid 2 fugitives. (1983, September 22). San Fran- Levi, P. (1987). The drowned and the saved. New York: Summit.
cisco Chronicle. Lynch, B. S., & Bonnie, R. J. (Eds.). (1994). Growing up tobacco
Cohen, D., & Nisbett, R. E. (1994). Self-protection and the culture of free: Preventing nicotine addiction in children and youths.
honor: Explaining Southern violence. Personality and Social Washington, DC: National Academy Press.
Psychology Bulletin, 20, 551-567. March, J. G. (1982). Theories of choice and making decisions. Trans-
Dedman, B. (1998, March 3). Executive says he's uncertain about to- action: Social Science and Modern Society, 20, 29-39.
bacco harm. The New York Times, p. A16. Marine, C. (1990, March). Death's doorman. San Francisco Exam-
Diaz, T. (1999). Making a killing: The business of guns in America. iner, p. B5.
New York: New Press. McAlister, A. L., Ama, E., Barroro, C., Peters, R. J., & Kelder, S.
Diener, E. (1977). Deindividuation: Causes and consequences. So- (1999). Promoting tolerance and moral engagement through
cial Behavior and Personality, 5, 143-156. peer modeling. Unpublished manuscript, University of Texas
Diener, E., Dineen, J., Endresen, K., Beaman, A. L., & Fraser, S. C. Health Science Center, Houston.
(1975). Effects of altered responsibility, cognitive set, and mod- McGinnis, J. M., & Foege, W. H. (1993). Actual causes of death in
eling on physical aggression and deindividuation. Journal of the United States. Journal ofthe American MedicalAssociation,
Personality and Social Psychology, 31, 328-337. 270, 2207-2212.
Drew, C. (1998, December 23). RJR subsidiary pleads guilty to McHugo, G. J., Smith, C. A., & Lanzetta, J. T. (1982). The structure
smuggling. The New York Times, p. Al. of self-reports of emotional responses to film segments. Motiva-
Elliott, D. S., & Rhinehart, M. (1995). Moral disengagement, delin- tion and Emotion, 6, 365-385.
quentpeers and delinquent behavior. Unpublished manuscript, Meier, B. (1998a, February 23). Cigarette maker manipulated nico-
University of Colorado, Institute of Behavioral Science. tine, its records suggest. The New York Times, pp. 1, A16.

208
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016
MECHANISMS OF MORAL DISENGAGEMENT
Meier, B. (1998b, January 15). Files of R. J. Reynolds tobacco show Gender violence: Interdisciplinary perspectives (pp. 52-66).
effort on youths. The New York Times, p. AI 0. New York: New York University Press.
Meier, B. (1998c, January 8). U.S. brings its first charges in the to- Skeyhill, T. (Ed.). (1928). Sergeant York: His own life story and war
bacco investigation. The New York Times, p. A 17. diary. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, Doran.
Milgram, S. (1974). Obedience to authority: An experimental view. Sprinzak, E. (1986, September). Fundamentalism, terrorism, andde-
New York: Harper & Row. mocracy: The case of the Gush Emunim underground. Paper
Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and presented at the Woodrow Wilson Center, Washington, DC.
shortcomings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Sprinzak, E. (1990>. The psychopolitical formation of extememe left
Prentice Hall. terrorism in a democracy: The case of the Weathermen. In W.
Oliner, S. P., & Oliner, P. M. (1988). The altruistic personality. New Reich (Ed.), Origins of terrorism: Psychologies, ideologies,
York: Free Press. theologies, states of mind (pp. 65-85). Cambridge, England:
Public Citizen Health Research Group. (1993). The influence of to- Cambridge University Press.
bacco money on the U.S. Congress. Health Letter, 9(11), 1-7. Stein, A. (1988). Quiet heroes. Toronto, Canada: Lester & Orpen
Rapoport, D. C., & Alexander, Y. (Eds.). (1982). The morality ofter- Dennys.
rorism: Religious and secular justification. Elmsford, NY: Thomas, A. (1982). Frank Terpil: Confessions of a dangerous man
Pergamon. [Film]. (Available from Studio Film & Tape, Inc., New York)
Reich, W. (Ed.). (1990). Origins ofterrorism: Psychologies, ideolo- Tilker, H. A. (1970). Socially responsible behavior as a function of
gies, theologies, states of mind. Cambridge, England: Cam- observer responsibility and victim feedback. Journal ofPerson-
bridge University Press. ality and Social Psychology, 14, 95-100.
Rorty, A. 0. (1993). What it takes to be good. In G. Noam & T. E. Zganjar, L. ( 1998, March 5). Forgotten hero of Mai Lai to be honored
Wren (Eds.), The moral self(pp. 28-55). Cambridge, MA: MIT after 30 years. San Francisco Chronicle, p. A9.
Press. Zimbardo, P. G. (1995). The psychology of evil: A situationist per-
Sanday, P. R. (1997). The socio-cultural context of rape: A spective on recruiting good people to engage in anti-social acts.
cross-cultural study. In L. L. O'Toole & J. R. Schiffman (Eds.), Research in Social Psychology, 11, 125-133.

209
Downloaded from psr.sagepub.com at UNIVERSIDAD DE CHILE on January 6, 2016

You might also like