You are on page 1of 15

196    PART V  •  READINGS

deliberators should go back-and-forth, as circum- thumb.” If so, principles might have no role in justi-
stances allow, between an “indirect” sympathy- fying moral decisions. Along these lines, Noddings
based deliberation and principle-based deliberation and Joan Tronto—two prominent care ethicists—
(Railton 1984; Driver 2005 on connecting this to both suggest that any principle general enough to
care ethics). Care ethicists themselves have argued be true will be too broad to be a full justification of
that Kantian ethics is consistent with a sympathetic particular actions. Noddings considers the principle
approach to moral practice (Miller 2005; O’Dowd “always act so as to establish, maintain or enhance
2012). In sum, a combination of sympathy and prin- caring relations” (2002, 30). Tronto considers the
ciples is recommended by a range of mainstream principle that “one should care” (1993, 153). They
ethical theories. Care ethicists can follow suit—and use these principles to demonstrate the emptiness of
some already have. true, general, and universal principles for care ethical
Second, principles are informative. Sometimes, justifications of actions. Crucially, though, these un-
the results of sympathy are unclear or indeterminate: conditional principles are viewed by their authors as
sympathy pulls you towards this person, and towards true. They are just not very rich justifications, since
that person, with seemingly equal strength. Which they don’t say anything about why we should care.
one should you help? In such situations, conscien- This raises the question: are there rich principles
tious carers need general principles to determine of justification that ring true to care ethics? Yes.
whose interests come first. Often, these decisions Here are three examples from the literature. First,
are made by likening the current situation to previ- Eva Feder Kittay’s “principle of social responsibil-
ous ones. This likening can occur only by referring to ity for care”: “[t]o each according to his or her need
general features that the situations share. Recogniz- for care, from each according to his or her capac-
ing these general features, and reacting to them con- ity for care, and such support from social institutions
sistently, brings order to our judgments: “[t]o argue as to make available resources and opportunities to
that no two cases are ever alike is to invite moral those providing care, so that all will be adequately
chaos” (Held 1987, 119). attended in relations that are sustaining” (1999,
Third, principles sometimes rightly overrule sym- 113, emphasis in original). Second, Daniel Eng-
pathy. Consider parents engaging in “tough love,” ster’s “principle of subsidiarity”: “we should shift
policymakers who must prioritise after funding cuts, the actual delivery of care whenever possible to the
or nurses deciding how to divide their time amongst most local and personal levels. We should care for
patients. Here, principles serve to constrain the ef- others whenever possible by enabling them to care
fects of sympathy. Sympathy is intentionally put to for themselves” (2007, 58). Third, my own “depen-
one side, in order to do what it best overall. This is in dency principle”: when an important interest is un-
part because engaging in sympathy—considering an- fulfilled, and you’re capable of fulfilling that interest,
other’s situation from her point of ­view—sometimes and fulfilling the interest will be not too costly, then
blinds us to other morally relevant features of the you have a responsibility to fulfil the interest (Col-
situation. lins 2015, ch. 6). In short, some principles are empty
In sum, we should endorse sympathy in delibera- and uninformative, while others are not. Informative
tion, but not at the complete exclusion of principles. principles might have a justificatory role within the
That is the most that care ethicists can credibly best version of care ethics—we should leave this as
claim—but they are right to claim that much. an open possibility.

1.3 Justification 1.4 Conclusion: Claim 1


If we grant a role for principles in deliberation, A key care ethical insight is that sympathy and direct
this might just be because they are useful “rules of attention to concrete particulars are important in
C ollins   •   Care Ethics: The Four Key Claims      197

deliberation. I have suggested that principles should he has more reason to value, preserve, or promote
also have some role in deliberation, and that care his relationship with his mother than his relationship
ethicists can preserve a place for principles in justifi- with other lonely rest home residents; and (c) his re-
cation (though I haven’t here argued that they should sponsibilities to visit his mother are weightier than
do this). We thus arrive at: any such responsibility he might have to other lonely
residents.
First Claim of Care Ethics. Deliberation should include But care ethicists do not think that the three
sympathy and direct attendance to concrete particulars.
claims of relationship importance apply to all per-
sonal relationships. Many relationships are abusive
or disrespectful to participants, despite having the
general characteristics of personal relationships
mentioned above—simply consider abusive spousal
2.  PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS relationships. So we need to specify the relationships
to which the three claims apply.

2.1 Three Claims About Relationship


Importance 2.2 Which Relationships?
Care ethicists greatly value personal relationships, One option is to say that the claims of relationship
that is (roughly), relationships that are not formally importance apply to those personal relationships that
contracted, that depend on a shared history (and/or are valued by their participants. However, partici-
predicted future) between the participants, and that pants are not always good judges of whether personal
are valued non-instrumentally by the participants. relationships are worthy of emulation, preservation,
In personal relationships, participants tend to take and special attention. Taking this option would mask
one another’s interests as their own: it is good for the power dynamics that limit some people’s abilities
me when something good happens to my relative. to properly assess their relationships’ value—most
Examples of such relationships include parents and notably children, and in many societies women. Re-
children, siblings, friends, and spouses. lationships so strongly inform our values, and do this
Care ethicists make three claims about personal in such a slow and creeping way, that it seems im-
relationships. First, personal relationships are para- possible to trust our own judgments of their value.
digms for the rest of morality. We should take the same Often, we’re too enmeshed in them to judge (Minow
kind of attitude—sympathetic, c­ompassionate—to and Shanley 1996).
everyone that we naturally take to personal relatives A second option suggests that the social
(even if not the same extent) (Noddings 2002, 2, community—and its norms, expectations, and so
­
29; 2010, ch. 3). Second, some of the most morally on—could mark out the valuable relationships. But
valuable actions and attitudes are those that value, this gives too much power to norms and tradition,
preserve, or promote personal relationships (Clem- and not enough to marginalised voices, such as those
ent 1996, 15; Held 1987, 126; Noddings 1999, 3; of women and subordinated cultural groups. And if
Tronto 1993, 78). Third, some of the responsibilities marginalised voices are given input, then we may be
that we have to all persons are weightier when had to left with disagreement within the social community
personal relatives (Kittay 1997, 234; Bubeck 1995, about which relationships are valuable. We would be
229–236). left in a stalemate.
Common-sense accords with these claims. Imag- We can begin to resolve this by noting an assump-
ine a person who does not visit his lonely mother in tion here: the assumption that “relationships are
a rest home, despite living nearby. We think that (a) sources of moral importance.” This is suspect. More
this might indicate a general moral ineptitude; (b) plausibly, relationships—similarly to food, shelter,
198    PART V  •  READINGS

and security—are valuable in virtue of how they preservation, and give rise to weighty obligations. The
affect persons (Pettit 1997, 155). The relationship is first two claims of relationship i­mportance—that the
not the thing for the sake of which we should take the relationship is a paradigm and ought to be preserved—
claims of relationship importance to be true. Rather, are true to the extent that the relationship is of value to
we should take them to be true for the sake of the participants.
people in relationships. For the last kind of relationship importance—
Following this, I suggest the claims of relation- that the relationship is a source of morally weighty
ship importance apply to all and only those personal duties—the story is more complicated. Here we want
relationships that have “value to” their participants. to say that a relationship that has negative value to its
The idea of “value to” a person includes a subjective participants—such as an exploitative relationship—
aspect: part of what adds value to a relationship is might give rise to weighty duties. Care ethicists do
that participants take the relationship to be valuable not disagree with this. But these are not duties of care
to them. One might object to this, since, it seems, an ethics. Recall that care ethics is not a theory of the
abusive relationship’s value is not enhanced by the whole of morality. Morality includes duties that arise
fact that the abused participant takes the relationship out of harming others, out of receiving benefits, out
to be valuable. But we can acknowledge the minimal of making promises and contracts, and so on. It also
value the subjective aspect adds in this case, while includes duties not to interfere with others. These are
emphasising that the subjective aspect does not ex- all important duties—but they are not duties of care
haust a relationship’s value to its participants. An- ethics. Neither are the duties that arise out of non-
other part of what adds value to a relationship is that valuable relationships.
the relationship is in fact life-enhancing for them, That said, the exaltation of “relationships that are
whether they take it to be or not. This is the objective valuable to participants” gets us a wider range of
aspect. In an abusive relationship, the objective dis- duties than might first meet the eye. This is because
value greatly outweighs the subjective value, so that the claims of relationship importance—in particu-
the relationship is disvaluable overall. lar, the second one about relationships being valued,
Why adopt this view of the relevant relation- protected, and promoted—properly apply not just to
ships? A powerful reason relates to the scope of relationships that already have value to participants,
care ethics. Contemporary care ethicists deny that but also to relationships that would have value to par-
their theory applies only to personal relationships. ticipants, if the relationship were formed. If we could
They instead emphasise that the responsibilities of create a relationship that would have value to partici-
care ethics are global: we have them to those at a pants, then care ethics says we have moral reasons
great distance from us (Engster 2007; Held 2006; to form—i.e., promote—that kind of relationship.
Kittay 2005; Miller 2010; Robinson 2011; Ruddick Obviously, these reasons need to be balanced against
1989). This has resulted in a tension within care moral reasons of all other kinds, including reasons to
ethics: on the one hand, personal relationships are care for oneself. And—given what I said above about
still seen as important in the three ways outlined globalising the theory—personal relationships aren’t
earlier. On the other hand, non-personal relation- the only kind of relationships that are relevant here.
ships are recognised as sources of imperatives to If we could form a “relationship” with an impover-
care. How can care ethicists account for the latter ished person that involved us contributing to institu-
imperatives? tional arrangements that benefited that person, and if
They can do it by saying that the importance of any that relationship would have value to them and/or us,
relationship—personal or non-personal—is determined then we have moral reason to form that relationship.
by that relationship’s value to the individuals in that This is part of promoting valuable relationships.
relationship. When our relationships to distant others The suggestion, then, is that the importance of any
have high value to us and to them, these non-personal ­relationship—actual or potential—is determined by
relationships are moral paradigms, are worthy of that relationship’s value to the participants. The special
C ollins   •   Care Ethics: The Four Key Claims      199

role of personal relationships within care ethics— by supporting other carers, and by contributing to
as embodied in the three claims of relationship institutions that care. Care can last a minute or go
­importance—is explained by personal relationships’ on for decades. It occurs on a multitude of levels,
high value to participants. But these are not the only from the individual to the global. I’ll divide care into
relationships we should emulate, promote, and respond two basic kinds: caring attitudes and caring actions.
to. This interpretation allows us to exclude abusive per- Some care ethicists run these together (Tronto 1993,
sonal relationships from being valuable, and, perhaps 108; Held 2004, 60; Ruddick 1980, 348), but I will
most importantly, to make sense of how we can glo- demonstrate that they each have value of their own.
balise and institutionalise the demands of care ethics: The present section focuses on attitudes, while Sec-
we have moral reason to create all sorts of valuable re- tion 4 focuses on actions.
lationships, even over long distances or mediated by What are caring attitudes? In brief, to “care about”
institutions. In some cases, relationships can give rise something is for it to matter to you—and for your
to duties in other ways—such as if the relationship is emotions, desires, decisions, and attention to be in-
exploitative—but this is not part of care ethics. fluenced by how you believe things are going with it.
The possible objects of caring attitudes are numerous:
we can care about someone, something, some place,
2.3 Conclusion: Claim 2 or some time. We can care about types or tokens: we
might care about a type of thing (“interests”), or a type
Care ethicists generally agree that personal relation- of person (“individuals with interests”). We might
ships are moral paradigms that ought to be preserved care about a type of event (“volcanic eruptions”), a
and that generate weighty responsibilities. I sug- type of state of affairs (“poverty”), or a type of prop-
gested that we identify the relevant relationships by erty (“being ill”). Or we might just care about a par-
asking whether they have value to their participants. ticular token—a particular individual with interests, a
So we get Claim 2 of care ethics: particular volcanic eruption, a particular illness of a
particular person, or similar. This type-token distinc-
Second Claim of Care Ethics. To the extent that they tion matches onto a distinction made by Michael Slote
have value to individuals in the relationship, relation-
and Virginia Held (respectively) between “gener-
ships ought to be (a) treated as moral paradigms, (b)
alised” (type-focused) and “specific” (token-focused)
valued, preserved, or promoted/formed, and (c) ac-
knowledged as giving rise to weighty duties. caring attitudes (Slote 1999, 2–3; Held 1993). Caring
can be positively valenced (a pro-attitude, e.g., “I care
about scientific discovery, so I want it to continue”) or
negatively valenced (a con-attitude, e.g., “I care about
3.  CARING ATTITUDES human rights abuses, so I want them to discontinue”).
For you to genuinely not-care about something, you
have to be entirely indifferent to it (“I don’t care about
3.1 What Are Caring Attitudes? what we have for dinner”). In short, caring attitudes
are everywhere, and are easy to hold.
Unsurprisingly, care ethics calls upon agents to But presumably care ethics calls upon agents to
care. Care is multi-faceted. We can care about have only those caring attitudes that are morally
­something—pay attention to it, emotionally invest in valuable. Which caring attitudes are these?
it, worry about it. We can care for something—tend
to it, nurture it, help it thrive. We can take care around
something—make sure it isn’t disrupted, ensure it 3.2 Morally Valuable Caring Attitudes
is left to go on without our interference. We care
through directing our thoughts, through one-on-one Plausibly, caring attitudes are like relationships: valu-
interactions, through coordinated action with others, able in proportion to their value to persons. That
200    PART V  •  READINGS

value might lie in the attitude’s being instrumental Caring about human rights abuses in a negatively
to a person’s wellbeing, being partly constitutive of valenced way is morally valuable.
their wellbeing, or simply being a valuable attitude to But can mere attitudes really be morally valuable?
them or for them, independently of their wellbeing. To answer this, imagine an aged father, Frank, who
Thus caring attitudes have only extrinsic value—they needs to have his house maintained. In one scenario,
are valuable in virtue of their relation to something Frank’s child, Sean, does this out of a personal, deep,
else—but this doesn’t mean that it only has instru- long-lasting attitude of care for his father. In another
mental value—that it is valued only as a means to scenario, a social worker, Wanda, does this because
some further end. Rather, caring attitudes might she’s getting paid. Wanda cares about Frank to some
be non-instrumentally (but extrinsically) valued as extent—she wouldn’t like to see Frank hurt. But
manifestations of love, kindness, forgiveness, or so Wanda’s care doesn’t affect her emotions, decisions,
on—where these goods are intrinsically valuable to desires, attention, and so on nearly as much as, or
persons. in the way that, Sean’s affects his. Wanda doesn’t
Care ethicists, though, are particularly concerned have the same kind of, or extent of, caring attitudes.
with caring attitudes that fulfil persons’ needs Plausibly, Sean’s assistance has value to Frank that
(Bubeck 1995, 132; Engster 2007, 48; Held 2006, Wanda’s assistance does not.
10, 39; Kittay 1999, 133, 233; Miller 2010, 141, How can we explain this? First, a caring attitude
150; Noddings 2010, ch. 7; Sevenhuijsen 1998, 60; can be instrumentally valuable, by enabling atten-
Tronto 1993, 137–141). Needs are the most basic or tion to detail that generates knowledge of this par-
vital constituents of, or means to, a minimally decent ticular person’s interests and a motivation to fulfil
life. Should we restrict morally valuable instances those interests. Second, the caring attitude might
of caring attitudes to those that fulfil needs? I sug- have non-instrumental value, due to the attitude’s
gest not. There may be a stronger, or more urgent, relation to a fact whose truth they indicate—in this
moral imperative to fulfil needs than other interests. case, the fact that Sean loves Frank. Sean’s attitude
But this does not exclude imperatives to fulfil less could have this value despite the fact that Wanda is
basic, urgent, or important interests. It is just that equally disposed to recognise Frank’s needs when
these imperatives will be of a weaker strength. they arise, equally recognising of the specificity of
One plausible view of caring attitudes’ moral his needs, just as motivated to fulfil them (though
value, then, is this. Morally valuable caring at- motivated in a different way, i.e., money), and
titudes have as their object something that has, equally aware of the desirability of fostering caring
or that might affect something that has, interests, attitudes within herself. This is not to say that Wan-
where the caring about is a pro-attitude to the ful- da’s attitude is not caring: Wanda does take a pro-
filment of those interests. This is consistent with stance towards the fulfilment of Frank’s interests.
us caring about things without interests, though But our concern is the moral value of the two caring
such caring has no moral value. It is also consis- attitudes. Sean’s attitude fares better in this regard.
tent with us caring about things without interests We are now in a position to more carefully charac-
(like medicine), where that caring has moral value, terise the kinds of attitudes that are called for by care
if the caring is nonetheless a pro-attitude to the ful- ethics. These are attitudes that (i) have as their object
filment of interests (like the interests of people who something that has interests, or something that might
need medicine). So, this is not to say that morally affect something that has interests; and that (ii) are a
valuable caring attitudes are necessarily a positive positive response (e.g. promoting, respecting, rever-
response to the object of the caring. For example, to ing) to those interests; and that (iii) lead the agent’s
have a negative attitude to human rights abuses— affects, desires, decisions, attention, or so on to be in-
that is, to be invested in such abuses discontinu- fluenced by how the agent believes things are going
ing—is to respond positively to the interests of with the interest-bearer. Clauses (i) and (ii) derive
beings (humans) that are affected by that object. from the moral value of caring attitudes. Clause (iii)
C ollins   •   Care Ethics: The Four Key Claims      201

ensures that the attitude is one of caring, as charac- 4.  CARING ACTIONS
terised in the previous sub-section.

4.1 What Are Caring Actions?


3.3 Responsibilities for Attitudes?
In addition to having attitudes, we care by perform-
An objection arises: attitudes—and particularly the de- ing, practicing, or giving care. I will use the phrases
sires, emotions, and so on that might constitute, cause, “caring for” (as opposed to “about”), “giving care,”
or result from those attitudes, and generate their moral and “taking care of” synonymously, to refer to ac-
value—seem not to be under our voluntary control. It tions of care. This includes actions that intend to
seems we can only have responsibilities to do things leave alone, or not disturb, the thing we care for.
that are under our voluntary control. So, care ethics Caring actions differ from caring attitudes in
cannot say that we “should” have caring attitudes. a number of ways. First, the range of possible ob-
In reply: we can, in many circumstances, bring our- jects is smaller. One does not care for a type of
selves to have caring attitudes, including their motiva- event (“volcanic eruptions,” “human rights abuses,”
tional and emotional aspects. We do this by consciously “scientific discoveries”), or a type of state of affairs
attending to the reasons we have to care about some- (“poverty”), or a property (“having AIDS”). We
thing, downplaying the reasons against caring about might care for (as well care about) those who are af-
the thing, or simply acting as if we care about the thing fected by volcanic eruptions (human rights abuses,
(with the aim that such actions will produce the atti- scientific discoveries, having AIDS), but then we are
tude). And even if this is impossible, we can exercise not caring for these things themselves. Also, care as
long-term cultivation of dispositions and capacities to an action is not open to a “pro” and “con” reading:
experience care emotions—so that the statement “you to care for something is always to respond positively,
ought to care about suffering” (say) would translate rather than negatively, to that thing. And minimally
into “you ought regularly to attend to others’ suffering, caring actions are more costly to realise than mini-
do your best to ignore other demands on your atten- mally caring attitudes. While we care about anything
tion, place yourself in environments where suffering we are not indifferent to, caring for something re-
presents itself, remember or imagine yourself suffer- quires intentional actions or omissions.
ing . . .” and so on. This is perfectly intelligible. Specifically, caring actions are intended in the
manner “trying to do what I believe is good for this
thing.” Why just “trying” and “what I believe”? Con-
3.4 Conclusion: Claim 3 sider a child who keeps a rock wrapped up in a blan-
ket, carries the rock around with him, asks people to
The attitude of care comes in many forms. Care be quiet when he believes the rock is sleeping, and so
ethics calls for those forms that have moral value, on. He is asked whether he is caring for the rock, and
which, I have suggested, are those that are positively he answers affirmatively. Does he actually care for
oriented towards interests. We now have: the rock? He at least intends to. He intends to look
after the rock, tend to it, enable it to live well, and so
Third Claim of Care Ethics. Agents should have caring
on. In short, he does what he believes is in the rock’s
attitudes, that is, attitudes that: (i) have as their object
something that has interests, or something that might interests.
affect something that has interests; and that (ii) are a I suggest that the boy does, in fact, care for the
positive response (e.g. promoting, respecting, revering) rock. He just does not do it very well. It is often dif-
to those interests; and that (iii) lead the agent’s affects, ficult to distinguish doing something badly from not
desires, decisions, attention, or so on to be influenced doing it at all. If I get out paints and use them to rep-
by how the agent believes things are going with the resent the bird outside my window, then I am paint-
interest-bearer. ing the bird even if the painting is unrecognisable
202    PART V  •  READINGS

as a bird. In such cases, my intentions (along with, fulfil any interests of the rock. The rock does not
perhaps, social conventions) are key to determining have any interests. The boy’s actions are caring. But
whether I am painting the bird. For caring, I suggest, they have less moral value than if the rock had inter-
it is all in the intentions. To care for someone is to ests that were being fulfilled. Effects matter.
do what you believe is in the interests of that thing— One might object as follows. Imagine you and I
even if that thing, in fact, lacks interests, or even if each stumble upon injured dogs. We each attempt
you are incorrect about their interests. (Importantly, to drive our dog to the nearest vet. While your dog
this is what it takes for an action to be care as op- reaches the vet in time and is healed, I get caught
posed to non-care, not what it takes for an action to in traffic and arrive five minutes too late. It seems
be good care as opposed to bad care.) odd, one might think, to say that your action is more
The intention is not a very strict condition. The valuable than mine. Your action had better effects,
carer need not consciously entertain their intention as but this seems irrelevant for the moral assessment of
“doing what I believe is in the recipient’s interests” the action.
and they need not have a full-blown concept of inter- However, we should distinguish: (i) the sources
ests. They just need an implicit belief that the action of an action’s moral value, (ii) the conditions under
is good for the recipient in some way. Children, for which an agent morally ought to perform the action,
example, can perfectly well care for their parents, (iii) the conditions under which the agent should be
without a hint of reflection on the fact. Moreover, praised or blamed for performing the action. You
fulfilling the person’s interests need not be the final and I deserve equal praise for our dog-saving efforts.
intention of the carer—the care can be intended to be And assuming that I couldn’t reasonably have known
instrumental to some other aim. Consider our social about the traffic, we each had an equally weighty
worker Wanda, who intends to fulfil Frank’s interests reason to do what we could for our respective dogs.
only as a means to a paycheck. She cares for Frank, But it is nonetheless true that your action was more
despite not caring much about Frank. valuable—was better care—than my action, through
As a result, I will use the following definition of no fault of my own. That is to say, when we are ret-
caring action (to be distinguished, in the next sub- rospectively assessing the value of an action (as op-
section, from morally valuable caring action): posed to prospectively assessing whether the action
should be performed, or retrospectively assessing the
an action is caring if and only if it is performed under praiseworthiness or blameworthiness of the agent),
the (perhaps tacit) intention of fulfilling (or going some
its actual effects matter, alongside intentions and
way to fulfilling) interest(s) that the agent perceives
some perceived moral person (the recipient) to have.
beliefs.
Additionally, some effects matter more than
others. This point is frequently made by care ethi-
cists, who, as we have seen, focus on persons’
4.2 Morally Valuable Caring Actions needs. While care might be directed at fulfilling any
­interest—however trivial—care will have value if it
The above definition is broad, and allows more spe- fulfils a more vital, important, or compelling interest
cific definitions to be used for specific purposes. In (a need). By a­ llowing that care is more valuable if it
particular, we should whittle this definition down fulfils ­interests—and even more valuable if it fulfils
so that it specifies only those caring actions that are the most important interests—we are able to avoid the
called for by care ethics, that is, the morally valuable “paternalism objection” to care ethics. This is the ob-
caring actions. jection that care ethicists endorse actions that patro-
In defining caring action, I talked only about the nise, belittle, or otherwise undermine the autonomy
intentions and beliefs of the caregiver. These things of the care recipient—by fulfilling interests that are
enhance moral value. But the effects matter greatly. trivial, or not the ones the care recipient wants ful-
Take the boy and his rock. The boy’s actions do not filled. For morally valuable caring actions, it is not
C ollins   •   Care Ethics: The Four Key Claims      203

enough that the action is intended to fulfil important plans, projects, and purposes are inseparable from,
interests: to be valuable, the care must actually fulfil and hugely influenced by, those around us. Many
important interests. In many cases, these will be the care ethicists emphasise that the world of ethics is
interests the recipient themselves endorses, including constituted by complex webs of relationships be-
empowerment, autonomy, independence (insofar as tween fragile, embodied human beings. With the
this is ever possible), and so on. four key normative claims now on the table, it is
I suggest the following, then, about morally valu- easy to see how they might arise out of a deep ap-
able caring actions. The moral value of caring action preciation of these descriptive claims. But the four
is a function of (1) how well that action fulfils the key claims are what make care ethics a normative
recipients’ interests (where needs are more impor- ethical theory.
tant than other interests), and (2) the strength of the Although moral theorists who do not call them-
agent’s intentions to fulfil the recipient’s interests. selves care ethicists may endorse the four claims,
(2) is separable from (1). An action can be caring the claims are unlikely to be the central or most im-
despite having little moral value, just as long as it portant parts of non-care ethical theories. Non-care
has the right intentions (i.e. fulfilling perceived inter- ethicists are unlikely to be interested in intricately
ests). Above this threshold, a caring action can have analysing actions of care in particular, or in vindi-
more or less moral value, as a function of (1) and (2). cating sympathetic modes of deliberation in particu-
lar, as a central part of their theoretical edifice. It is
the combination of these claims, and their status as
4.3 Conclusion: Claim 4 the most important normative aspects of the theory,
which makes care ethics distinctive.
Caring actions are actions performed with intentions
to fulfil interests. These actions are morally valuable
in proportion to the strength of the intention and the REFERENCES
goodness of the effects. That is: Bubeck, Diemut. 1995. Care, Gender and Justice.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Fourth Claim of Care Ethics. (i) Agents should perform Clement, Grace. 1996. Care, Autonomy, and Justice:
actions that are performed under the (perhaps tacit) in- Feminism and the Ethic of Care. Boulder: Westview Press.
tention of fulfilling (or going some way to fulfilling) Collins, Stephanie. 2015. The Core of Care Ethics.
interest(s) that the agent perceives some moral person Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
(the recipient) to have; (ii) the strength of this “should” Driver, Julia. 2005. “Consequentialism and Feminist
is determined by the moral value of action, which is a Ethics.” Hypatia 20(4), 183–199.
function of the strength of the intention, the likelihood Engster, Daniel. 2007. The Heart of Justice: A Political
that the action will fulfil the interest, and the extent to Theory of Caring. New York: Oxford University Press.
which the interest is appropriately described as a “need.” Gilligan, Carol. 1982. In a Different Voice. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Held, Virginia. 1987. “Feminism and Moral Theory.”
Pp. 111–128 in E. F. Kittay and D. Meyers (eds), Women
CONCLUSION and Moral Theory. Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.
Held, Virginia. 1993. Feminist Morality. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Held, Virginia. 2004. “Taking Care: Care as Practice
These four claims are merely the normative claims and Value.” Pp. 59–71 in C. Calhoun (ed.), Setting the
of care ethics. Many care ethicists make descrip- Moral Compass: Essays by Women Philosophers. Oxford:
tive claims that support their overall outlooks. For Oxford University Press.
example, many care ethicists endorse a relational Held, Virginia. 2006. The Ethics of Care: Personal,
view of autonomy, according to which autonomous Political, and Global. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
204    PART V  •  READINGS

Held, Virginia. 2014. “The Ethics of Care as Normative Noddings, Nel. 2010. The Maternal Factor: Two
Guidance: Comment on Gilligan.” Journal of Social Paths to Morality. Los Angeles: University of California
Philosophy 45(1), 107–115. Press.
Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: O’Dowd, Ornaith. 2012. “Care and Abstract Principles.”
Oxford University Press. Hypatia 27(2), 407–422.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1997. “Human Dependency and Pettit, Philip. 1997. “Love and its Place in Moral
Rawlsian Equality.” Pp. 219–266 in D. T. Meyers (ed.), Discourse.” Pp. 153–163 in R. Lamb (ed.), Love Analyzed.
Feminist Rethink the Self. Colorado: Westview Press. Boulder: Westview Press.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love’s Labor: Essays on Railton, Peter. 1984. “Alienation, Consequentialism,
Women, Equality and Dependence. New York: Routledge. and the Demands of Morality.”  Philosophy & Public
Kittay, Eva Feder. 2005. “Dependency, Difference and Affairs 13(2), 134–171.
the Global Ethic of Longterm Care.” Journal of Political Robinson, Fiona. 2011. The Ethics of Care: A Feminist
Philosophy 13(4), 443–469. Approach to Human Security. Philadelphia: Temple
Kohlberg, Lawrence. 1973. “The Claim to Moral University Press.
Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral Judgment.” Journal Ruddick, Sara. 1980. “Maternal Thinking.” Feminist
of Philosophy 70(18). Studies 6(2), 342–367.
Miller, Sarah Clark. 2005. “Need, Care and Obligation.” Ruddick, Sara. 1989. Maternal Thinking: Toward a
Royal Institute of Philosophy 80, supp. 57 (supplement on Politics of Peace. Boston: Beacon Press.
“The Philosophy of Need”), 137–160. Sevenhuijsen, Selma. 1998. Citizenship and the Ethics
Miller, Sarah Clark. 2010. “Cosmopolitan Care.” Ethics of Care: Feminist Considerations on Justice, Morality, and
and Social Welfare special issue on “Care Ethics: New Politics. New York: Routledge.
Theories and Applications” 4(2), 145–157. Slote, Michael. 1999. “Caring Versus the
Minow, Martha and Mary Lyndon Shanley. 1996. Philosophers.” Philosophy of Education 1999, 25–35.
“Relational Rights and Responsibilities: Revisioning the Slote, Michael. 2007. The Ethics of Care and Empathy.
Family in Liberal Political Theory and Law.” Hypatia London: Routledge.
11(1), 4–29. Tronto, Joan C. 1993. Moral Boundaries: A Political
Noddings, Nel. 1984. Caring: A Feminine Approach Argument for an Ethic of Care. London: Routledge.
to Ethics and Moral Education. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Noddings, Nel. 1999. “Two Concepts of Caring.” NOTE
Philosophy of Education 1999, 36–39. 1. For present purposes, “sympathy” and “empathy”
Noddings, Nel. 2002. Starting at Home: Caring and can be treated synonymously, though there are subtle dis-
Social Policy. Los Angeles: University of California Press. tinctions that are relevant for other purposes.

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS
1.  What are care ethicists’ arguments against using principles in ethical deliberation? Do you find
those arguments compelling? Why or why not?
2.  What does Claim 2 (about the importance of relationships) mean for how we should live our lives?
Would taking Claim 2 seriously dramatically affect how you live your life? Why or why not?
3.  In what sense does Collins say the effects of one’s caring actions matter morally? Do you agree with
her claim about this? Why or why not?
4.  In what ways are the key claims of care ethics at odds with deontology, consequentialism, and virtue
ethics? In what ways do they overlap with those theories?
M encius   •  Essential Mengzi: Selected Passages with Traditional Commentary      205

MENCIUS (CA. 372–289 BCE)


TRANSLATED BY BRYAN VAN NORDEN

Essential Mengzi: Selected Passages with


Traditional Commentary

Mencius is known as Mengzi in Chinese; the book that records his discussions with various
rulers and disciples in ancient China is also called Mengzi. Reading the Mengzi is a bit differ-
ent than reading most Western philosophers because the text conveys Mencius’s teachings by
relating Mencius’s aphorisms and stories about Mencius talking to other people. You some-
times need to know something about ancient Chinese history or culture to understand the
point that Mencius is making in each passage. To help with that, even Chinese scholars have
typically read the Mengzi along with traditional commentaries, such as those by the great
twelfth-century philosopher Zhu Xi. In the excerpts below, the translator has included some
of this commentary, along with his own, to help you understand the meaning of the various
passages. You’ll find these commentaries set off in the text next to the Chinese character 注
(zhù), which means “to annotate” or “to comment.”

GUIDING QUESTIONS
1.  What does Mencius mean by “profit”? What is his main criticism of focusing on profit?
2.  In 1A3 (i.e., chapter 3 of Book 1A), Mencius compares King Hui to soldiers who flee from battle
but turn around after fifty paces. What point is Mencius making with that analogy?
3.  What skill is Mencius trying to encourage King Xuan to practice in 1A7?
4.  What point is Mencius trying to make about human nature with the story about the child near the
well in 2A6?
5.  What is Mencius trying to say about virtue in 2A9? In what other passages does he make a similar
point?
6.  In what ways do the stories about Shun in 5A1, 5A2, and 5A3 seem inconsistent? What point is
Mencius making by telling all three stories?
7.  Does Mencius think that human nature is good or not good? What arguments does he give for his
view in Book 6A?
8.  What kinds of moral arguments do you see Mencius making in the text? For instance, is he ap-
pealing to obligations, consequences, or virtues? Is he making arguments by analogy or offering
examples to support or undermine intermediate moral principles? (If you’re not used to reading
Chinese philosophy, Mencius might present some of these arguments in a slightly different way
than you’re used to seeing, but they’re there!)

Reprinted with permission of Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. All rights reserved.
206    PART V  •  READINGS

BOOK 1A China] that encouraged people to judge actions


in terms of the benefits (or “profit”) they bring to
people in general and not just to oneself or one’s
group.  .  .  . But Mengzi argues that this practice
1. Mengzi had an audience with King Hui of Liang.
is self-undermining: aiming directly at profit is,
The king said, “Venerable sir, you have not regarded
paradoxically, unprofitable.
hundreds of leagues too far to come, so you must
have a way of profiting my state.” 3. King Hui of Liang said, “We use our heart to the
Mengzi replied, “Why must Your Majesty utmost for our state. When the region within the river
speak of ‘profit’? Let there simply be benevolence has a famine, we move some of the people to the
[rén] and righteousness [yì]. If Your Majesty says, region to the east of river and move grain to the region
‘How can I profit my state?’ the Chief Counsel- within the river. When there is a famine in the region
ors will say, ‘How can I profit my clan?’ and the to the east of river, we do likewise. When we examine
nobles and commoners will say, ‘How can I profit the governments of neighboring states, there are none
my self?’ Superiors and subordinates will seize that use their hearts to the utmost like we do. Why is
profit from each other, and the state will be endan- it that the people of neighboring states do not grow
gered. When the ruler in a state that can field ten fewer and our people do not grow more numerous?”
thousand chariots is assassinated, it will invari-
ably be by a clan that can field a thousand chari- 注 Zhu Xi explains, “He moves the people in order to
ots. When the ruler in a state that can field a thou- get them to the food. He moves the grain to give it to
sand chariots is assassinated, it will invariably those too old or young to move.”
be by a clan that can field a hundred chariots. To
Mengzi replied, “Your Majesty is fond of war, so
have a thousand out of ten thousand or a hundred
allow me to use war as an illustration. Thunderingly,
out of a thousand is plenty. But when people put
the drums spur the soldiers on. Blades clash together.
profit before righteousness, they cannot be satis-
Casting aside their armor and weapons, they run.
fied without grasping for more.1
Some stop after running a hundred paces; some stop
“Never have the benevolent left their parents
after running only fifty paces. How would it be if
behind. Never have the righteous put their ruler last.
those who ran fifty paces were to laugh at those who
Let Your Majesty speak only of benevolence and
ran a hundred paces?”
righteousness. Why must one speak of ‘profit’?”
The king said, “That is not acceptable. They
注 Zhu Xi comments, “If one accords with the Heav- simply did not run a hundred paces. But this too is
enly Pattern, one will not seek profit, but one will running.”
naturally never fail to profit. If one submits to human Mengzi replied, “If Your Majesty understands
desires, then one will never obtain profit though one this, then you will not expect your people to be more
seeks it, and harm will follow upon it. . . . This is the numerous than those of neighboring states. . . . ”
profound meaning with which the Mengzi begins.
This is something learners should carefully examine 注 Notice the subtle irony in Mengzi’s comment, “Your
and clearly understand.” Majesty is fond of war, so allow me to use war as
Cheng Yi said, “A gentleman never fails to desire an illustration.” Mengzi’s general point is that King
profit, but if one is single-mindedly focused on profit, Hui only understands a small part of good govern-
then it leads to harm. If there is only benevolence ment. He goes on to explain other policies that the
and righteousness, then one will not seek profit, but king needs to enact. . . .
one will never fail to profit.”
[This passage] can be read as a criticism of 7. King Xuan of Qi . . . said, “What must one’s Virtue
Mohism, a consequentialist philosophy [in ancient be like so that one can become King?”2
M encius   •  Essential Mengzi: Selected Passages with Traditional Commentary      207

Mengzi said, “One cares for the people and be- does one distinguish between them and exchange
comes King. This is something no one can stop.” the sheep for the ox? Mengzi intentionally sets up
The king said, “Can one such as ourselves care this difficulty, desiring the king to examine himself
for the people? and seek his fundamental heart. The king seems
unable to do so. . . .
Mengzi said, “You can.”
The king said, “How do you know that we
Mengzi said, “There is no harm. What you did
can?”
was just a technique for (cultivating your) benev-
Mengzi said, “I heard your attendant Hu He say,
olence. You saw the ox but had not seen the sheep.
While the king was sitting up in his hall, an ox was led Gentlemen cannot bear to see animals die if they
past below. The king saw it and said, “Where is the ox have seen them living. If they hear their cries
going?” Hu He replied, “We are about to ritually anoint of suffering, they cannot bear to eat their flesh.
a bell with its blood.” The king said, “Spare it. I cannot Hence gentlemen keep their distance from the
bear its frightened appearance, like an innocent going kitchen.”
to the execution ground.” Hu He replied, “So should
we dispense with the anointing of the bell?” The king 注 Zhu Xi comments, “On the one hand, killing the
said, “How can that be dispensed with? Exchange it ox was something that the king could not bear
for a sheep.” to do. On the other hand, anointing the bell was
something that could not be dispensed with.  .  .  .
Mengzi continued, “I do not know if this happened.” When he saw the ox, this heart had already been
The king said, “It happened.” expressed and could not be repressed. But he had
Mengzi said, “This heart is sufficient to become not yet seen the sheep, so . . . there were no feel-
King. The commoners all thought Your Majesty was ings to hinder. Hence, exchanging the sheep for
the ox allowed for the two (i.e., the heart and the
being stingy. But I knew that Your Majesty simply
ritual) to be complete without harm. This is how it
could not bear the suffering of the ox.”
is a technique of benevolence.  .  .  . Now, humans
The king said, “That is so. There were indeed are the same as animals in being alive but are dif-
commoners who said that. But although Qi is a small ferent categories of things. Hence, we use animals
state, how could I be stingy about one ox? It was just for rituals, and our heart that does not bear their
that I could not bear its frightened appearance, like suffering applies only as far as they are seen and
an innocent going to execution ground. Hence, I ex- heard. Keeping one’s distance from the kitchen is a
changed it for a sheep.” technique used to cultivate this heart and broaden
Mengzi said, “Let Your Majesty not be surprised one’s benevolence.”
at the commoners taking you to be stingy. You took
a [big] thing and exchanged it for a [small] thing. The king was pleased and said, “The Odes say,
How could they understand it? If Your Majesty were Another person had the heart,
pained at its being innocent and going to the execu- I measured it.
tion ground, then what is there to choose between an
ox and a sheep?” This describes you, Master. I was the one who did it.
The king laughed, saying, “What was this feeling, I examined myself and sought to find my heart but
actually? It’s not the case that I grudged its value and failed to understand it. But when you discussed it,
exchanged it for a sheep. But it makes sense that the my heart was moved. So in what way does this heart
commoners would say I was stingy.” accord with becoming King?”
注 Zhu Xi says, “This means that the ox and sheep are 注 Zhu Xi comments, “Because of Mengzi’s words, the
both going to die although innocent. In what ways king’s heart from the previous day sprouts again.
208    PART V  •  READINGS

Consequently, he understands that this heart does and elder brothers of others. ‘To treat as young ones’
not come from outside, but he still does not under- is to nurture young ones. ‘Your young ones’ means
stand how to examine its root and extend it. your children and younger brothers. ‘The young
ones of others’ means the sons and younger brothers
Mengzi said, “Suppose there were someone who of others. . . .”
reported to Your Majesty, ‘My strength is sufficient
to lift five hundred pounds, but not sufficient to lift
one feather. My eyesight is sufficient to examine the BOOK 1B
tip of an autumn hair, but I cannot see a wagon of
firewood.’ Would your Majesty accept that?”
The king said, “No.” 5. King Xuan of Qi asked, “People all tell me to
Mengzi said, “In the present case your kindness destroy the Bright Tower. Should I destroy it or
is sufficient to reach animals, but the effects do not leave it?”
reach the commoners. How is this different from Mengzi replied, “The Bright Tower is the tower
the examples I just gave? Hence, one fails to lift a of a King. If your Majesty desires to put into effect
feather only because one does not use one’s strength. Kingly government, do not destroy it.”
One fails to see a wagon of firewood only because The king said, “May I hear more about Kingly
one does not use one’s eyesight. The commoners fail government?”
to receive care only because one does not use one’s Mengzi replied, “In former times, King Wen ruled
kindness. Hence, Your Majesty fails to become King his state like this. For farmers, there was the nine-
because you do not act, not because you are unable one system [of field management]. For those in posi-
to act. . . .” tions of responsibility, there were stipends for their
注 Zhu Xi comments, “People have the most valu- descendants. The customs officers of the roads and
able natures of anything in Heaven and Earth. markets made inspections but levied no duties. The
Hence, people are in the same category as other people were not prohibited from fishing in the ponds
people and are affectionate to each other. Con- and weirs. Guilt for crime did not extent to the crimi-
sequently, the expression of compassion to the nals’ wives. The old without wives were called ‘wid-
people is very immediate, but to animals it is owers,’ the old without husbands were ‘widows,’ the
slow.  .  .  . In the present case, the king is al- old without children were ‘bereft,’ the young without
ready able to extend this heart [of benevolence] fathers were ‘orphans.’ These four were the poorest
to animals. So his failure to care for the people among the people and had none to bring their cares
and become King is not because he is unable
to. King Wen, in applying benevolent government,
to act. It only comes from his not being willing
to act.”
put these four first. The Odes say,

“Treat your elders as elders, and extend it to Fitting it is for those with funds
the elders of others; treat your young ones as To be sad for these wretched, lonely ones.
young ones, and extend it to the young ones of
The king exclaimed, “What excellent teachings!”
others, and you can turn the world in the palm of
Mengzi responded, “If Your Majesty regards
your hand. . . . Hence, if one extends one’s kind-
them as excellent, then why do you not put them into
ness, it will be sufficient to care for all within the
effect?”
Four Seas. . . .”
The king said, “We have a weakness. We are fond
注 Zhu Xi explains, “ ‘To treat as elders’ is to serve the of wealth.”
elderly. ‘Your elders’ means your father and elder Mengzi responded, “In former times, Duke Liu of
brothers. ‘The elders of others’ means the fathers Zhou was fond of wealth. The Odes say,
M encius   •  Essential Mengzi: Selected Passages with Traditional Commentary      209

They stacked, they stored, manner in which sages fully use their natures. To
Bundled up dried goods, give free reign to one’s desires and be selfishly inter-
In bags, in sacks, ested in oneself alone is the way in which the masses
extinguish the Heavenly in themselves. . . .”
Thinking to gather together and bring glory.
His bows and arrows were displayed,
With shields, spears, and battle-axes,
He commenced the march against Bin. BOOK 2A
Hence those who stayed at home had loaded gra-
naries, and those who marched had full provisions.
6. Mengzi said, “All humans have hearts that are not
Only then could they ‘commence the march.’ If Your
unfeeling toward others. . . .
Majesty is fond of wealth but treats the common-
“The reason why I say that all humans have hearts
ers the same, what difficulty is there in becoming [a
that are not unfeeling toward others is this. Suppose
great] King?”3
someone suddenly saw a child about to fall into a
注 Zhu Xi comments, “Mengzi means that Duke Liu’s well: anyone in such a situation would have a feeling
people were satisfied with their wealth because, al- of alarm and compassion—not because one sought
though he was fond of wealth, he was able to extend to get in good with the child’s parents, not because
his own heart so that it reached to the people. . . .” one wanted fame among one’s neighbors and friends,
and not because one would dislike the sound of the
The king said, “We have a weakness. We are fond child’s cries.
of sex.”
Mengzi responded, “In former times, King Tai 注 Note that Mengzi does not say that every human
of Zhou was fond of sex, and loved his wife. The would necessarily act to save the child. All he claims
Odes say, is that any human would have at least a momentary
feeling . . . of genuine compassion, and that the re-
The Ancient Duke Danfu action would occur “suddenly” (which shows that
it is not the result of calculations of self-interest).
Came riding his horse in the morning,
This passage is, in part, a response to the “ethical
Along the banks of the Western waters. egoist” Yang Zhu, who seems to have claimed that
He came to the foot of Mount Qi, only self-interested motivations are part of human
With his Lady Jiang. nature. . . .
They came and both settled there.
“From this we can see that if one is without the
At that time, there were no bitter women in private, feeling of compassion, one is not human. If one is
or any unmarried men in public. If Your Majesty is without the feeling of disdain, one is not human.
fond of sex but treats the commoners the same, what If one is without the feeling of deference, one is
difficulty is there in becoming [a great] King?” not human. If one is without the feeling of approval
and disapproval, one is not human. The feeling of
注 Zhu Xi comments, “In my humble opinion, from the
compassion is the sprout of benevolence. The feel-
opening chapter of [Book 1B] down to this one, the
ing of disdain is the sprout of righteousness. The
general idea is the same. Whether it is the delights
of making music (1B1), parks (1B2), touring (1B4), feeling of deference is the sprout of propriety. The
of the heart that is fond of courage (1B3), wealth, feeling of approval and disapproval is the sprout of
or sex (1B5), these are all part of the Heavenly Pat- wisdom.
tern that human feelings cannot lack. . . . To accord “People’s having these four sprouts is like their
with the Pattern and be impartial to the world is the having four limbs. To have these four sprouts, yet
210    PART V  •  READINGS

to claim that one is incapable (of Virtue), is to steal Heaven and Earth in giving birth to things. One
from oneself. To say that one’s ruler is incapable is to gets it first of all, and it links all four virtues
steal from one’s ruler. In general, having these four together. . . . Because one is not benevolent, one
sprouts within oneself, if one knows to fill them all is not wise. Because one is not wise, one does
out, it will be like a fire starting up, a spring breaking not understand wherein propriety and righteous-
ness lie.”
through! If one can merely fill them out, they will be
sufficient to care for all within the Four Seas. If one
“If you are ashamed of it, there is nothing as
merely fails to fill them out, they will be insufficient
good as becoming benevolent. Benevolence is like
to serve one’s parents.”
archery. An archer corrects himself and only then
shoots. If he shoots but does not hit the mark, he does
注 A “normal,” healthy human has four limbs. Simi- not resent the one who defeats him but simply turns
larly, a normal human has the four “sprouts.” But,
and seeks for it in himself.”
as the comparison to limbs suggests, it is possible to
lose the sprouts.
注 Zhu Xi comments, “He does not discuss wisdom,
Mengzi thinks the capacity for virtue is innate
propriety, and righteousness, because benevo-
in humans, but it must be cultivated (“filled out”) in
lence encompasses the entire substance. If one can
order for us to become fully virtuous. . . .
become benevolent, then the other three are in its
midst. . . .”
7. Mengzi said, “Is the arrow-maker less benevolent
than the armor-maker? Yet the arrow-maker only fears 8. Mengzi said, “Kongzi’s disciple Zilu was
that he may not harm people; the armor-marker only pleased if someone informed him of his faults.
fears that he may harm people. The s­haman-healer When King Yu heard good teachings he bowed
and the coffin-maker are the same way, respectively. down in thanks. The Great Shun was even greater
Hence, one may not fail to be careful about one’s than they. He was good at unifying himself with
choice of craft. others. He put himself aside and joined with
others. He delighted in copying from others in
注 The arrow-maker and the coffin-maker are born order to do good. From plowing, planting, making
with the same heart of benevolence as the armor-
pottery, and fishing on up to being Emperor—he
maker and the shaman-healer. But their choices of
never failed to copy from others. To copy others
career and way of life determine whether they want
humans to live or die. when they do good is to do good with others.
Hence, for a gentleman, nothing is greater than to
“Kongzi said, ‘To dwell in benevolence is beau- do good with others.”
tiful; if one chooses to not dwell in benevolence,
注 Zhu Xi explains how the people mentioned form a
how can one be wise?’ .  .  .  If one is not benevo-
hierarchy. “Zilu was pleased that he heard about his
lent though nothing prevents it, this is to fail to be faults so he could reform them. Such was his cour-
wise. If one fails to be benevolent and fails to be age in self-cultivation.” Zhou Dunyi commented,
wise, then one lacks propriety and righteousness. “Nowadays, when people have a fault, they are
This is to be the lackey of other people. To be the not pleased to be corrected by others. This is like
lackey of other people yet to be ashamed of being a concealing an illness and shunning medicine.” Zhu
lackey is like being a bow-maker yet to be ashamed Xi continues, “In contrast, King Yu did not wait to
of making bows, or to be an arrow-maker yet to be have a fault, but was capable of humbling himself
ashamed of making arrows. to accept what was good in the world.” Finally,
Shun was greater than Zilu or King Yu, because he
注Z
 hu Xi explains this paragraph in the terms of the did not await being told criticisms or hearing good
unity of the virtues: “Benevolence is the heart of advice. . . .

You might also like