You are on page 1of 13

Kant and the Paradox of Respect

Author(s): William W. Sokoloff


Source: American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 45, No. 4 (Oct., 2001), pp. 768-779
Published by: Midwest Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2669323 .
Accessed: 29/05/2014 13:32

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Midwest Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Journal of Political Science.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KantandtheParadox
ofRespect
William
W.SokoloffUniversity
ofMassachusettsat Amherst

Kant is criticizedby postmodernists


(Connolly)and mis-appropriatedfor
T hisstudyreassesses in
theroleoffeeling-theparadoxofrespect,
particular-in Immanuel Kant and the ways it complicateshis
conservativepoliticalends (Rawls) moral philosophy.Kant is classifiedas the philosopherof human
Myessay on Kant is skeptical of both reason,but he is simultaneously a philosopherof feeling.'Withthefeeling
tendencies and offersan alternative of respect,Kant lodged a crisisin the centerof his practicalphilosophy
interpretationthatfocuses on the whichhas provedto be a significant sourceof contentionamong promi-
paradox of respect. Kant is nota cold nentcommentators. Tracingthecontoursof thisproblemmaylead to a re-
rationalistbut rathera radical thinker assessmentofthevalueand limitsof Kant'sethicalmeaningat a timewhen
who anticipatesthe ideas of Derrida. hiswritings arebecomingincreasingly unpopular.
Throughexaminingthe feelingof Criticsof KantincludingHonig (1993), Coles (1997), Connolly(1995,
respect and its relationshipto philo- 1999,2000),and othersdetectproblemsin hispracticalphilosophy and con-
sophical foundationsand freedomin cludethathe is,forlackofa betterexpression,conservative.2Althoughthese
the Groundworkof the Metaphysics readershaveprovocative and insightful theyhaveoverstated
interpretations,
of Morals and the Critiqueof Practical theircase. Not onlyare thereresourceswithintheKantianprojectthatcan
Reason, Kantianethics are cast in a rejuvenateradicalpoliticalthought,freedomforexample,but also because
new light.I argue thatthe affirmation
ofthe paradoxical elements in the
feelingof respect can expand con- WilliamW. Sokoloffis a Ph.D.Candidatein theDepartment of PoliticalScienceat the
ceptualizationsof the foundationsfor Universityof Massachusettsat Amherst. theHeribertRamsMemorial
He is currently
Fellowat theUniversity Europahaus2, EG,Zimmer7, Ploeck61,69117
of Heidelberg,
ethico-politicalpractice,but firstwe Heidelberg,Germany (wsokoloff2000@yahoo.com).
mustmove beyond readings that
I wouldliketo thanktheInternational Programs Officeat theUniversity ofMassachu-
domesticate or dismiss Kant.The settsatAmherst and theKultusministerium desLandesBaden-Wuerttemberg fora Fel-
positiveresultof thisexpansion is a lowshipin Germany thatmadewriting thisarticlepossible.I also wishto thankNicho-
Kantianethic of paradox. las Xenos,JamesDer Derian,AndrewParker, Susan Meld Shell,M. J.Peterson, John
AnsonWarner, E. C. Graf,WilliamMauriceSprague,and theanonymousreviewers for
thisjournalfortheirgenerouscommentson thisarticle.I thankthePhilosophisches
SeminarandtheInstitut fuerPolitische
Wissenschaft attheUniversity ofHeidelberg for
permissionto use theirlibraries. I wouldliketo thanktheeditorsat theAJPS.
Finally,
' Thisstudyowesmuchto Fenves(1991),Hamacher(1996),and Nancy(1993).
2Although Honigclaimsthatrespectis a "paradoxically hybrid, rational,moralfeeling"
(1993,26, 18),she does notpursuethedestabilizing implications of thisinsightand
concludesthattwoof thethreestrandsofKantianrespectare"didacticand disciplin-
ary";butHonigshouldbe applaudedbecausesheacknowledged theplurality ofrespect.
Coles arguesthatKant'sthinking radically eclipsestheotherand "'respect'is entwined
witha systematic kindofoblivion,imperialism, and theft"(l 997,24,4); I commenton
Coles'sremarks on Kantingreater detaillaterin thisarticle.Connolly(1999; 1995,235)
overemphasizes thepurityof Kantianpracticalreasonand insufficiently examinesthe
ambiguousrolethatrespectoccupiesin Kant'sethics.Eventhoughtheremaybe mul-
ofrespect,
tipletraditions ConnollyinvokestheKantianlanguagehe disavowswhenhe
appealsto"agonistic respect";Adorno(1973) claimsthatKantis repressive andauthori-
tarian.In contrast a thinker
to thesecritics, whoinsistedon theimportance ofKantfor
thefuture ofphilosophy is Benjamin:"It is of thegreatestimportance forthephiloso-
phyof thefuture to recognizeand sortoutwhichelementsof theKantianphilosophy
shouldbe adoptedand cultivated, whichshouldbe reworked, and whichshouldbe re-
jected"(1989,3).
American ofPoliticalScience,Vol.45,No. 4, October2001,Pp.768-779
Journal
?2001 bytheMidwestPoliticalScienceAssociation

768

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 769

Kant's writingsdo not constitutea unified corpus.3 "Consistency is the greatestobligationof a philosopher
Velkley(1989) claimsthatKantshiftsfroman analytical, and yetthemostrarelyfound"(CritiqueofPracticalRea-
logical,and cognitiveorientation to a synthesizing,spon- son 22). Even thoughKantvalues philosophicalconsis-
taneous,and practicalone. Giventhisturn,theKantian tency,he suggeststhattheparadoxcould servea critical
projectis hauntedby ambiguityand tension,but these function.This is apparentwherehe explicitlydiscusses
momentstend to be insufficiently examinedor are ig- the paradox in a sectionentitled"On Egotism"in An-
noredaltogether. thropologyfrom a PragmaticPointofView(1978, 10-13).
Throughan analysisof thefeelingof respectand its Althoughhe knew thatit could be used as a tool em-
relationshipto philosophicalfoundationsand freedom, ployedmerelyto make one appear unique and original,
myinterpretation emphasizesthe structuralinstability Kantalso maintainedthattheparadoxcould servemore
inherentto Kant'sethicalprojectin orderto defendit in thanone'svanity:
post-structuralist terms.Kantis not"cognitivist, formal-
ist,and universalist,"as Habermas(1993, 321) contends, Preference fortheparadoxicalis logicalobstinacy in
buta radicalthinker who anticipatestheideas ofDerrida whicha mandoesnotwanttobe an imitator ofoth-
(1992, 1996).4Hence,myorientationalso distinguishes ers,but ratherprefers to appearas an unusualhu-
itselffromthosewho exclusively focuson Kant'snotion man being.Insteadof accomplishing his purpose,
of rightin orderto defendor presupposethevalueoflib- sucha man frequently succeedsonlyin beingodd.
eral institutions.5Rawls(1971) claimsthattherootsfor But,becauseeveryone musthaveand maintainhis
A TheoryofJusticecan be found in Kant. But Rawls's ownintelligence, thereproachofbeingparadoxical,
(1980) domesticatedimageof Kanthas littlesimilarity to whenitis notbasedon vanityorthedesiretobe dif-
thecriticalKoenigsbergian thinker.6 Forpostmodernpo- ferent,carriesno bad connotations. Oppositeto the
liticaltheoristsKant is too cold; forliberals,he is per- paradoxicalis thecommonplace, whichsideswith
fectly conservative. But thereis anotherKant. the generalopinion. But withthe commonplace
ifnotless,becauseitlullsthe
thereis as littlesafety,
mind to sleep,whereasthe paradoxawakensthe
Paradox mindto attentionand investigation, whichoften
leadto discoveries. (1978,12)
The word "paradox" appears in Kant's corpus infre-
quently, and thishas lead to itsrelativeneglectas a theme Since,"everyonemusthaveand maintainhis own intelli-
amongcommentators. Perhapsit is evenjustifiableto di- gence,"takingdelightin the paradoxical removesone
rectour attentionto othertopics giventhe following: from"generalopinion."A self-imposed exilecorresponds
to intellectualindependence.With the commonplace,
3Asforthefirst claim,Kantinsistson theimportance offreedom, one is prone to narcolepsyor perhapseven a dogmatic
and in thewordsofArendt, freedomis the"raisond'etreof poli- slumber.But Kantmaintainedthattheparadoxcould be
tics"(1956,151).ForKant,freedom is thegroundofall action;but an antidoteforcognitiveapathysinceittriggers attention
thisgroundis unstableand perhapsevengroundless. As forthe
secondclaim,Allison(1990,230) tendsto overstate theoverallco- and may lead to discoveries.If theparadox suspends rea-
herenceoftheKantianproject.It is notclearto mehowthefactof son, it also simultaneously enlivensit and "awakensthe
reasonis"a genuineadvance." mind."Not a symptomof cognitiveweakness,the para-
4AsfortheKantand Derridarelation, I am thinkingoftheprob- dox stimulatesautonomousthinking and is eventhesign
lemoffreedom inKantand Derrida'scontention thatanypolitical of a-"humorousintelligence" (Anthropology 120).7Even
actworthy of thenamemustenduretheordealof undecidability.
Arguably, is Derrida'swordforfreedom.
undecidability Forboth though Kant is aware that it could be abused, he did not
Kantand Derrida,freedom is beyondtheorderofknowledge and seek to devalue the paradox.
practicefrommechanicalimplemen-
thisrescuesethico-political There are also infrequentreferencesto paradox in
tation. Kant's practical philosophy. In many places, Kant
5Teuberclaims:"Contingenciesplayno roleinhis[Kant's]concep-
tionof themoralperson"(1983,389); Rawlsasserts:"thepriority
ofrightis a centralfeature
ofKant'sethics"(1971,31). 7In a sectionofKant'sAnthropology "On theSpecificDif-
entitled
ferencesBetweentheComparative and theArgumentative Intelli-
6See Rawls(1980). Rawlsgivesprimacyto thesocialeventhough gence,"he linkstheparadoxtolaughter: inpunningis
"Intelligence
Kantinsistson theprimacy ofthepractical.
Rawls'spreoccupation stale;whileneedlesssubtlety
(micrology) ofjudgmentis pedantic.
withinstitutions,
moreover, ignoresKant'svalorizationofcritical Humorousintelligence arisesfromdirectingtheheadtoappreciate
moralcitizenship,thatis,autonomy. The contrastI seekto draw paradoxes,in whichthe(sly)knavepeersfrombehindthenaive
betweenKantand Rawlsis notabsolutesinceKantalso theorizes soundofsimplicity inordertosubjectsomebody(or evenhisown
buttoa lesserextentthanis oftenemphasized.
institutions, opinion)to laughter"(1978,120).

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
770 WILLIAM W. SOKOLOFF

acknowledgesthe enigmaof practicalreason.And even see, thehuman'smoraltransformation materializesas a


thougha particular"circle"threatensKant'sprojectnear mode of self-affection Kantcallsrespect.'0
the conclusionof the Groundwork oftheMetaphysics of One of Kant'searliestsustainedreferences to respect
Morals (1997, 55, 46), the word paradox appears only appearsin a footnotein theGroundwork oftheMetaphys-
once in thistext,and in a contextsomewhatremoved ics ofMorals.It is thefirstthorough,albeitpreliminary,
fromthe feelingof respect.In the CritiqueofPractical articulation ofthisfeelingand itsinterrelationship to the
Reason (1997, 54), Kant refersto the "paradox of networkoffundamental moralconceptsin Kant'spracti-
method,"but he neverexplicitlysaysthatthe feelingof cal philosophy. This footnoteappearsearlyon in thefirst
respectis a paradox. sectiontitled"Transitionfromcommonrationalto phil-
Butin theCritiqueofPureReason(1965, 165-166) in osophic moralcognition."That respectis discussedin a
thesectionentitled"The Applicationof theCategoriesto footnoteis notinsignificant. EventhoughKantdiscusses
ObjectsoftheSensesin General,"Kantrefers to thepara- respectin the CritiqueofPureReason(1965), Critiqueof
dox of self-affection.8 Respectcan justifiablybe desig- PracticalReason(1997), CritiqueofJudgment (1987), Re-
nateda paradoxbecauseitis a feelingthatis notreceived ligionwithintheBoundariesofMereReason(1998), and
fromoutsideinfluences butone thatis self-generated,that Metaphysics ofMorals(1991), his discussionof it in the
And self-affection,
is,self-affected. Kantsuggests, is para- Groundwork demonstrates hisown uncertainty abouthis
doxical.But moreimportantly, thefugitive movementof appeal to a specifically moralfeelingin a textthatsevers
respectitselfis a strongerindicatorof itsparadoxicalsta- feelingfromthefieldof moralpractice.
tus.Respectis neithercompletely sensiblenorcompletely It is clearfromthefirstlineofthisnote,fromitssub-
intelligible
but bothand neitherat thesame time.It is a junctivegrammaticalconstruction to theanticipationof
transient thateludesbothpoles of thebinaryopposition an objection,thatKantbelievedhis appeal to respectwill
reason/feeling thatinaugurates Westernmetaphysics. be criticized.He triesto refutethe chargethathe seeks
refugebehind an obscuremoral feeling.Perhapsmore
importantly, Kantis hereconcernedwiththemerepossi-
Respect bilityof the feelingof respect.For thisreason,he must
distinguishit both fromtheinclinationsas wellas from
Kant'sviewson humanfeelingsare ambiguousand pro- thesphereof cognition.This is notan easytaskand Kant
vocative.Even thoughthe role and significanceof feel- knowsit.Respect,itseems,willoccupya nonspacesome-
ingsincludingthefeelingof thebeautiful,sublime,and wherebetweenthe phenomenaland noumenal realms.
respect,changesthroughout hispoliticaland philosophi- After introducing thefamousproposition"dutyis thene-
cal writings,his interestin human feeling persists cessity ofan actionfromrespectfor law"(Groundwork 13),
throughout hisentireintellectual career.As earlyas 1764, Kantappendsthefollowingnote:
Kantinvestigates offinerfeelingsin Obser-
thepossibility
vationson theFeelingof theBeautifuland theSublime It couldbe objectedthatI onlyseekrefuge, behind
(1960,46-50). Later,he dedicatesan immenseamountof thewordrespect, in an obscurefeeling,insteadof
attentionto therelationship betweenfeelingand moral- distinctly thequestionbymeansofa con-
resolving
in
ityand theways whichtheformerthreatens thepossi- cept of reason.But thoughrespectis a feeling, it is
bilityof thelatter.But Kantdoes not accordall feelings
thesame worth;fortheultimatesuccessof his practical 'IOnadditionto thescholarship therehavebeen
alreadydiscussed,
numerousstudiesofrespect.Fora clearand helpfuldiscussionof
philosophyhingeson his capacityto make qualitative respect,in additionto otherdifficulties in Kant'swritings, see
distinctionsbetweenspecificfeelings.9 And thequalita- Paton(1971); Gregor(1963, 186) discussestherelationship be-
tivefeelingpar excellenceis respect(Achtung). As we shall tweenloveand respect;McCartymakesa helpfuldistinction be-
tweentheintellectualistic viewsofKantianmoral
and affectivistic
8Fenves(1991,222) has an insightful
discussionofKant'selabora- motivation andalso claimsthat"somemystery ... shroudsthepe-
tionoftheparadoxofself-affection. See alsoCaygill:"Thediscus-culiarfeelingofrespect"(1993,434);Broadieand Pybus(1975,63)
sionofaffectionin the'TranscendentalAesthetic'
and'Deduction' distinguish betweentheSocratic(reason)and Sentimental (feel-
... has featureswhichKant himselfdescribesas paradoxical." ing) moralpositionsand claimthatKanthas effected a compro-
Caygillcontinues:
"Kanthimself seemsto havechosennottosolve misebetweenthem;Wolff observes:"theintroduction oftheemo-
theproblem, butrathertoleaveitopenas an ineluctable tionof reverenceis contradictory
butfertile to theentirethrustof Kant's
philosophicaldifficulty
or'aporia"'(1995,58-59). argument" (1973,83); Reath(1989) hasa helpful studyoftherela-
tionshipbetweenrespectand theinclinations; MacBeathexplores
9Kantdistinguishesrespectfromawe,reverence, contempt,admi- therelationship betweenthesublimeand thefeelingof respect
ration,fear,hope,and amazement.Fora discussionof manyof but,forreasonsthatareobvious,I cannotsupporthisclaimthat
thesefeelingssee Sokoloff(2001); see also Kant (Anthropology we must"ignoreall Kant'scontradictions ofwhatI taketo be his
1978,157) forthedifferencebetweenemotionand passion. official
theory oftheproperobjectsofrespect. . ." (1973,302).

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 771

notone received bymeansofinfluence; itis,instead,cal."l Theyestablisha relationof similitudethroughthe


a feelingself-wroughtbymeansofa rationalconcept reflective transfer(metaphe'rein) of thefeaturesof differ-
and therefore specifically differentfromall feelings entobjectsplaced in a spatialrelationship. This moment
ofthefirst kind,whichcanbe reducedto inclination of analogical spatializationin Kant simultaneouslyin-
or fear.WhatI recognizeimmediately as a law forterconnectsand separatesrespectfromits siblingsfear
me I cognizewithrespect,whichsignifiesmerely and inclination.All threeare similarsincetheyare feel-
consciousnessof thesubordination of mywillto a ings;fortheyall appearon theradarof corporeality. But
law withoutthemediationof otherinfluences on theyare not the same. Kant doubts theextentto which
mysense.Immediatedetermination of thewillby fearcould engendermoral conductsince it signalsthe
meansofa lawandconsciousness ofthisis calledre- absenceof freedom;respect,in contrast,namestheleap
spect,so thatthisis regarded as theeffect of thelaw out of thecausal mechanism.And,actiondrivenbyfear
on thesubject,and notas thecauseof thelaw.Re- would "destroythe whole moral worthof actions"be-
spectis properly therepresentation of a worththat cause it receivesitsgroundforconductcompletelyfrom
infringes upon myself-love. Hence thereis some- sensibility (CritiqueofPracticalReason108).
thingthatis regarded as an objectneither ofinclina- Something else is strikingabout this subtextual
tionnorof fear,thoughithassomething analogous qualification.Kant maintainsthat"respectis a feeling."
to both.The objectofrespectis therefore simplythe The inclinations willnotand could notbe eradicatedbe-
law,and indeedthelaw thatwe imposeupon our- cause,as Kantstates,thehuman"can neverbe altogether
selvesand yetas necessary in itself.
As a law we are freefromdesiresand inclinations. . ."(CritiqueofPracti-
subjectto itwithoutconsulting self-love;as imposed cal Reason71). The totalpurification of sensibilityis an
uponus byourselves itis nevertheless a resultofour impossibility.'2 Kantgoes evenfurther whenhe claimsin
will;and in thefirstrespectit has an analogywith ReligionwithintheBoundariesofMereReasonthat"con-
inthesecondwithinclination.
fear, Anyrespectfora sideredin themselves naturalinclinationsare good . . ."
personis properly onlyrespectforthelaw(ofinteg- (1998, 78). But theinclinationsmustnonethelessbe cir-
rityand so forth)ofwhichhe givesus an example. cumscribedso thatthehumancan be morallyelevated.
Because we also regardenlargingour talentsas a And thehumiliationor circumscription ofhumansensi-
duty,we represent a personof talentsalso as, so to bilityis proportionate to his moralelevation(Critiqueof
speak,an exampleofthelaw(to becomelikehimin PracticalReason67).
thisbypractice),and thisis whatconstitutes ourre- If respectreceivesa preliminary and subtextualelu-
spect.Allso-calledmoralinterest consistssimplyin cidation, this is not surprisingsince the Groundwork
respectforthelaw.(Groundwork 14) only prepares the way for another textthat takes up
similarthemes.But thefeelingof respectis not dropped
Kant's discussion in
of respect thislongfootnote strik- as an elusive object of inquiry; Kant develops it in
is
ing.Respect(if thereis such a thing)is a self-produced greaterdetailthreeyearslaterin the CritiqueofPractical
feelingas opposed to one receivedfromexternalstimuli, Reasonwhereit takescenterstage as the incentivefor
and thatis whatmakesitdifferent fromall otherfeelings. moral conduct.'3And Kant's discussionof it does not
The unmediatedrecognitionof the validityof moral occurbeneaththetextbut in one of thelongestsections
claimsimposedupon humansgeneratesrespect.It is the in themiddleof thisbook. Froma painstakingfootnote
"effectofthelawon thesubject"thatresultswhenwe im- in the Groundwork, respectreemergesto occupya cen-
pose a law withno mediatinginfluencesupon ourselves. tralplace in Chapter3 of theanalyticof practicalreason
The immediacyof thislaw meansrespectis feltas imme-
diacy itself,as pure force:"lawgivingreason . . . forces
11Derridamaintainsthat"Analogyis metaphorpar excellence"
fromme immediaterespect"(Groundwork 16). And this (1982,242).
peculiar mode of immediacyis preciselywhat distin-
guishesrespectfromotherfeelings. In thewordsof Kant, '2ThepurityConnolly(1999) seesinKantianmorality contradicts
Kant'sownwordson thesensiblebasisof it.Kantwantsto purify
respectis more"powerfulthanall . . . feelingstogether" morality froma certainmodeofsensiblecontamination butone
(Metaphysics ofMorals209). feelingremains(respect),
and itis theunstablenexusbetweenthe
Respectis neitherfearnor inclinationbut is "analo- humanand thelaw.
gous" to both. It is not surprisingthatKant invokesan 13Kantdistinguishes betweenincentive(Triebfeder)and contin-
analogicalmode of presentation hereas an indirectway gent grounds (Bewegungsgrund)in theCritique
ofPractical
Reason
(1997),a distinction
thatwasnotmadein theGroundwork (1997).
to elucidaterespect.Analogicalrelationships are not re- Gregor, of Kant(1997,32), makesthispointin a foot-
translator
lationsof identityand are not rationalbut metaphori- notetohereditedvolumeoftheCritiqueofPracticalReason.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
772 WILLIAM W. SOKOLOFF

in the sectionof the CritiqueofPracticalReasontitled accountofitsorigin,cannotbe calledpathologically


"On theincentivesof purepracticalreason."Respect,we effected butmustbe calledpractically effected,and is
learn,is thesole motiveto moralconduct. effected as follows:therepresentation of themoral
Whereasin the Groundwork (1997, 48) Kantclaims law deprivesself-love of itsinfluence
and self-con-
thatbasingmoralityon incentives destroysitssublimity, ceitofitsillusion,and thereby thehindrance to pure
in the CritiqueofPracticalReasonthisis no longerthe practical reasonis lessenedandtherepresentation of
case.'4 A specificincentiveis now distinguishedfrom thesuperiority ofitsobjectivelawto theimpulsesof
contingent ones,and theformerwillundergirdthesub- sensibility,andwithittherelative weightiness ofthe
limityof moralpractice.Anydoubt Kanthad about the law . . . is producedin the judgmentof reason
possibilityof respectaccomplishingthisin the Ground- through theremovalofthecounterweight .... (Cri-
workis gone:"respectforthemorallaw is ... thesole and tiqueofPractical Reason65)
also theundoubtedmoralincentive"(CritiqueofPracti-
cal Reason67). Buthow is respectan incentive? Respectis an effecton feelingbut it is not pleasure;nor
Kant definesan incentiveas "the subjectivedeter- can itbe comparedto anypathologicalfeelingbecause it
mininggroundof thewillof a beingwhose reasondoes is not,Kant claims,"pathologically effected." And yet,it
not by itsnaturenecessarilyconformwiththeobjective presupposesthesensibility and finitudethatis itscondi-
law. . ." (CritiqueofPracticalReason62). But at theout- tion of possibility:"Sensible feeling. . . is indeed the
setoftheCritiqueofPracticalReasondedicatedto clarify- conditionof thatfeelingwe call respect... ."Yet,respect
ingthe moralincentive(Triebfeder), Kantacknowledges is nonethelessproducedsolelybyreason,byan "intellec-
thedifficulty of evenconceivingof one: "How a law can tual ground" (Critique of Practical Reason 64). This
be of itselfand immediately a determining groundofthe opens the arduous path to genuinemoral practicethat
willis forhumanreasonan insolubleproblem.. ." (Cri- requiresgettingrid of sensibility, "the counterweight."
tiqueofPracticalReason62, italicsadded). Kant avoids This is not an excavationthatthe human subjectwel-
theproblemand redefines histask.The taskbecomesone comes: "So littleis respecta feelingof pleasurethatwe
ofshowing"notthegroundfromwhichthemorallaw in give way to it only reluctantly.... We tryto discover
itselfsuppliesan incentivebut ratherwhatit effects (or, somethingthatcould lightenthe burdenof it forus . .
to putitbetter, musteffect)in themindinsofaras itis an ."(CritiqueofPracticalReason66). Again:"Respectis a
incentive" (CritiqueofPracticalReason62-63). The effect tributethatwe cannot refuseto pay merit,whetherwe
willbe elucidated,not thegrounditselffromwhichthe want to or not; we may indeed withholdit outwardly
morallaw servesas a sourceof motivation. but we stillcannothelp feelingit inwardly"(Critiqueof
As we have learned,Kant thinksthatthe human is PracticalReason66). Respectexceedsthe intentionsof
nevertotallyfreefrominclinations and desires.And even the subject.But it also does more.It exposes theworld
thoughhumanscan neverstepoutsideof sensibility, the of appearancesto inherentmeaninglessness sincesome-
challengeis whethersomethingotherthansensibility can thingotherthanthephenomenalworld,somethinges-
motivateactionin orderto giveitjustifiable moralworth: sentiallynegative,provides the ground for genuine
moralconduct.
sensiblefeeling. . . is indeedtheconditionof that A peculiarnegativity thatcan be cognized a priori
feelingwe call respect, butthecausedeterminingit willprovidedetermination fortheliberatedwill.Butthis
liesin purepracticalreason;and so thisfeeling,on liberationis not entirelypleasant.And this particular
mode of determinativediscomfortcorrespondsto the
"4Coles's(1997,24-74) underexamines theinterconnectionbe- firstmomentof respect:
tweensublimity and moralcategoriesin Kant'sphilosophy.
This
connection wouldprobablyfrustrate
thelinehe seeksto drawbe- Whatis essentialin everydetermination of thewill
tweenthefirst and thethird.Colesprivileges
twocritiques theCri-
tiqueofJudgmentwhileadoptinga somewhat dismissive
stanceto- by themoral law is that,as freewill . . . it is deter-
ward the Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Practical minedsolelybythelaw.So far,then,theeffect ofthe
Reason.Colesfindstheconsequences ofKant'snarrative
ofsubjec- morallawas incentive is onlynegative, and as such
tivesovereigntyin theCritiqueofPureReasonproblematic. Kant's
views on lyingand revolution,accordingto Coles, are short-
thisincentivecan be cognizeda priori.For,all incli-
As thisarticleseeksto demonstrate,
sighted. theradicalresources nationand everysensibleimpulseis basedon feel-
Coles unearthsin theCritiqueofJudgment thatcan productively ing,and thenegative effect on feeling. . . is itselfa
disfigure
dominantinterpretations ofKantin thenameofan ethic Hencewecanseea priorithatthemorallaw,
feeling.
ofreceptivegenerositycan also be foundin Kant'stheoretical
and
practicalphilosophyas well,althoughthespecificethicalconse- as the determining groundof the will, must by
quenceswouldnot,ofcourse,necessarily be thesame. thwartingall ourinclinations producea feeling that

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 773

can be calledpain .... (Critique ofPracticalReason gainsreluctantreverence


(thoughnotalwaysobedi-
63,italicsadded) ence),a lawbeforewhichall inclinations
aredumb,
eventhoughtheysecretly workagainstit;whatori-
"The negativeeffecton feelingis itselfa feeling." On the ginis thereworthyofyou,andwhereis to be found
one hand, feelingis crossed out, but on the other,a therootofyournobledescentwhichproudlyrejects
feelinglessfeelingis itselffeltas a feeling.Respectseems allkinshipwiththeinclinations,
descentfromwhich
to liveofftheveryfeelings thatseekto denyrespect'sown conditionof thatworthwhich
is theindispensable
possibility.Feeling the absence of feeling-that is, humanbeingsalonecan givethemselves? (1997,73)
"pain"-corresponds to thenegationof theinclinations
of the self;thissignalsthebeginningof one's infinitely The interconnection betweenour moraldutyand thelaw
testedmembershipin an intelligible world.The devasta- silencesthe inclinations.The criticalphilosophereven
tion of self-loveis a prerequisite;self-conceitmustalso raisesthepossibility ofduty'simmaculateconception;no
be struckdownand thisinvolveshumiliation(Critiqueof originis worthyofher.This mystery does notjeopardize
PracticalReason64). Kantacknowledgesthat"respect... thehuman'smoralworthbut is thefundamental condi-
showsus our unworthiness with... severity" (Critiqueof tionof it.This worthis notgrantedbya politicianbut is
PracticalReason67). self-given,thatis, taken.In orderto be a moral citizen,
The second momentof respectis also a negative one mustplace a law above oneselfwhich in turn"el-
feelingbut one closerto thefeelingof pleasure.And it is evatesa humanbeingabovehimself"and theendlessness
here that a strikingresemblancebetweenthe compli- of thisself-overcoming constitutes
our properself(Cri-
cated networkof sensationsthatconstituterespectand tique ofPracticalReason 74). Finally,we discover"the
Kant'sdiscussionof thesublimein theCritiqueofJudge- sublimityof our own supersensibleexistence. . ." (Cri-
mentappears. The movementof attractionand repul- tiqueofPracticalReason75). But whydoes Kant evade
sion in boththefeelingof thesublimeand thefeelingof the questionof the originof duty?If thereis an origin
respectresultsin a negativepleasure.'5But in thecase of worthyof duty,whatwould itbe?
respect,the law is not onlya sourceof pain but also the
groundof a "positivefeeling"(CritiqueofPracticalRea-
son 63). Althoughrespectis not pleasure, one is "el-
evated,"and thiscorrespondsto theawarenessof need- Ground
ing nothing,thesign of whichis an "innertranquility"
(CritiqueofPracticalReason67, 75). This is notso much The wordground(Grund)has particularsignificance for
a pathologicalrewardas it is a peculiar comfortKant Kantsince respectis unfathomable(unergruendlich) for
names "consolation" that is the resultof viewingthe speculativereason and because he soughtto providea
majestyof the moral law in its absolute holiness (Cri- criticalgroundforpractice.'6The conceptof theground
tiqueofPracticalReason75). is centralin thefirstand one of themostsignificant texts
As we haveseen,a discussionof therelationship be- in the developmentof his criticalpracticalphilosophy:
tween duty and respect in the Groundworkinitiates Groundwork oftheMetaphysics ofMorals.'7 This textis
Kant'sinvestigation of thelatter.He provisionallycon- ambitiousbecause it seeks out and establishesthe su-
cludeshis discussionof respectby returning to thecon- premeprincipleof morality, thecategoricalimperative.
cept of dutyin the Triebfeder sectionof the Critiqueof This is necessaryand justifiablesince all previoustexts
PracticalReason: on moralphilosophyfailedto locatethisprinciple.Butto
getthereone musttraverse "thehighestlimitofall moral
Duty! Sublimeand mightyname that embraces inquiry"(Groundwork 65).
nothingcharming butrequiressub-
or insinuating Despiteitsmonumentalgoal,theGroundwork has an
mission,and yetdoes notseekto movethewillby astonishingconclusion. For the ultimatefoundation
threatening anythingthatwould arouse natural formoralityremainsa question and is fundamentally
aversionorterror in themindbutonlyholdsforth a
law thatof itselffindsentryintothemindand yet
16Gregor,translator
ofKant(1997,68), renders
"unergruendlich"
as "impenetrable"
whicherasestheforceof theliteralconnection
"In reference to thefeelingof thesublime,Kantmaintains: "the to theground.Unfathomableisbetter.
mindis notjustattracted bytheobjectbutis alternatively
always
repelledas well,thelikingforthesublimecontainsnotso mucha 17Foran antifoundationalist accountoftheKantiancriticalproject
positivepleasureas ratheradmiration and respect,
and so should see O'Neill(1989). O'Neill'sdiscussionofthefirst
critiqueas a re-
be calleda negativepleasure"(CritiqueofJudgment
98). flexiveand politicaltaskis provocative.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
774 WILLIAM W. SOKOLOFF

inaccessibleto cognition.'8A massivegap separatesthe less.Thatis also whygovernments havegladlyper-


bodyof thetextfromthecharacterof theinquiryprom- mittedreligionto be amplyfurnished withsuchac-
isedbythetitle.AlthoughthewordGroundwork suggests cessories:theyweretrying to relieveeverysubjectof
thatthistextwill providea groundlaying, groundwork, thetrouble, yetalsooftheability,
toexpandhissoul's
grounding,or foundationformorals,sucha foundation is forcesbeyondthebarriers thatone canchoosetoset
preciselywhatthetextfailsto supply.In fact,the"Con- forhimso as to reducehimto merepassivity and so
cludingRemark"containsthefollowing paradox: makehimmorepliable. . . thispure,elevating, and
merelynegativeexhibition of morality involvesno
Andthuswe do notindeedcomprehend thepracti- dangeroffanaticism, whichisthedelusion[ Wahn]of
cal unconditioned necessityofthemoralimperative, wanting toSEE somethingbeyond all boundsofsensi-
butwe nevertheless comprehend itsincomprehensi- bility... The exhibition
avoidsfanaticism precisely
bility,
and thisis all thatcan fairlybe requiredof a becauseitis merely negative.Fortheideaoffreedom
philosophy thatstrivesin itsprinciples to reachthe isinscrutableandthereby precludes all positiveexhi-
veryboundaryofhumanreason.(Groundwork 66) bitionwhatever....(1987,135)

Aftera transitionfrom"OrdinaryRationalKnowledgeof The negativity of moralityis not "cold and lifeless"but


Moralityto the Philosophical"and one from"Popular producesimaginative momentumand is simultaneously
Moral Philosophyto a Metaphysicsof Morals,"the text a checkon fanaticism; theinverseinstantaneously dead-
culminatesin a paradoxthatsignalsthefundamental in- ens the soul and is a tool of governments thatengineer
of thefoundationforpractice.Eventhough
accessibility moralpassivity. Governments fearthatmoralclaimswill
groundingonlynames a preliminaryproject,one that haveno forceunlesstheyare supplementedwith"child-
will be workedout threeyearslater in the Critiqueof ishdevices."Kantdoes nothavethisfear.Forhim,moral
PracticalReason,Kant does not even providea prelimi- practicegroundedon freedomultimately lacksa ground;
narygrounding.Instead,we getsomethinglikean abso- freedomis essentially negative.And itis indeedthisnega-
lute ungroundingsignaledin the invitationto embrace tivitythatengendersthemoralcitizen'sempowerment.
negativityor"comprehendincomprehensibility:" Butthenegativecharacterofmoraldemandsand the
The negativityof Kantianmoralityhas provedto be human'sinabilityto conceivethepossibility of an action
a significant
pointof contentionamongreadersof Kant done out of dutydoes not mean thatmoralityis a mere
leadingmanyto dismisshisethicalprinciples.Butduring "phantom"or thatthelaw failsto effectus (Groundwork
Kant'sdiscussionof thesublimity of theJewishlaw pro- 51). We are summonedbythelaw thatwe cannotcom-
hibitingimagesof thedivinein theCritiqueofJudgment, pletelygrasp even thoughwe can nonethelesshear its
Kantreversestherelationbetweensensibility and moral- command.The "voice of reason"is one thatis "so dis-
ityand insiststhatit is indeedthenegativity
of morality tinct,so irrepressible,
and so audible"(CritiqueofPracti-
thatinvigorates themoralimagination-givesit force- cal Reason 32). It "makes even the boldest evildoer
and checksthepracticesofgovernments who seekpliable tremble;"moreterrifyingly, "eventhedead arenotalways
subjects: safefromthiscriticalexamination"(CritiqueofPractical
Reason 68, 66). We are in doubt, though,whetherthe
It is indeeda mistaketo worrythatdeprivingthis voice of reason "comes fromman, fromthe perfected
presentation ofwhatever couldcommenditto the powerof his own reason,or whetherit comes froman
senseswillresultin itscarrying
withitno morethan other,whoseessenceis unknownto us .. ." ("On a Newly
a coldandlifelessapprovalwithoutanymovingforce ArisenSuperiorTone in Philosophy"71, italicsadded).
or emotion.It is exactlytheotherwayround.For The groundformoralitycannotbe rationally elucidated
oncethesensesno longersee anything beforethem, or graspedbecause it is freedom;thatalone transfers the
whileyettheunmistakable andindelibleideaofmo- humanintoa higherorder.
rality onewouldsoonerneedtotemperthe
remains,
momentum of an unboundedimagination so as to
keepitfromrisingtothelevelofenthusiasm, thanto
seekto supporttheseideaswithimagesandchildish Freedom
devicesforfearthattheywouldotherwise be power-
WhenKantdesignatesGod, freedom, and immortalityin
'Groundlaying
is theliteraltranslation
of theGermanword the CritiqueofPureReasonas the"unavoidableproblems
"Grundlegung." setby pure reason"(1965, 46), thisdoes not name three

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 775

separateundertakings but onlyone. It is theannounce- is nota stablefoundationbutdesignatesthecompletere-


mentof theproblemof freedomas themostimportant movalof all determinate grounds.Freedomwillneverbe
metaphysical investigation.Forboth theidea of an eter- a particularplaceor standpoint.Kant'sfamous"footpath
nal divinityand immortalityinvolvethe possibilityof offreedom," thepath"on whichitis possibleto makeuse
somethingthatis entirely unconditioned, thatis,free.In of our reasonin our conduct. . ." turnsout to be not so
thecase of God, independencefroman originor ground much a trailof securitybut somethingelse,something
otherthanone thatis self-given, or,in thecase of immor- thatis at best undecidable(Groundwork 60). The unde-
somethingoutsideoftemporaldetermination
tality, alto- cidablecharacterof freedomis,in thewordsof Kant,"a
gether.And thepossibilityofboththeformerand thelat- terriblething,"not onlybecause it is the condition of
terpointto theproblemof freedom. bothgood and evil,but because it annihilatesthestabil-
Perhapsmore so thanany otherphilosopher,Kant ityofthefundamental groundforpractice(KantLectures
dedicateshimselfto freedomwithunprecedentedrigor. on Ethics17). The result:the human comes faceto face
And even thoughit occupies a centralplace in Kant's withtheradicalindeterminacy of all action.Kant:"The
writings,freedomneverceases to be an unproblematic law cannotspecifypreciselyin whatwayone is to act ...
concept.Consider,forexample,how Kantspeaksof free- (Metaphysics ofMorals194).19
dom in threedifferent texts.In theGroundwork, freedom But,and thisis Kant'sgenius,theinstability of free-
is "presupposed"(1997, 53). In the CritiqueofPractical dom does notauthorizeethicallicense.The fundamental
Reason,freedomis a "factof reason"(1997, 28). In An- undecidability of freedompromisesto generatemodesof
thropology froma PragmaticPointofView,freedomap- actionthatdo not negatethefreedomthatinitiallyper-
pearsas somethingprimordial:"The childwho has just mitstheseactsto be possibleat all.Thereis thusa certain
come fromitsmother'swomb,unlikeall otheranimals, lawfulness thatcorrespondsto theinstability offreedom:
seemsto entertheworldwitha loud shriekjust because "A freewilland a will undermorallaws are one and the
it considersthe inabilityto make use of its limbs a re- same"(Groundwork 53).20Butthereciprocalrelationship
straint;consequently,itannouncesthisclaimto freedom betweenlawfulness and freedomdoes noteffacethefun-
(whichno otheranimalknows)"(l978, 176). damentalriddleof freedom.Atthebottomof it all,free-
But overand above thesestrainedformulations and dom is thelaw,and thelaw can neverbe anythingother
anthropological speculationabouttheprimalcry,thereis thanfreedom.
somethingparadoxicalabout Kant'smeditationon free- Kantmaintainsin theGroundwork thatcontemplat-
dom. In thethoughtof freedom,reasonmustdo whatit ingthepossibility of thelawvas an imperative of freedom
is ultimatelyunable to do, thatis, thinkthe uncondi- leads one to the"extremeboundaryof all practicalphi-
tioned.A gap separatestheconditioningactivityof rea- losophy"(1997, 59). Conductingoneselfin accordance
son and the unconditionedessenceof freedom;forthe withitgoes further. For Kantbelievedthatitwould lead
thoughtof the unconditionedis incompatiblewiththe to nothingless thana totalcosmicinversionof thefun-
groundgivingcharacterof reason. It seems thatevery damentallawsoftheuniverse;theforceofthelawsof na-
thoughtof freedomis destinedto missits.target. In order turein determining conductare replacedwiththeforce
to thinkfreedom,then,we have to thinkthe uncondi- of freedom.We must"conductourselvesin accordance
tioned.Thoughtmustthinktheunthinkable. An unsatis- withmaximsof freedomas iftheywerelaws of nature"
fyingpredicamentindeed:"Byconstantinquiryafterthe
condition,the satisfactionof reasonis onlyfurther and '9Thisdoes notthreaten Kantianmorality withpointlessness.It
furtherpostponed" (Groundwork66). The deferralof preserves thesublimityoffreedom andprevents thedenigrationof
cognitivegratificationmeans thatfreedomalwaysex- thelaw to a tool.Fora critiqueof thepotentialpointlessness of
Kantianmorality, see Schneewind (1992).Fora valorization ofthe
ceeds our faculties:"We shall neverbe able to compre- nontechnical foundation forethics,politics,and culturalidentity
hendhow freedomis possible"(Groundwork 60). Butwe see Derrida:"whena responsibility is exercisedin theorderofthe
shouldbe satisfied"ifonlywe can be sufficiently assured possible,itsimplyfollowsa direction and elaboratesa program. It
makesofactiontheappliedconsequence, thesimpleapplication of
thatthereis no proofof itsimpossibility. . ." (Critiqueof a knowledge or know-how. It makesofethicsand politicsa tech-
PracticalReason79). This is a surprisingclaim ifwe ac- nology.No longeroftheorderofpractical reasonordecision,itbe-
ceptAllison'sobservation( 1990,1) thatfreedominhabits ginstobe irresponsible ... Europeanculturalidentity ... mustbe-
longto thisexperience and experiment of theimpossible" (1992,
themostimportantplace in Kant'spracticalphilosophy.
45, italicsadded).AlthoughDerridais criticalof Kant,thereis a
The theoretical
impossibility of completely conceiv- striking betweenKant'sconceptionofpracticalreason
similarity
ing freedomcorrespondsto thepracticaldifficulty of it and theDerrideandecision.
as well. On the one hand, freedomis the condition of (1989) fora discussionoftheimpactofJean-Jacques
Velkley
211See
possibilityforethicalpractice,but,on theother,freedom oflawon Kant.
Rousseau'sconception

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
WILLIAM W. SOKOLOFF

(Groundwork 66). Freedom,a new groundin theouter tionof thehumanout of thecausal mechanismand into
reachesof cognition,changesplace withthelawsof na- a "kingdomof ends."Althoughhe is morallyelevated,he
tureand becomestheconditionof possibilityforan el- is also embodied.22He is freebut he cannotcompletely
evatedand redeemedplanet.The initialsignof thispos- stepoutsideof sensibility.Ascendingas he fallsand de-
sibilityis thefeelingof one's own radicalindependence scendingas he rises,theKantianmoralagentis occupied
fromnature. by divergentforcesthatneverentirelysupplya stand-
But thepossibility of evenpartiallyrisingabove na- point thatexceedsthe poles of thismotileopposition.
turedepends on human receptivity. One mustreceive But theregimeof sensibility does not stop him fromat-
whatis absolutelyotherand intrinsically opposed to the tempting to elevatehimselfabove thetyrannicalvoiceof
innermostcompositionof thehuman.This is especially pathologybecause the Kantian moral agentalso hears
difficult to bearsincethemorallaw recognizesno limits. the"voiceof reason"(CritiqueofPracticalReason32).
The logical resultof the limitlessnessof moral com-
mandsis permanentmoralfailure;thesecommandscan
neverbe fulfilled.2' But theunfulfillability
and impossi-
bilityof moralcommandsdoes not mean thattheyare EthicalParadox
opaque, even thoughtheymayproduce thaumain the
residentof Koenigsberghimself:"The simplicityof this Readersof Kantfroma wide varietyof priesthoodshave
law ... mustseemastonishing..." (Metaphysics ofMorals had a difficult timecomingto termswiththe feelingof
51). This is thelaw: "So act thatthe maximof yourwill respect.It is, in the wordsof Kofman,an "economyof
could alwayshold at thesametimeas a principlein a giv- panic;"forLyotardit is "a blankfeeling;"forAdorno,re-
ingof universallaw" (CritiqueofPracticalReason28). In spect is even"repressive"(Kofman 1997; Lyotard1994,
thecategoricalimperative, thehumanis commandedto 118; Adorno 1973, 232). But forthe purposes of this
do the impossible,and thisis theessence,not of Kant's study,I examineConnolly's(1999, 163-177) recentcri-
moralreform, butofhismoralrevolution. Kant'sfamous tiqueofKant.In hisimportantWhyI am Nota Secularist,
criticismof revolutionin the Metaphysicsof Morals he theorizesthe"visceralregister," a name designating
(1991, 129-133) shouldbe viewedstrictly withinthedo- gut feelingsand embodied trauma,and in the Chapter
mainof legality. Kantneverruledout thepossibility of a entitled"A Critiqueof Pure Politics,"he launchesa cri-
moralrevolution:"That a humanbeingshould become tique of Kantian purity.And it is here that Connolly
not merelylegallygood,but morallygood ... cannotbe smellsan unconsciousdogmatismand imperialismin
effectedthroughgradual reform but mustratherbe ef- Kant;he is also nervousabouttheKantiandevaluationof
fectedthrougha revolution in thedispositionof thehu- sensibility;he wonders,finally,whetherKant places his
man being"(ReligionwithintheBoundariesofMereRea- commandmorality outsidea zone oflegitimate contesta-
son67-68). tion (see also Connolly2000). I understandand share
The nameforthemoralrevolutionin thedisposition Connolly'shesitationsbut,as I haveshown,thereis an-
of thehumanis Achtung. Respectnamestheannihilation otherwayto approachKant.
of politicalprojectsgroundedon pathologicalsubjectiv- Connollysees a dangerousdriveto purityin Kant
ity.It also signalstheimpossibility of humanmoralper- but,as I havedemonstrated, thereis also structural
con-
fectionbut withoutabandoningthe aspirationforit.A taminationat work. He sees a command moralityin
distinctlyhuman feelingof moral failure,respectre- Kant;so do I, but,it is a paradoxicalone. In contrastto
mindsus thatthereis no securepositionon whichmoral Connolly,myreadingseeksto unhingetheconservative
conductcan be based.Butas a signofthehuman'smoral appropriationof Kant at its root in orderto develop a
finitude,respectnonethelessnames the possibleeleva- Kantianethicof paradox.Such an ethicdoes not involve

2'Foran intriguingdiscussionof thenonfulfillable


characterof 22Forthe themeof embodimentin Kant's writingssee Shell
themorallaw see Hamacher(1996,81-108). Duringhis discus- (1996). In Shell(1980) sheobserves: "Bythusheightening theim-
betweenthemorallaw and happiness,
sion of therelationship portanceof intellectual and economicrights,
Kantlessensthesig-
Coles claimsthatthe"morallaw ... wouldinvolvereasonin the nificanceof thedistinction he drawsbetweenactiveand passive
contradictionofcommanding thatitdetermine
and willitselfac- citizenship.An empiricallyrepublican governmentis lessurgently
cordingto something whichis fundamentally
impossible" (1997, needfulthantheformalrightto developfullyone'sownpowers"
45). Byappealingto theprincipleof noncontradiction,
it is not (173). I am made uneasybythedistinction Shelldrawsbetween
Kantbut Coles who privilegesthesovereigntyof reason.I find activeand passivecitizenship. GivenKant'sown insistence on the
Hamacher'sdiscussion(1996) ofstructural
impossibilityin Kant importance of autonomyand,moregenerally, Kant'segalitarian
morepersuasive. hopefulness, passivecitizenshipis oxymoronic.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 777

theeither/or choiceofembracinglawor affirming essen- creatingand enactingmodes of thinkingand practices


tial contingency(an oppositionthatI believecontem- thatvalue bothat thesametime.In Derrida'swords:"The
poraryethico-political needs to questionto a
reflection difficultyis to gesturein oppositedirectionsat thesame
greaterextentthan it has) but doing bothat the same time"(1984, 120). This"doubleduty"simultaneously en-
time.23 And thisis precisely whatcan deepenand expand ables ethicalconductbut disablesit too. It makesethics
contemporary conceptualizations of thefoundationsfor difficult.Butwithoutethicaldifficulty thereis no reason
ethico-political practice.24AlthoughI can onlysketchthe to workat beingethical.
outlines of this new ethic, it is my alternativeto But let us returnto Kant.Have I forcedKantianre-
Connolly'sconceptionof "agonisticrespect"thathe de- spect into a paradoxicalstructurethatunderminesthe
velopsin oppositionto Kant. logical consistencyof Kant'spracticalphilosophy?The
A Kantianethicof paradoxaffirms thevalue of the answeris no. All commentatorson Kant acknowledge
moralforcecontainedin categoricallawfulpronounce- respect'smysterious status.And I refuseto ignoreor ho-
mentsand is also attentiveto the inescapableaporetic mogenizethetextualtensionsthatconstitute respect.In-
dimensions,theconditionsof possibility thatare simul- deed,I affirm itsparadoxicalmovement.Butwhatis the
taneouslyconditions of impossibility,of these com- value oftheparadoxof respectand whataretheimplica-
mands.25Secondly,a Kantianethicof paradoxaspiresto tionsof thisparadoxon Kant'spracticalphilosophyas a
value universality and particularity at the same time.It whole?
thus seeks a middle positionbetweenadvocatesof ab- First,theparadoxof respectmayhelp us appreciate
stractuniversalism, on the one hand,and particularity, the essentiallyambiguous status of fundamentalele-
on theother.At itsworst,an overemphasis on universal- mentsof Kant'spracticalphilosophyin orderto attune
ityresultsin imperialism, homogenization, and universal us to theactualcomplexity of moralproblemsin thereal
domination;affirming the particular,takento the ex- world.The paradox,theone thatreasonand thewill to
treme,producesnationalism,relativism, and subjectiv- meaningseek to annul,can open a space forreflection.
ism.So we needto knowthedangersofbothuniversality Second, generatinga paradox in a relativelynew place
and particularity, but also thevalueofboth. may providean impetusto read othercrisispoints in
Derrida'srecentworkon culturalidentity, cosmo- Kant'swritings. WhileI thinkthathe is too dismissiveof
politanism,and hospitalityhas gone furtherthan any Kant'spracticalphilosophy, I applaud Coles's (1997) af-
othercontemporary thinkerin thisregard.He articulates firmative rereadingof thesublime,genius,and aesthetic
the necessity,value, and indispensabilityof a "double ideas in the CritiqueofJudgment thathe developsto ar-
contradictory imperative"or "double duty"(1992, 77- ticulatean ethicof receptive generosity.
78).26 Universality is limitedbyvaluingparticularity,and Third,theparadoxofrespectcan createa space from
particularity is stretched outsideof itsidiombytheuni- whichone can contestethicalprogramsthatdestroyspace
versal.The one is alwaysinscribedintotheother.So it is forthesingularity of theother,especiallywhentheother
not a choice betweenuniversalityor particularitybut is a hybridor paradox.Kant'sown valuationof thepara-
dox (1978, 12) is consistent withthefoundinggestureof
thecriticalproject:restraining cognitivehubris. Affirming
23Habermas theclearestexampleofan advocateofra-
is probably paradoxsuspendsthewillto cognitivedomination.But
tionalityand universality,buta critiqueofhisworkis beyondthe
scopeofthecurrent article. sometimeslettinga paradoxpersistsignalsa pathological
yearningto appearunique,or as Kantputitearlier, "logi-
24Although I cannotdevelopthisthemehere,Connollyhasprema-
turely accepteda domesticated rendering ofKant. cal obstinacy" (1978, 12). Butnot always. It may be a gen-
erousresponseto constitutive ethicalambiguity. Finally,
25 I borrowthisparadoxical formulationfromtheworkofDerrida.
For his discussionof conditionsof possibility thatare simulta- eventhoughtheparadoxmaysuspendthesovereignty of
neouslyconditions ofimpossibilitysee hisessayin Deconstruction reasonand pushitto itslimit,itis valuablebecauseitcan
and Pragmatism entitled"Remarkson Deconstruction and Prag- irritatereasonout of self-assurance or thoughtlessness,
matism"(1996,82).
and perhapsthe paradox can even"awakenthe mind"
26Derridaarticulates thepracticalformsthatthis"doubleduty" (KantAnthropology 12). As Nancyputsit:"Thinkingis al-
takesin TheOtherHeading"The samedutyalso dictateswelcom-
ingforeigners inordernotonlyto integrate thembutto recognize
waysthinkingon thelimit.The limitof comprehending
and accepttheiralterity:twoconceptsofhospitality thattodaydi- definesthinking. Thus thinkingis alwaysthinking about
videourEuropeanand nationalconsciousness." He goeson toadd: theincomprehensible..." (1993,54).
"Thesamedutydictatesrespecting idioms,minorities,
differences,
offormallaw,thedesirefor
butalso theuniversality
singularities,
translation,
agreement thelawofthemajority,
and univocity, op- ManuscriptsubmittedAugust16,2000.
positionto racism,nationalism,
andxenophobia" (1992,77,78). Final manuscript
received
April2, 2001.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
WILLIAM W. SOKOLOFF

References Kant,Immanuel.1965.CritiqueofPureReason.Trans.Norman
KempSmith.NewYork:St Martin'sPress.
Adorno,Theodor.1973.NegativeDialectics.Trans.E. B. Ashton. Kant,Immanuel.1978.Anthropologyfrom a PragmaticPointof
NewYork:ContinuumPress. View.Trans.VictorLyleDowdell.Carbondale:SouthernIl-
linoisUniversity Press.
Allison,HenryE. 1990. Kant'sTheoryofFreedom.Cambridge:
Press. Kant,Immanuel.1987. CritiqueofJudgment. Trans.WernerS.
CambridgeUniversity
Pluhar.Indianapolis:HackettPublishingCompany.
Arendt,Hannah. 1977. "What is Freedom?"In BetweenPast
Kant, Immanuel. 1991. MetaphysicsofMorals. Trans. Mary
and Future:EightExercisesin PoliticalThought.New York:
Gregor.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press.
Penguin.
Kant,Immanuel.1993."On a NewlyArisenSuperiorTone in
Benjamin,Walter.1989."On the Programof theComingPhi-
Philosophy." Trans.PeterFenves.In RaisingtheToneofPhi-
losophy."Trans.Mark Ritter.In Benjamin:Philosophy, His-
losophy:Late EssaybyImmanuelKant,Transformative Cri-
tory,Aesthetics,ed. GarySmith.Chicago:University of Chi-
tiquebyJacquesDerrida,ed. PeterFenves.Baltimore:The
cago Press.
JohnsHopkinsUniversity Press.
Broadie, Alexander,and Pybus,Elizabeth M. 1975. "Kant's
Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Critiqueof PracticalReason. Trans.
Conceptof'Respect."'Kant-Studien 66:58-64.
MaryGregor.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press.
Caygill, Howard. 1995. A Kant Dictionary. Oxford: Basil Kant,Immanuel.1997. Groundwork oftheMetaphysics ofMor-
Blackwell.
als. Trans.MaryGregor.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity
Coles, Romand. 1997. Rethinking Generosity:CriticalTheory Press.
and thePoliticsofCaritas.Ithaca:CornellUniversity Press. Kant,Immanuel.1998. ReligionwithintheBoundariesofMere
Connolly,WilliamE. 1995.EthosofPluralization. Minneapolis: Reason.Trans.AllenWood. Cambridge:CambridgeUniver-
University of MinnesotaPress. sityPress.
Connolly,WilliamE. 1999. WhyI Am Not a Secularist. Minne- Kofman,Sarah. 1997."The Economyof Respect:Kantand Re-
apolis: University of MinnesotaPress. spectforWomen."Trans.Nicola Fisher.In Feminist Interpre-
Connolly,WilliamE. 2000. "Speed, ConcentricCultures,and tationsofImmanuelKant,ed. RobinMay Schott.University
Cosmopolitanism." PoliticalTheory28:596-618 Park:Pennsylvania StateUniversity Press.
Derrida,Jacques.1982. "WhiteMythology:Metaphorin the Lyotard, Jean-Francois. 1994.Lessonson theAnalyticoftheSub-
Textof Philosophy."In MarginsofPhilosophy. Trans.Alan lime.Trans.ElizabethRottenberg. Stanford:StanfordUni-
Bass. Chicago:University of ChicagoPress. versity Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 1984. "Deconstructionand the Other."In MacBeath,A. Murray.1973. "Kant on Moral Feeling."Kant-
Dialogues withContemporaryContinentalThinkers:The Studien64:283-314.
Phenomenological Heritage,ed. RichardKearney.Manches- McCarty,Richard.1993."KantianMoral Motivationand the
ter:ManchesterUniversity Press. Feeling of Respect."Journalof theHistoryof Philosophy
Derrida, Jacques. 1992. The OtherHeading: Reflectionson 31:421-435.
Today'sEurope.Trans.Pascale Anne Braultand Michael B. Nancy,Jean-Luc. 1993. The Experienceof Freedom.Trans.
Nass. Bloomington:Indiana University Press. BridgetMcDonald. Stanford:StanfordUniversity Press.
Derrida,Jacques.1996."Remarkson Deconstruction and Prag- O'Neill, Onora. 1989. Constructions ofReason:Explorations of
matism."Trans. Simon Critchley.In Deconstructionand Kant'sPracticalPhilosophy. Cambridge:CambridgeUniver-
Pragmatism, ed. ChantalMouffe.London: Routledge. sityPress.
Fenves,PeterD. 1991.A PeculiarFate:Metaphysics and World- Paton,H. J.1971. The CategoricalImperative: A Studyin Kant's
Historyin Kant.Ithaca:CornellUniversity Press. Moral Philosophy. Philadelphia:University of Pennsylvania
Gregor,Mary.1963.LawsofFreedom:A StudyofKant'sMethod Press.
ofApplying theCategoricalImperative in theMetaphysik der Rawls,John.1971. A TheoryofJustice.Cambridge:Harvard
Sitten.Oxford:Basil Blackwell. University Press.
Habermas, Juergen.1993. "Moralityand Ethical Life:Does Rawls,John.1980."KantianConstructivism in Moral Theory."
Hegel'sCritiqueof KantApplyto DiscourseEthics?"Trans. TheJournalofPhilosophy 77:515-572.
ChristianLenhardtand Shierry WeberNicholsen.In KantcS Reath,Andrews.1989. "Kant's Theoryof Moral Sensibility."
PoliticalPhilosophy:The Contemporary Legacy,ed. Ronald Kant-Studien 80:284-302.
Beinerand WilliamJamesBooth.New Haven:Yale Univer- Schneewind,J.B. 1992."Autonomy, Obligation,and Virtue:An
sityPress. Overviewof Kant'sMoral Philosophy."In The Cambridge
Hamacher,Werner.1996. Premises:Essayson Philosophyand CampaniontoKant,ed. Paul Guyer.Cambridge:Cambridge
Literature fromKant to Celan. Trans. PeterFenves.Cam- University Press.
bridge:HarvardUniversity Press. Shell,Susan Meld. 1980. TheRightsofReason:A StudyofKant's
Honig,Bonnie. 1993. PoliticalTheoryand theDisplacementof Philosophyand Politics.Toronto: Universityof Toronto
Politics.Ithaca:CornellUniversity Press. Press.
Kant,Immanuel.1960.Observations on theFeelingoftheBeau- Shell,Susan Meld. 1996. The Embodiment ofReason:Kant on
tifuland Sublime.Trans.JohnT. Goldthwait.Berkeley:Uni- Spirit,Generation, and Community. Chicago: University of
versity of CaliforniaPress. Chicago Press.
Kant,Immanuel.1963. Lectureson Ethics.Trans.Louis Infield. Sokoloff,WilliamW. 2001. "Politicsand Anxietyin Hobbes's
Indianapolis:HackettPublishingCompany. Leviatha n." TheorycSEvent.5:1.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KANT AND THE PARADOX OF RESPECT 779

Teuber,Andreas.1983."Kant's RespectforPersons."Political RobertPaul. 1973. TheAutonomy


Wolff, ofReason:A Commen-
Theory11:369-392. taryon Kant'sGroundwork ofMorals.New
oftheMetaphysic
Velkley,
RichardL. 1989.Freedomand theEndofReason:On the York:Harper& Row.
Moral FoundationofKant's CriticalPhilosophy.Chicago:
Universityof ChicagoPress.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.133 on Thu, 29 May 2014 13:32:05 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like