You are on page 1of 1

Search Wikipedia Search Create account Log in

Intention 32 languages

Contents hide Article Talk Read Edit View history Tools

(Top) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Definition
For the philosophical concept, see Intentionality. For other uses, see Intention (disambiguation).
Theories of intention Several terms redirect here. For other uses, see Intent (disambiguation), Intentionally (horse), Intentions (disambiguation), and Purpose
Types of intentions (disambiguation).

Formation of intentions An intention is a mental state in which the agent commits themselves to a course of action. Having the plan to visit the zoo tomorrow is an example of
an intention. The action plan is the content of the intention while the commitment is the attitude towards this content. Other mental states can have action
Psychological functions
plans as their content, as when one admires a plan, but differ from intentions since they do not involve a practical commitment to realizing this plan.
Knowledge of the intention of Successful intentions bring about the intended course of action while unsuccessful intentions fail to do so. Intentions, like many other mental states, have
others
intentionality: they represent possible states of affairs.
In criminal law
Theories of intention try to capture the characteristic features of intentions. The belief-desire theory is the traditionally dominant approach. According to a
Relation to other concepts
simple version of it, having an intention is nothing but having a desire to perform a certain action and a belief that one will perform this action. Belief-
See also desire theories are frequently criticized based on the fact that neither beliefs nor desires involve a practical commitment to performing an action, which is
References often illustrated in various counterexamples. The evaluation theory tries to overcome this problem by explaining intentions in terms of unconditional
evaluations. That is to say that intentions do not just present the intended course of action as good in some respect, as is the case for desires, but as
External links
good all things considered. This approach has problems in explaining cases of akrasia, i.e. that agents do not always intend what they see as the best
course of action. A closely related theory identifies intentions not with unconditional evaluations but with predominant desires. It states that intending to
do something consists in desiring it the most. Opponents of this approach have articulated various counterexamples with the goal of showing that
intentions do not always coincide with the agent's strongest desire. A different approach to the theories mentioned so far is due to Elizabeth Anscombe
and denies the distinction between intentions and actions. On her view, to intend a goal is already a form of acting towards this goal and therefore not a
distinct mental state. This account struggles to explain cases in which intentions and actions seem to come apart, as when the agent is not currently
doing anything towards realizing their plan or in the case of failed actions. The self-referentiality theory suggests that intentions are self-referential, i.e.
that they do not just represent the intended course of action but also represent themselves as the cause of the action. But the claim that this happens on
the level of the content of the intention has been contested.

The term "intention" refers to a group of related phenomena. For this reason, theorists often distinguish various types of intentions in order to avoid
misunderstandings. The most-discussed distinction is that between prospective and immediate intentions. Prospective intentions, also known as "prior
intentions", involve plans for the future. They can be subdivided according to how far they plan ahead: proximal intentions involve plans for what one
wants to do straightaway whereas distal intentions are concerned with a more remote future. Immediate intentions, on the other hand, are intentions that
guide the agent while they are performing the action in question. They are also called "intentions-in-action" or "act-related" intentions. The term
"intention" usually refers to anticipated means or ends that motivate the agent. But in some cases, it can refer to anticipated side-effects that are neither
means nor ends to the agent. In this case, the term "oblique intention" is sometimes used. Intentions are rationally evaluable: they are either rational or
irrational. Conscious intentions are the paradigmatic form of intention: in them, the agent is aware of their goals. But it has been suggested that actions
can also be guided by unconscious intentions of which the agent is not aware.

The formation of intentions is sometimes preceded by the deliberation of promising alternative courses of action and may happen in decisions, in which
the agent chooses between these alternatives. Intentions are responsible for initiating, sustaining, and terminating actions and are frequently used to
explain why people engage in a certain behavior. Understanding the behavior of others in terms of intentions already happens in early childhood.
Important in this context is the role of gestures, pointing, attention, and eye movement to understand the intentions of others and to form shared
intentions. In the philosophy of action, a central question is whether it is true for all intentional actions that they are caused or accompanied by intentions.
The theory of reasoned action aims to predict behavior based on how pre-existing attitudes and subjective norms determine behavioral intentions. In
ethics, the intention principle states that whether an action is morally permissible sometimes depends on the agent's intention for performing this action.

Definition [ edit ]

Intentions are mental states that involve action plans to which the agent has committed themselves.[1][2][3][4] As action plans, they can guide behavior.
The action plan constitutes the content of the intention while the commitment is the agent's attitude towards this content.[5][6] The term "intention" can be
used both for prospective intentions, which are not yet executed, and for the intentions guiding the behavior as it happens, so-called immediate
intentions, as discussed below.[1][2][3][7][8] Intending to study tomorrow is an example of prospective intentions while trying to win a game by scoring a
three-point field goal involves an act-related intention.

Folk psychology explains human behavior on the basis of mental states, including beliefs, desires, and intentions.[9][10] This explanation is based on the
idea that desires motivate behavior and beliefs direct the behavior towards the desired goal.[11] This can be understood in terms of causal chains, i.e. that
desires cause intentions, intentions cause actions, and actions cause the realization of the desired outcome.[9]

Content and commitment [ edit ]

Intentions, like various other mental states, can be understood as consisting of two components: a content and an attitude towards this content.[6] On this
view, the content of an intention is the action plan in question and the attitude involves a commitment to executing this action.[5] Intentions may share the
same content with other mental states, like beliefs and desires. But the different mental states are distinguished from each other concerning their
attitudes.[5][6] Admiring the idea of helping the poor, for example, is different from intending to help the poor, even though both states share the same plan
as their content.[5] One difference between desires and intentions is that intentions impose more restrictions on their contents.[1] This includes that
intentions are directed at possible courses of action, i.e. that they involve something the agent can do or at least thinks they can do.[1][2][3][4] Desires, on
the other hand, do not involve this form of restriction.[1] In this sense, it is possible to desire sunny weather for tomorrow but not to intend sunny weather
for tomorrow.

A central aspect of intentions concerning the attitude towards their content is that the agent has committed themselves to the plan in question. This is
different from merely wanting to do something and thinking that doing it would be good.[5][3] It is sometimes argued that this commitment consists in an
all-out judgment that the intended course of action is good.[2][4][12] On this view, intentions evaluate their intended course of action as good all things
considered. This aspect stands in contrast to desires, which evaluate their object merely as good in some sense but leave it open whether it is bad in
another sense.[2][4][12] Someone who is still deliberating whether to perform a certain action, for example, has not yet committed themselves to
performing it and therefore lacks the corresponding intention.[5][3] It has been argued that this form of commitment or being-settled-on is unique to
intentions and is not found in other mental states like beliefs or desires. In this sense, intentions may be based on or accompanied by beliefs and desires
but are not reducible to them.[5][6]

Another important aspect of intentions is that they have conditions of satisfaction, like beliefs and desires.[3][13] This means that intentions are either
successful or unsuccessful. An intention that produces the intended action is a successful intention. But if the produced behavior falls short of its goal, the
intention is unsuccessful.[5][13] The content of the intention determines its conditions of satisfaction. Success is usually not fully up to the agent since
various factors outside the agent's control and awareness may influence the success of the attempted action.[5]

Intention and intentionality [ edit ]

The meaning of the term "intention" is different from the term "intentionality" even though the two are closely related.[14][15] Intentionality is the more
general term: it refers to the power of minds to represent or to stand for things, properties, and states of affairs. Intentions are one form of intentionality
since their contents represent possible courses of action.[16] But there are other forms of intentionality, like simple beliefs or perceptions, that do not
involve intentions.[16] The adjective "intentional" is ambiguous since it can refer either to intentions or to intentionality.[17]

Theories of intention [ edit ]

Theories of intention try to capture the characteristic features of intentions. Some accounts focus more either on prospective or on immediate intentions
while others aim at providing a unified account of these different types of intention.[2]

Belief-desire theory [ edit ]

The traditionally dominant approach reduces intentions to beliefs and action-desires.[1][2][3] An action-desire is a desire to perform an action.[5] On this
view, to intend to do sport tomorrow is to have a desire to do sport tomorrow together with a belief that one will do sport tomorrow.[1] Some accounts also
hold that this belief is based on the desire: one believes that one will do it because one desires to do it.[2] A similar definition sees intentions as "self-
fulfilling expectations that are motivated by a desire for their fulfillment and that represent themselves as such".[2] An important virtue of this approach is
its simplicity and its explanatory power. It also manages to account for the fact that there seems to be a close relationship between what one believes,
what one desires, and what one intends. But various arguments against this reduction have been presented in the contemporary literature.[1][5][2] These
often take the form of counterexamples, in which there is both a corresponding belief and a desire without an intention or an intention without one of
these components.[4] This is sometimes explained in relation to the idea that intentions involve a form of commitment to or settledness on the intended
course of action by the agent.[5][3] But this aspect is not present in beliefs and desires by themselves.[5] For example, when considering whether to
respond to an insult through retaliation, the agent may have both a desire to do so and a belief that they will end up doing this, based on how they acted
in the past. But the agent may still lack the corresponding intention since they are not fully decided.[5] It is also possible to have an intention to do
something without believing that one actually will do it, for example, because the agent had similar intentions earlier and also failed to act on them back
then or because the agent is unsure whether they will succeed.[4][2] But it has been argued that a weaker relation between intentions and beliefs may be
true, e.g. that intentions involve a belief that there is a chance of achieving what one intends.[4]

Another objection focuses on the normative difference between beliefs and intentions.[2] This is relevant for cases where the agent fails to act according
to the intended course of action, for example, due to having a weak will. This type of failure is different from the mere epistemic error of incorrectly
predicting one's own behavior. But various belief-desire theories are unable to explain this normative difference.[2] Other arguments focus on the
dissimilarities between these states. For example, one can desire impossible things but one cannot intend to do what one thinks is impossible. And
whereas beliefs can be true or false, this does not apply to intentions.[1]

Evaluation theory [ edit ]

Another prominent approach, due to Donald Davidson, sees intentions as evaluative attitudes. On his view, desires are conditional evaluative attitudes
while intentions are unconditional evaluative attitudes.[4][2][12] This means that desires see their object as positive in a certain respect while intentions see
their object as positive overall or all things considered. So the agent may have a desire to go to the gym because it is healthy whereas their intention to
go to the gym is based on the evaluation that it is good all things considered.[4] This theory is closely related to the belief-desire theory explained above
since it also includes the idea that beliefs are involved in intentions. Here the belief in question is not a belief that one will do the action but a belief that
the action in question is a means towards the positively evaluated end.[2][12]

This theory has been criticized based on the idea that there is a difference between evaluating a course of action and committing oneself to a course of
action. This difference is important for explaining cases of akrasia, i.e. that people do not always do what they believe would be best to
do.[4][18][19][2][12][1] An example of akrasia is an author who believes it would be best to work on his new book but ends up watching TV instead, despite
his unconditional evaluative attitude in favor of working. In this sense, intentions cannot be unconditional evaluative attitudes since it is possible to intend
to do one alternative while having an unconditional evaluative attitude towards another alternative.[2][12]

Strongest-desire theory [ edit ]

Another theory focuses exclusively on the relation between intention and desire. It states that intending to do something consists in desiring it the
most.[4][20][21] The claim that intentions are accompanied by desires is generally accepted. But there are various arguments against the claim that
intentions are nothing but desires. They often focus on cases where people intend to do something different from their predominant desire.[22] For
example, the agent may intend to go to the gym even though they have a much stronger desire to go to the pub instead. This may be the case because
the agent thinks that going to the gym is better even though this is not in tune with their desires.[4] Another counterexample comes from cases where the
agent has not yet formed an intention even though one desire is predominant.[4] A closely related theory understands intentions as dispositions to act and
desires as dispositions to form intentions, i.e. as higher-order dispositions to act.[4]

Intending as doing [ edit ]

Most theories of intention see intentions as mental states that are closely related to actions but may occur without the corresponding action in question.
Elizabeth Anscombe and her followers provide an alternative account that denies the distinction between intentions and actions.[2][23][13] On this view, to
intend a goal is already a form of acting towards this goal and therefore not a distinct mental state. This means that when one intends to visit the zoo next
Thursday, one is already on the way to doing so.[2] An important strength of this account is that it gives a unified explanation of intentions: it does not
need to distinguish between prospective and immediate intentions since all intentions are immediate intentions.[2][23]

An obvious counterargument to this position is that, in the example of the zoo above, one is not currently doing anything towards realizing this plan.[23]
Defenders have rejected this argument by trying to elucidate how even minimal preparatory steps may already be seen as part of the action.[2] Such
steps may include, for example, not making any other plans that may interfere with the plan in question, like planning a different appointment at the same
time at a different location. Another objection is based on the observation that not all intentions are successful, i.e. that one can intend to do something
but fail to do it.[2] For example, one may intend to follow the shortest route home but take a wrong turn and thereby fail to perform the corresponding
action. In such cases, it may be argued that the intention was present whereas the action was absent, i.e. the agent intended to take the shortest route
but did not take the shortest route. The possibility of the two coming apart would suggest that they are not identical.[2]

Self-referentiality theory [ edit ]

The self-referentiality theory asserts that one central feature of intentions is that they are self-referential.[4] This means that the intentions do not just
represent the intended course of action but also represent themselves as the cause of the action. On this view, the intention to go to the gym represents
itself as the cause of going to the gym.[4][2][24][25] One important motivation for accepting a self-referentiality theory is to explain a certain type of case: a
case in which the behavior is just like it was intended, but the intention either did not cause the behavior at all or did not cause it in the right way.[24][25]
For example, the agent intends to shoot an intruder, is then startled by a moving shadow, which causes their finger to twitch, thereby shooting the
intruder.[4] It is often claimed that in such cases, the behavior in question does not constitute an intentional action, i.e. that the agent did not shoot the
intruder intentionally, despite intending to shoot the intruder and shooting the intruder.[4] This paradox can be solved through self-referentiality theories.
The behavior in question is not an intentional action because the intention was not properly realized: it was part of the intention to cause the behavior,
which did not happen in the right way.[24][25] It is usually accepted that intentions have to cause the corresponding behavior in the right way for intentional
actions to arise. But the claim that this happens on the level of the content of the intention, i.e. that the intention represents itself as causing the behavior,
is often contested.[4][2][24][25] Instead, it has been argued that the content of intentions consists only of the corresponding action plan without representing
the intention itself and its causal relation to the execution of this plan.[4]

Types of intentions [ edit ]

Some difficulties in understanding intentions are due to various ambiguities and inconsistencies in how the term is used in ordinary language. For this
reason, theorists often distinguish various types of intentions in order to avoid misunderstandings and to clearly specify what is being researched.[3]

Prospective and immediate [ edit ]

An important difference among intentions is that between prospective and immediate intentions.[1][2][3] Prospective intentions, also called "prior
intentions", are forward-looking: they are plans held by the agent to perform some kind of action in the future. They are different from merely desiring to
perform this action since the agent has committed themselves to following them when the time comes.[1][2][3] In this sense, it is sometimes held that
desires evaluate their object only concerning one specific aspect while the commitments in intentions are based on an all-out evaluation. On this view,
the intended course of action is not just evaluated as good in one way but good all things considered.[2][4][12] In some cases, the intention may point very
far into the future, as when a teenager decides they want to become president one day.[26] In other cases, the formation of the prospective intention only
slightly precedes the action, as when the agent intends to scratch their back and does so right away.[26] The commitment to the course of action is
reversible. So if the agent encounters good reasons later on for not going through with it, the intention may be dropped or reformulated. In this sense,
having a prospective intention to perform a specific action does not ensure that this action will actually be performed later on.[1][5][26]

Immediate intentions, also known as "intentions-in-action" or "act-related" intentions, are intentions that guide the agent while they are performing the
action in question.[1][2][3][26] They are closely related to the sense of agency.[27][28][29] The agent's commitment to the course of action in question
consists in their active execution of the plan. But not all forms of human behavior are intentional. Raising one's hand may happen intentionally or
unintentionally, for example, when a student wants to signal to the teacher that they have a question in contrast to an involuntary bodily reflex.[26] It is
often held that a central aspect of immediate intentions is that the agent knows what they are doing and why they are doing it.[2][26] This means that the
action is accompanied by a certain form of knowledge that is absent in mere purposive behavior. This aspect is sometimes used to contrast the behavior
of humans and animals.[2] There is no general agreement that all intentional actions are accompanied by this type of knowledge. One reason to doubt
this is that even for intentional actions, the agent is not always able to articulate what they are doing and why they are doing it. Some defenders try to
explain this by holding that the corresponding knowledge is there, even if it is not conscious.[2]

Proximal and distal [ edit ]

Prospective intentions can be categorized by how far they plan ahead. Proximal intentions involve plans for what one wants to do straightaway whereas
distal intentions plan further ahead.[5][3][30][31][32][33] The same intention can be both proximal and distal if it is directed both at what to do right now and
what to do later. For example, deciding to start watching a movie now in one sitting involves an intention that is both proximal and distal.[5] This distinction
is important since many courses of action are too complex to be represented at once in full detail. Instead, usually only proximal intentions involve
detailed representations while distal intentions may leave their object vague until it becomes more relevant to the task at hand. But distal intentions still
play an important role in guiding the formation of proximal intentions.[5] A simple plan to buy batteries at the close-by electronics store, for example,
involves many steps, like putting on shoes, opening one's door, closing and locking it, going to the traffic light, turning left, etc. These steps are not
represented in full detail while the agent is putting on their shoes. Central to this process is the agent's ability to monitor the progress in relation to the
proximal intention and to adjust the current behavior accordingly.[5] In this way, intention has the capacity to coordinate the agent's behavior over time.
While both proximal and distal intentions are relevant for one's sense of agency, it has been argued that distal intentions lead to a stronger sense of
agency.[33]

Motivational and oblique [ edit ]

The intentional actions performed by agents usually carry a vast number of major or minor consequences with them. The agent is usually unaware of
many of them. In relation to these consequences, the agent is acting unintentionally.[3] Other consequences are anticipated by the agent. Some are
motivational in that they constitute the agent's reason for performing the action. A third type involves consequences of which the agent is aware but which
play no important role for the agent's motivation. These are the objects of oblique intentions: they involve side effects that the agent puts up with in order
to realize their main intention.[5][4][1][3][34] For example, Ted is unaware that smoking causes bladder cancer, but he is aware that it helps him to deal with
stress and that it causes lung cancer. His reason for smoking is to deal with stress. Increasing his risk of lung cancer is a side effect he puts up with. So
when smoking, Ted unintentionally increases his risk of bladder cancer, his motivational intention is to deal with stress whereas increasing his risk of lung
cancer is obliquely intended. Motivational intentions are the paradigmatic form of intentions and are the main focus of the academic literature on
intentions.[1]

These distinctions are relevant for morality and the law.[5][34] Committing a crime unintentionally, for example, is usually seen as a less serious offense
than committing the same crime intentionally.[5][34] This is often referred to as negligence in contrast to having bad intentions. It is usually held that bad
consequences intended obliquely carry more weight on a moral level than unintentional bad consequences.[1] There is no consensus whether obliquely
intended behavior constitutes an intentional action, e.g. whether it is correct to state that smokers aware of the dangers intentionally damage their
health.[4]

Rational and irrational [ edit ]

Intentions are rationally evaluable: they are either rational or irrational. In this sense, they stand in contrast to arational mental states, like urges or
experiences of dizziness, which are outside the domain of rationality.[35] Various criteria for the rationality of intentions have been proposed.[4][3] Some
hold that intentions are based on desires and beliefs and that, therefore, their rationality depends on these desires and beliefs.[36][37] On this view,
desires present certain goals, beliefs present the means needed to achieve these goals and intentions constitute commitments to realize the means
towards these goals. In this sense, an intention that is based on irrational states is itself irrational.[36] For example, the intention to heal oneself through
the power of crystals is irrational if it is based on an irrational belief concerning the healing power of crystals. But irrationality can also arise if two
intentions are not consistent with each other, i.e. if the agent intends both to perform one action and to perform another action while believing that these
two actions are incompatible with each other.[2][38] A closely related form of irrationality applies to the relation between means and ends. This so-called
principle of means-end coherence holds that it is irrational to intend to perform one action without intending to perform another action while believing that
this latter action is necessary to achieve the former action.[2][39][38] For example, it would be irrational to intend to become healthy if the agent believes
that exercising is necessary to become healthy but is unwilling to exercise.[39] In such a case, it may still be rational for the agent to desire to become
healthy, but intending it is not. This principle is expressed in the proverb "he who wills the end, wills the means".[40] It has also been suggested that
additional requirements of rationality concern the consistency between one's beliefs and one's intentions.[3]

Conscious and unconscious [ edit ]

Of special importance to psychology and psychoanalysis is the difference between conscious and unconscious intentions.[41][42] Unconscious intentions
are often used to explain cases where an agent behaves a certain way without being aware of this.[43] This is especially relevant if the behavior is clearly
directed at a goal while the agent does not consciously intend to pursue this goal or is not even aware of having this goal. At first, unconscious intentions
are usually ascribed to the agent by spectators and may only be avowed by the agent themselves retrospectively.[44] But this form of explanation is not
always conclusive, since, at least for some cases, other explanations are available as well. For example, some behavior may be explained as the
execution of a blind habit, which may occur with neither consciousness nor intention.[43]

Various prominent examples, due to Sigmund Freud, involve slips of the tongue, like declaring a meeting to be closed when one intends to open it.[45]
Freud sees such phenomena not as unintentional errors but ascribes to them a deeper meaning as expressions of unconscious wishes. As a window to
the unconscious, interpreting the unconscious intentions behind such phenomena and raising the patient's awareness of them are important aspects of
Freudian psychoanalysis.[45][44][46] But there is no general agreement as to whether this type of behavior should be seen as intentional behavior.[47]
Unconscious intentions are also sometimes used to explain apparently irrational behavior. In this sense, it has been claimed that excessive hand
washing seen in some people with the obsessive-compulsive disorder may be motivated by an unconscious intention to wash away one's guilt, even
though the person may cite very different reasons when asked.[43][48]

Critics of the notion of "unconscious intentions" have raised doubts about the empirical evidence cited in favor of unconscious intentions, which is often
based on interpretations resting on various controversial assumptions.[45] Another line of argument is directed against the concept of "unconscious
intention" itself.[45][43] On this view, it is incoherent to talk of the mental states in question as unconscious intentions. The reason given for this is that
intending something must be accompanied by some form of self-knowledge on the side of the agent about what is intended. This would not be possible if
the mental state is unconscious.[45][43]

Others [ edit ]

Various other distinctions among types of intentions are found in the academic literature. Conditional intentions are intentions to do something just in
case a certain condition obtains.[36] Planning to return a book to a friend on the condition that she asks for it is an example of a conditional intention.
Having the unconditional intention to return the book, on the other hand, involves planning to return it independent of the friend's behavior.[36]
Unconditional intentions are stronger in the sense that the agent is fully committed to the course of action without relying on the presence of a triggering
condition.[36]

Another distinction can be drawn between intentions that act as means to other intentions and intentions to do something for its own sake.[49][2] This is
closely related to the difference between intrinsic and instrumental desires. For example, an intention to go to the supermarket may be based on another
intention: the intention to eat. Because of this dependence, the agent would not have formed the earlier intention if the latter intention had been
absent.[49] In normal cases, the instrumental intention disappears if the intention it is based on does not exist anymore. In the example above, the agent
may drop the intention to go to the supermarket if their doctor recommends them to start fasting. But there are special cases in which the instrumental
intention persists nonetheless, sometimes referred to as motivational inertia.[50]

Formation of intentions [ edit ]

Intentions can arise in different ways. The paradigmatic type of intention formation happens through practical reason in the form of decisions.[51] In this
case, various alternatives are considered by the agent, who then chooses the most favorable one. This choice results in a commitment to the chosen
plan of action and thereby constitutes the formation of an intention. Often the choice itself is preceded by deliberation. Deliberation involves formulating
promising courses of action and assessing their value by considering the reasons for and against them.[52] An example of this type of intention formation
is a student who is up all night thinking about whether to major in English and then finally decides to do so.[5][3] But not all decisions are preceded by
deliberation and not every act of deliberation results in a decision. Another type of intention formation happens without making any explicit decision. In
such cases, the agent just finds themselves committed to the corresponding course of action without consciously deciding for it or against its
alternatives.[5] This is the case for many actions done out of habit. For example, habitually unlocking the office door in the morning is usually an
intentional action that happens without a prior explicit decision to do so.[5] It has been argued that decisions can be understood as a type of mental action
that consists in resolving uncertainty about what to do.[3] Decisions are usually seen as a momentary change from not having the intention to having it.
This contrasts with deliberation, which normally refers to a drawn-out process.[3] But these technical distinctions are not always reflected in how the
terms are used in ordinary language.[3]

Psychological functions [ edit ]

Intentions have various psychological functions in the agent's mind. Some theorists of intentions even base their definition of intentions on the functions
they execute. Intentions are responsible for initiating, sustaining, and terminating actions. In this sense, they are closely related to motivation.[3] They
also help guide the action itself and try to coordinate the agent's behavior over time.[5] A similar function of intentions is to coordinate one's behavior with
the behavior of other agents, either by forming intentions together or by reacting to the intentions others already have.[5] This enables various complex
forms of cooperation. Not every form of human behavior is guided by intentions. This concerns, for example, bodily reflexes like sneezing or other
uncontrolled processes like digestion, which happen without following a previously devised mental plan. Intentions are intimately related to practical
reason, i.e. to the reasons for which we act. These reasons are often explained in terms of beliefs and desires.[3] For example, the agent's reason to
cross a road may consist in their desire to reach the other side and their belief that this is achieved by crossing it.[3] Because of this close connection to
behavior, intentions are frequently used to explain why people engage in certain behavior. Such explanations are often teleological in the sense that they
cited the intended goal as the reason for the behavior.[9][11]

Knowledge of the intention of others [ edit ]

Developmental psychology [ edit ]

Developmental psychology is, among other things, concerned with how children learn to ascribe intentions to others. Understanding intention is thought
to be pivotal in understanding social contexts in numerous ways. First, acquiring an understanding of intention is important for development in that it
helps children conceptualize how people and animals differ from objects. Much of behavior is caused by intentions, and understanding intentions helps to
interpret these behaviors.[53] Second, intentions are integral to an understanding of morality.[54] Children learn to assign praise or blame based on
whether actions of others are intentional. Intention is also necessary to understand and predict the plans and future actions of others.[55] Understanding
the intentions and motives of others aids in the interpretation of communication,[56][57] and the achievement of cooperative goals.[58]

Psychological research suggests that understanding intentions of others may be a prerequisite for a higher-level understanding of other people's minds
or theory of mind.[59] Theory of mind research attempts to map how children come to understand the mind as a representational device for the world.[60]
This research has focused on the development of knowledge that others have beliefs, desires, and intentions that are different from one's own. A basic
ability to comprehend other people's intentions based on their actions is critical to the development of theory of mind.[59] Social, cognitive and
developmental psychological research has focused on the question: How do young children develop the ability to understand other people's behaviors
and intentions?

Infancy and early childhood [ edit ]

From an early age, typically-developing children parse human actions in terms of goals, rather than in terms of movements in space, or muscle
movements.[61] Meltzoff (1995)[62] conducted a study in which 18-month-olds were shown an unsuccessful act. For instance, children watched an adult
accidentally under or over shoot a target, or attempt to perform an action but their hand slipped. The aim of the study was to determine whether the
children were able to interpret the intention of the adult, regardless of the actual action performed. Young children have a tendency to imitate other
people's actions. The outcome measure was what the child chose to re-enact—the actual event (literal motions), or the adult's goal, which was not
accomplished.[62] The results of the study suggested that 18-month-olds are able to infer unseen goals and intentions of others based on their actions.
Infants who saw unsuccessful attempts at a target act and infants who saw the target act imitated the act at a higher rate than infants who saw neither
the act nor an attempt.[62] Similar paradigms were conducted with children 9 months old and 15 months old. Nine-month-olds did not respond to the
unsuccessful attempt demonstrations; however, 15-month-olds acted similarly to the 18-month-olds. This suggests that between 9 months and 15
months of age the ability to infer intentions in other people develops.[61]

The development of understanding intention has also been studied in toddlers. As mentioned previously, an intentional action is based on the belief that
the course of action will satisfy a desire.[60] In that case, what was intended can be interpreted as a function of an understanding for what was desired.
When outcomes are achieved without the action of the individual directed at the goal, intention is not attributed to the actor; rather, the event is
considered an accident.[8] Research by Astington and colleagues (1993)[9] found that 3-year-olds are skilled at matching goals to outcomes to infer
intention. If another individual's goals match an outcome, 3-year-olds are able to conclude that the action was done “on purpose.” Conversely, when
goals do not match outcomes, the children labeled the individual's actions as accidental.[9] Children may come to distinguish between desire and
intention when they learn to view the mind as a medium for representations of the world.[63] Astington argues that initially desire is undifferentiated from
intention in that both function as a goal state. Children then develop a more mature command of understanding other's intentions when they are able to
represent an action as caused by a prior intention that is separate from desire.[63]

Thus, research suggests that by the age of fifteen months, humans are capable of understanding intentional acts in others.[61] The ability to distinguish
between intention and desire develops in early childhood. Gestures and object-directed actions have also been studied in connexion with the
development of the understanding of intention. The development of the ability to use gestures and object-directed actions in social situations has been
studied from numerous perspectives, including the embodiment perspective and the social-cognitive perspective.

Gestures and pointing [ edit ]

Gestures are often recognized as a tool indicative of higher social reasoning. In order to engage in or understand a gesture, an individual has to
recognize it as an indicator of an object or event separate from the self or the actor. It is thought that pointing, especially declarative pointing (i.e. pointing
intended to direct and share intention rather than request an object), reveals the understanding of others as attentional and intentional agents (e.g.
Liszkowski, Carpenter, & Tomasello, 2007[64]). This understanding is indicated by object-directed reactions to pointing (rather than focusing on the
hand).[65] Pointing is also thought to denote perspective-taking ability and understanding of intention, as the individual must be able to understand that
the actor is attending to the object and, perhaps most importantly, that the actor is attempting to communicate information regarding the referent.[65] The
development of pointing is thought to reach a critical stage at around 9 to 12 months in normally developing children (e.g. Leung & Rheingold, 1981; Moll
& Tomasello, 2007; Schaffer, 2005[66][67][68]). Liszkowski, Carpenter and colleagues (2004)[69] found that human children begin to point at around one
year of age and do so with a multiple motives, including sharing attention and interest.[69] Earlier pointing may be different in nature and is thought to
develop from a learned association between reaching and adult responsiveness to the child's desire for a referent object.[70]

Thus, it seems pointing may be more complex than a straightforward indicator of social understanding. Early pointing may not indicate an understanding
of intention; rather it may indicate an association between the gesture and interesting objects or events.[71][72][73] However, an understanding of intention
may develop as the child develops a theory of mind and begins to use pointing to convey meaning about referents in the world.

Attention and eye movement [ edit ]

Research suggests that faces are pivotal in offering social cues necessary for children's cognitive, language, and social development. These cues may
offer information on another's emotional state,[74][75] focus of attention,[76] and potential intentions[77][78] (For a discussion see Mosconi, Mack, McCarthy,
& Pelphrey, 2005[79]). Intention may be ascribed to an individual based on where in space that individual is attending. Intention is understood not only
through actions and the manipulation of objects, but by tracking eye movements.[61] Research in this area is focused on how humans develop the
understanding that eye gaze indicates that the observer may be psychologically connected to the referent.[61]

Intention-ascription based on biological motion [ edit ]

Neuroimaging research suggests that biological motion is processed differently from other types of motion. Biological motion is processed as a category
in which individuals are able to infer intention.[59] An evolutionary perspective of this phenomenon is that humans survived on the basis of being able to
predict the internal mental states and potential future actions of others. Research on biological motion has found cells in the primate superior temporal
polysensory area (STP) that respond specifically to biological motion.[80] In addition, there are brain regions, including the superior temporal sulcus, that
respond to biological but not non-biological motion.[81][82] These findings suggest that humans may have a biologically-based affinity for spotting and
interpreting purposeful, biological motions.

In one experiment, 18-month-olds observed either a human or a mechanical arm attempting to perform actions, but failing to achieve a goal. The children
imitated the action to complete the intended goal when the arm was human, but not when it was mechanical. This suggests that from a young age,
humans are able to infer intention specifically as a biological mechanism between motions and goals.[83]

Humans have a tendency to infer intention from motion, even in the absence of other distinguishing features (e.g. body shape, emotional expression).
This was demonstrated in a study by Heider and Simmel;[84] they had observers view videos of moving triangles, and found that participants tended to
attribute intentions and even personality traits to the shapes based on their movements. The movement had to be animate, meaning self-propelled and
non-linear.[84]

Johansson[85] devised a way to study biological motion without interference from other characteristics of humans such as body shape, or emotional
expression. He attached dots of light to actors' joints and recorded the movements in a dark environment, so that only the dots of light were visible. The
Johansson figures, as they came to be known, have been used to demonstrate that individuals attribute mental states, such as desires and intentions to
movements, that are otherwise disconnected from context.[59]

Simulation theory [ edit ]

The simulation hypothesis holds that in order to understand intention in others, individuals must observe an action, and then infer the actor's intentions by
estimating what their own actions and intentions might be in the situation.[59] Individuals connect their own actions to internal mental states through the
experience of sensory information when movements are carried out; this sensory information is stored and connected to one's own intentions. Since
internal mental states, such as intention, cannot be understood directly through observing movements, it is hypothesized that these internal states are
inferred based on one's own stored representations of those movements.[59]

This theory is supported by research on mirror neurons, or neural regions, including the premotor cortex, and parietal cortex, that activate both when
individuals are engaging in an action, and when they are observing the actions of others. This suggests individuals may be simulating the motor
movements via internal representations of their own motor movements.[86][87] Thus, research indicates that humans are hard-wired to notice biological
motion, infer intention, and use previous mental representations to predict future actions of others.

In criminal law [ edit ]

Main article: Intention (criminal law)

Intention or intent is a key aspect in criminal law. It refers to the state of mind of the perpetrator, specifically to their plan to commit a crime.[88] As such, it
belongs to the mental element of the crime, known as mens rea, and not to the physical element, actus reus.[89][90] Some form of mens rea is usually
required for criminal offenses but legal transgressions committed without it can still be grounds for civil liability.[89] The severity of criminal offenses often
depends on the type and the degree of intent involved.[91][90] But the specific characterizations and the role of intent differ from jurisdiction to
jurisdiction.[92]

In criminal law, an important distinction is between general and specific intent. General intent is the weaker term. It implies that the person meant to act
the way they did. It does not imply that they wanted to cause harm or that they were trying to achieve a particular result, unlike specific intent.[93][91] For
some offenses, general intent is sufficient while for others, specific intent is required. For example, battery and manslaughter are usually seen as general
intent offenses while for murder, a specific intent is required.[93][94][95] This distinction is closely related to the difference between direct and indirect
intent, but not identical to it. Direct intent refers to the desire to bring about a specific outcome. Indirect intent is about an almost certain outcome of an
action that the agent is aware of but does not actively want. For example, if Ben intends to murder Ann with a stone by throwing it at her through a closed
window then murdering Ann is a direct intent while breaking the window is an indirect intent.[90]

For most criminal offenses, to ensure a conviction, the prosecution must prove that there was intent (or another form of mens rea) in addition to showing
that the accused physically committed the crime.[96] There are different ways in which intent can be proved or disproved depending on the case and the
type of intent involved. One way to do so is to look at previous statements by the accused to assess whether a motive was present. For example, if a
female employee is accused of murdering her male boss, then her previous blog posts condemning the patriarchal society and idolizing women who
killed men could be used as evidence of intent.[97] Certain forms of evidence can also be employed by the defense to show that intent was not present.
For example, a person suffering from seizures could claim that, when they hit another person, they did not do so intentionally but under the effect of a
seizure.[98] If the perpetrator was intoxicated during the crime, this may be used as a defense by claiming that no specific intent was present. This is
based on the idea that the defendant was mentally too impaired to form a specific intent.[91]

Relation to other concepts [ edit ]

Beliefs and desires [ edit ]

Intentions are closely related to other mental states, like beliefs and desires.[3] It is generally accepted that intentions involve some form of desire: the
intended action is seen as good or desirable in some sense.[2] This aspect makes it possible for intentions to motivate actions. Various ways have been
suggested how intentions are related to beliefs. On the one hand, it seems impossible to intend to do something one beliefs to be impossible.[2] Some
accounts go even further and suggest that intentions involve the belief that one will perform the action in question.[2][1][5] Besides that, it has been
suggested that beliefs are necessary for intentions to connect the behavior to the intended goal. On this view, intentions involve the belief that the
intended behavior would cause the intended goal.[2][12]

Action [ edit ]

In the philosophy of action, a central question is how actions are to be defined, i.e. how they differ from other types of events like a sunrise, a car
breaking down, or digestion. The most common approach to this question defines actions in terms of intentions.[5] According to Donald Davidson, an
action is an event that is intentional under some description. On this view, it is a central aspect of actions that they are caused by an agent's mental state:
their intention.[99][100][2] Another important aspect is that this causation happens in the right way, i.e. that the intention causes the event it planned and
that the event is caused by employing the agent's abilities. These additional requirements are needed to exclude so-called "wayward" causal chains, i.e.
cases in which the intended behavior happens but the corresponding intention either did not cause the behavior at all or did not cause it in the right
way.[101][102][2][3]

Some philosophers have rejected this close link between action and intention. This criticism is based on the idea that a person can perform an action
intentionally without having a corresponding intention to perform this action.[4][2][3] Doing something intentionally is usually associated with doing it for a
reason. The question then is whether doing something for a reason is possible without having a corresponding intention.[2][3] This is especially relevant
for simple actions that are part of bigger routines. Walking to the cinema, for example, involves taking various steps. According to this argument, each
step is an intentional action but the agent does not form a distinct intention for each step. Instead, most of them are not explicitly represented by the
mind.[4] Another counterexample against the thesis that performing an action intentionally involves intending to perform this action is based on the
awareness of unintended side-effects, sometimes referred to as oblique intentions.[1][4][5] One example consists of a chairman deciding to endorse a new
project to boost profits despite its negative impact on the environment. In this case, it has been argued that the chairman intentionally harms the
environment without an intention to do so.[3]

Toxin puzzle [ edit ]

A well-known thought experiment concerning the relation between intention and action is the toxin puzzle due to Gregory Kavka.[5][103][104] It involves a
billionaire offering the agent one million dollars for forming the intention by the end of the day to drink a vial of toxin the following day. The toxin makes a
person ill for one day but has no lasting effect otherwise. It does not matter whether the agent actually drinks the toxin the next day, all that matters is that
they have the intention to do so by the end of today.[5][103][104] The puzzle concerns the question of whether it is possible to really form this intention. The
reason for doubting this is that once the agent has formed the intention and received the money, they have no reason anymore to actually drink the toxin:
this step is optional. But if they know all along that they won't drink the toxin after all, it is highly questionable whether they can actually form the
corresponding intention.[5][103][104] This is closely related to the idea that intending something entails believing that one will do it.[2][1][5] But since the
agent has no reason to actually do it once they have received the money, they would not believe that they would do it. This counts against the idea that
they can intend it to begin with.[5]

Various philosophers agree that it is impossible to form this type of intention.[105] Their goal is often to find a general principle explaining why this is the
case. Various accounts focus on the idea that the reason to perform the action is absent when it is time to perform it.[105][104] So the agent has a reason
to form the intention today but not a reason to perform the action tomorrow. So the reason for forming the intention is different from the reason for
performing the action. This is sometimes expressed by saying that the agent has the "wrong type of reason" to form the intention. On this account, it is
impossible to form the intention because the right type of reason for the intention is derivative of the reason for the action itself, which is absent.[105]

But not everyone agrees that forming the intention is impossible. According to the rationalist solution, for example, it is possible to form the intention
because there is a decisive reason to drink the toxin.[104] The idea behind this approach is that there are two options today: (1) not form the intention and
not drink the toxin or (2) form the intention and drink the toxin.[104] Since the second option maximizes utility, it is rational to follow it and drink the toxin.
The difficulty for this approach concerns explaining how the agent can hold onto their intention to drink the toxin after they have received the money.[104]

Theory of reasoned action [ edit ]

Although human behavior is extremely complex and still remains unpredictable, psychologists are trying to understand the influential factors in the
process of forming intentions and performing actions. The theories of Reasoned Action and Planned Behavior are comprehensive theories that specify a
limited number of psychological variables that can influence behavior, namely (a) intention; (b) attitude toward the behavior; (c) subjective norm; (d)
perceived behavioral control; and (e) behavioral, normative and control beliefs.[106] In the theory of reasoned action, intention is influenced by people's
attitude toward performing the behavior and the subjective norm. However, the level of perceived control is believed to be influential on people's
behavioral intention along with their attitude and subjective norms, according to the theory of planned behavior. Not surprisingly, in most studies, intention
is driven by attitudes to a greater extent than by subjective norms.[107]

The predictive validity of the theory of Reasoned Action has been examined in numerous studies that have previously served as literature for at least
three quantitative reviews. Ajzen and Fishbein (1973) reviewed 10 studies and reported a .63 average correlation for the prediction of behavior from
intentions and a mean multiple correlation of .76 for the equation predicting intentions from both attitudes and norms.[108] With similar objectives but
larger samples, Sheppard et al.'s and van den Putte's meta-analyses estimated correlations of .53 and .62 for the prediction of behavior and multiple
correlations of .66 and .68, respectively, for the prediction of intentions.[109][110] All these studies have reflected the strong correlation that exists between
people's attitudes, social norms and their intentions, as well as between their intention and the prediction of their behaviors. However, these correlations
do not remain unchanged across all the conditions in people's life. Although people are likely to develop intentions to perform the action in question if
they have a favorable attitude and perceive the behavior as controllable, then people's perception of control would be irrelevant to intentions when
people have negative attitudes and perceive normative pressure not to perform certain actions.[107] Research has also shown that people are more likely
to perform an action if they have previously formed the corresponding intentions. Their intentions to perform the action appear to derive from attitudes,
subjective norms, and perceived behavioral control.[111] To state an example: The reason one may be motivated to consume alcohol after work is
determined by several factors: (1) Intention. The idea that drinking can help an individual relieve stress and enjoy one's time, for example, can greatly
influence the attitude towards post-work drinking. (2) Subjective norms in one's surroundings. This factor is mainly cultural, so how much a society values
and rewards drinking, but also strongly influenced by one's immediate social circle's values about this specific issue. (3) Perceived behavioural control
towards the intended behaviour, specifically regarding the amounts of alcohol consumed. (4) Trends in behaviour. The longer the behaviour has been
influenced by the previous factors, the more likely the behaviour is prone to be repeated as the original intention becomes reinforced.

How people think about and verbally communicate their own intentions also impacts these intentions. For example, asking a question about prior
behaviors using the imperfective aspect of language seems to be able to bring out stronger intentions to perform such a behavior in the future.[112]
According to the World Atlas of Language Structures, "Imperfective Aspects" refers to a specific form of language structure used for reference to the
present and the future but also for ongoing and habitual events in the past. For example, ‘He writes/is writing/wrote/was writing/will write letters.’[113]
People are more likely to interpret the event as ongoing, and likely to resume the action in the future when it has been described with the imperfective
verb aspect.[114] Similarly, using present tense to describe an action as ongoing may strengthen intentions to perform the same action in the future.[115]
Previous research has showed that both information on past behavior and their attitude towards such behavior play crucial roles in predicting people's
future behavioral tendency.[116][117] Recent research done by Carrera and others concluded that verb tense may not have direct influence on intentions,
however it could still affect the type of information used as a basis of behavioral intentions. When participants described a past episode using the present
tense, they consistently used the more concrete past behavior as a basis for their intentions. In contrast, when participants described a past episode
using the past tense, they consistently used the more abstract attitude as a basis for their intentions.[118]

Morality [ edit ]

It is often suggested that the agent's intentions play a central role in the moral value of the corresponding actions.[119][120] This is sometimes termed the
"intention principle": the thesis that whether an action is morally permissible sometimes depends on the agent's intention for performing this action. On
this view, an otherwise permissible act may be impermissible if it is motivated by bad intentions.[119] For example, a doctor administers a lethal drug to a
suffering and terminally ill patient who consents. Defenders of the intention principle may claim that it depends on the doctor's intention whether this
action is permissible. Specifically, this concerns whether it is done with the intention to relieve the patient's pain or with the intention of getting rid of a
despised enemy. Opponents may claim that the moral difference in question only concerns the evaluation of the doctor as a person but not of their
action.[119][121] On this view, there is a difference between the moral values of persons and of actions: intentions concern the moral value of persons but
not of actions.[119][121] The intention principle is usually also rejected by consequentialists.[119] They hold that only the consequences of an action matter
but not how it was motivated.[122][123] According to utilitarians, for example, an action is right if it produces the greatest good for the greatest number of
people.[124] In some cases, even actions performed with bad intentions may have this effect.

Immanuel Kant is a famous defender of the intention principle. For him, it is central that one does not just act outwardly in accordance with one's duty,
which he terms "legality" (Legalität). Instead, the agent should also be inwardly motivated by the right intention, which he terms "morality"
(Moralität).[125][126][127][128][129] On this view, donating a lot of money to charities is still in some sense morally flawed if it is done with the intention of
impressing other people. According to Kant, the main intention should always be to do one's duty: the good will consist in doing one's duty for the sake of
duty.[125][129]

The doctrine of double effect is a closely related principle. It states that there are cases in which the agent may not intend to harm others, even if this
harm is used as means to a greater good. But in otherwise equivalent cases it is permissible to harm others if this harm is a side effect, or a double
effect, but not a means.[119][121] On this view, for example, terror bombing an ammunition factory in order to weaken the enemy's resolve by killing all the
civilians working in it is impermissible. But performing the same attack as a tactical bombing in order to reduce the enemy's ammunition supply is
permissible, even if the same amount of civilian deaths were foreseen as a side effect.[121][119] Many of the arguments directed at the intention principle
also apply to the doctrine of double effect. Additional arguments focus on the difficulty of drawing a general distinction between intended means and
foreseen side-effects.[121][119]

See also [ edit ]

Collective intentionality
Entention
Intention (criminal law)
Intentional stance
Intentionality
Intentions (disambiguation)
Motivation
Scienter
Telos (philosophy)

References [ edit ]

1. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Honderich, Ted (2005). "Intention". The 66. ^ Leung, Eleanor H.; Rheingold, Harriet L. (1981). "Development of pointing
Oxford Companion to Philosophy . Oxford University Press. as a social gesture". Developmental Psychology. 17 (2): 215–220.
2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am doi:10.1037/0012-1649.17.2.215 . S2CID 145185720 .
an ao ap aq ar Setiya, Kieran (2018). "Intention" . The Stanford 67. ^ Moll, H.; Tomasello, M. (2007). "Cooperation and human cognition: the
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford Vygotskian intelligence hypothesis". In Emery, N.; Clayton, N.; Frith, C
University. Retrieved 7 November 2021. (eds.). Social intelligence: From brain to culture. pp. 245–260.
3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac Mele, Alfred R. (2009). 68. ^ Schaffer, H.R. (2005). The child's entry into a social world. London:
"Intention and Intentional Action". In Beckermann, Ansgar; McLaughlin, Brian Academic Press.
P.; Walter, Sven (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. 69. ^ a b Liszkowski, Ulf; Carpenter, Malinda; Henning, Anne; Striano, Tricia;
pp. 691–710. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.003.0041 . ISBN 978- Tomasello, Michael (June 2004). "Twelve-month-olds point to share attention
0-19-926261-8. and interest". Developmental Science. 7 (3): 297–307. doi:10.1111/j.1467-
4. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa Craig, Edward (1996). 7687.2004.00349.x . hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0013-2524-6 .
"Intention". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Routledge. PMID 15595371 . S2CID 3915664 .
5. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai Borchert, 70. ^ Bates, E.; Benigni, L.; Bretherton, I.; Camaioni, L.; Volterra, V. (1979). The
Donald (2006). "Intention". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd emergence of symbols: Cognition and communication in infancy . New
Edition . Macmillan. York: Academic Press. ISBN 9781483267302.
6. ^ a b c d Oppy, Graham. "Propositional attitudes - Routledge Encyclopedia of 71. ^ Barresi, John; Moore, Chris (2010). "Intentional relations and social
Philosophy" . www.rep.routledge.com. Retrieved 13 November 2021. understanding". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 19 (1): 107–154.
7. ^ Pacherie, Elisabeth; Haggard; Patrick (2011). "What are intentions?" . In doi:10.1017/S0140525X00041790 . S2CID 145165393 .
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Nadel, Lynn (eds.). Conscious Will and 72. ^ Butterworth, George; Jarrett, Nicholas (1991). "What minds have in
Responsibility: A Tribute to Benjamin Libet. Oxford University Press. pp. 70– common is space: Spatial mechanisms serving joint visual attention in
84. ISBN 978-0-19-538164-1. infancy". British Journal of Developmental Psychology. 9 (1): 55–72.
8. ^ a b Searle, J.R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. doi:10.1111/j.2044-835X.1991.tb00862.x .
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. 73. ^ Moore, C. (1999). Zelazo, P.D.; Astington, J.W.; Olson, D.R. (eds.).
9. ^ a b c d e Astington, J.W. (1993). The child's discovery of the mind. Developing theories of intention. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Associates.
10. ^ Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge, 74. ^ Bassili, J.N. (1989). On-line Cognition in Person Perception. Hillsdale, NJ:
Massachusetts: Bradford Books/MIT Press. Lawrence Erlbaum.
11. ^ a b Malle, Bertram F.; Knobe, Joshua (March 1997). "The Folk Concept of 75. ^ Ekman, P. (1982). Emotion in the Human Face. New York: Cambridge
Intentionality". Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 33 (2): 101–121. University Press.
doi:10.1006/jesp.1996.1314 . S2CID 14173135 . 76. ^ Langton, S.R. (2000). "The mutual influence of gaze and head orientation
12. ^ a b c d e f g h Conradie, Niel Henk (2014). "3. DAVIDSON'S ACCOUNT OF in the analysis of social attention direction" (PDF). The Quarterly Journal
INTENTION". Towards a Convincing Account of Intention (PhD Thesis). of Experimental Psychology. A, Human Experimental Psychology. 53 (3):
University of Stellenbosch. 825–45. doi:10.1080/713755908 . hdl:1893/21047 . PMID 10994231 .
13. ^ a b c Driver, Julia (2018). "Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe: 4. S2CID 1880814 .
Action Theory" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics 77. ^ Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 November 2021. of Mind. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
14. ^ Jacob, Pierre (2019). "Intentionality" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of 78. ^ Baron‐Cohen, Simon; Wheelwright, Sally; Hill, Jacqueline; Raste, Yogini;
Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved Plumb, Ian (February 2001). "The 'Reading the Mind in the Eyes' Test
13 November 2021. Revised Version: A Study with Normal Adults, and Adults with Asperger
15. ^ "Britannica: intentionality" . www.britannica.com. Retrieved 13 November Syndrome or High‐functioning Autism". Journal of Child Psychology and
2021. Psychiatry. 42 (2): 241–251. doi:10.1111/1469-7610.00715 .
16. ^ a b Jacob, Pierre (2019). "Intentionality: 1. Why is intentionality so- PMID 11280420 . S2CID 3016793 .
called?" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics 79. ^ Mosconi, Matthew W.; Mack, Peter B.; McCarthy, Gregory; Pelphrey, Kevin
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 13 November 2021. A. (August 2005). "Taking an 'intentional stance' on eye-gaze shifts: A
17. ^ "Collins English Dictionary: Intentional" . www.collinsdictionary.com. functional neuroimaging study of social perception in children". NeuroImage.
Retrieved 13 November 2021. 27 (1): 247–252. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2005.03.027 .
18. ^ Lee W (2020). "Enkratic Rationality Is Instrumental Rationality" . PMID 16023041 . S2CID 25792636 .
Philosophical Perspectives. 34 (1): 164–183. doi:10.1111/phpe.12136 . 80. ^ Baizer, JS; Ungerleider, LG; Desimone, R (1991). "Organization of visual
ISSN 1520-8583 . inputs to the inferior temporal and posterior parietal cortex in macaques" .
19. ^ Steward H. "Akrasia - Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy" . The Journal of Neuroscience. 11 (1): 168–90. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.11-
www.rep.routledge.com. Retrieved 13 May 2021. 01-00168.1991 . PMC 6575184 . PMID 1702462 .

20. ^ McCann, Hugh (1995). "Intention and Motivational Strength". Journal of 81. ^ Oram, MW; Perrett, DI (1994). "Responses of Anterior Superior Temporal
Philosophical Research. 20: 571–583. doi:10.5840/jpr_1995_19 . Polysensory (STPa) Neurons to "Biological Motion" Stimuli". Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience. 6 (2): 99–116. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.330.4410 .
21. ^ Mele AR (2003). "7. Motivational Strength". Motivation and Agency .
doi:10.1162/jocn.1994.6.2.99 . PMID 23962364 . S2CID 18583392 .
Oxford University Press.
82. ^ Grossman, ED; Blake, R (2002). "Brain Areas Active during Visual
22. ^ Miller, Christian (June 2008). "Motivation in Agents". Noûs. 42 (2): 222–
Perception of Biological Motion" . Neuron. 35 (6): 1167–75.
266. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2008.00679.x .
doi:10.1016/s0896-6273(02)00897-8 . PMID 12354405 .
23. ^ a b c Conradie, Niel Henk (2014). "2. ANSCOMBE'S ACCOUNT OF
S2CID 14169352 .
INTENTION". Towards a Convincing Account of Intention (PhD Thesis).
83. ^ Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). "Understanding the intentions of others: Re-
University of Stellenbosch.
enactment of intended acts by 18-month-old children" . Developmental
24. ^ a b c d Mele, Alfred R. (1987). "Are Intentions Self-Referential?".
Psychology. 31 (5): 838–850. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.31.5.838 .
Philosophical Studies. 52 (3): 309–329. doi:10.1007/BF00354051 .
PMC 4137788 . PMID 25147406 .
JSTOR 4319923 . S2CID 170415727 .
abcd 84. ^ a b Heider, Fritz; Simmel, Marianne (1944). "An Experimental Study of
25. ^ Roth, Abraham Sesshu (2000). "The Self-Referentiality of
Apparent Behavior". The American Journal of Psychology. 57 (2): 243.
Intentions". Philosophical Studies. 97 (1): 11–52.
doi:10.2307/1416950 . JSTOR 1416950 . S2CID 143057281 .
doi:10.1023/A:1018336525240 . JSTOR 4320993 . S2CID 169717685 .
85. ^ Johansson, Gunnar (1973). "Visual perception of biological motion and a
26. ^ a b c d e f Conradie, Niel Henk (2014). "1. Five requirements for an
model for its analysis" . Perception & Psychophysics. 14 (2): 201–211.
convincing account of intention". Towards a Convincing Account of
doi:10.3758/BF03212378 .
Intention (PhD Thesis). University of Stellenbosch.
86. ^ Gallese, Vittorio; Fadiga, Luciano; Fogassi, Leonardo; Rizzolatti, Giacomo
27. ^ Schlosser, Markus (2019). "Agency" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of
(1996). "Action recognition in the premotor cortex" . Brain. 119 (2): 593–
Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved
609. doi:10.1093/brain/119.2.593 . PMID 8800951 .
9 October 2021.
87. ^ Gallese, V; Goldman, A (1 December 1998). "Mirror neurons and the
28. ^ Moore, James W. (29 August 2016). "What Is the Sense of Agency and
simulation theory of mind-reading". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 2 (12):
Why Does it Matter?" . Frontiers in Psychology. 7: 1272.
493–501. doi:10.1016/s1364-6613(98)01262-5 . PMID 21227300 .
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01272 . PMC 5002400 . PMID 27621713 .
S2CID 10108122 .
29. ^ Kawabe, Takahiro; Roseboom, Warrick; Nishida, Shin'ya (22 July 2013).
88. ^ Bergsmo, Morten (2005). Shelton, Dinah (ed.). Encyclopedia of Genocide
"The sense of agency is action–effect causality perception based on cross-
and Crimes Against Humanity . Macmillan Reference. p. 524. ISBN 978-0-
modal grouping" . Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological
02-865992-3.
Sciences. 280 (1763): 20130991. doi:10.1098/rspb.2013.0991 .
89. ^ a b Robinson, Paul H. (2002). Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice
PMC 3774240 . PMID 23740784 .
(2nd ed.). New York: Macmillan Reference USA. ISBN 9780028653198.
30. ^ Mele, Alfred (1 February 2008). "Proximal Intentions, Intention-reports, and
90. ^ a b c Elliott, Catherine; Quinn, Frances (2008). Criminal Law . Pearson
Vetoing". Philosophical Psychology. 21 (1): 1–14.
Longman. p. 16. ISBN 978-1-4058-5871-7.
doi:10.1080/09515080701867914 . S2CID 144771278 .
91. ^ a b c Phelps, Shirelle, ed. (2005). "Specific Intent". West's Encyclopedia of
31. ^ Mele, Alfred R. (1 November 2019). "On snubbing proximal intentions".
American Law . Thomson/Gale. ISBN 9780787663674.
Philosophical Studies. 176 (11): 2833–2853. doi:10.1007/s11098-018-1153-
0 . S2CID 149780291 . 92. ^ Crump, David (1 January 2010). "What Does Intent Mean?" . Hofstra
Law Review. 38 (4): 1060–81.
32. ^ Plaks, Jason E.; Robinson, Jeffrey S. (1 September 2017). "Proximal and
Distal Intent: Toward a New Folk Theory of Intentional Action". Review of 93. ^ a b Phelps, Shirelle, ed. (2005). "General Intent". West's Encyclopedia of
General Psychology. 21 (3): 242–254. doi:10.1037/gpr0000122 . American Law . Thomson/Gale. ISBN 9780787663674.
S2CID 148919243 . 94. ^ Lanham, David; Wood, David; Bartal, Bronwyn; Evans, Rob (2006).
33. ^ a b Vinding, Mikkel C.; Pedersen, Michael N.; Overgaard, Morten (1 Criminal Laws in Australia . Federation Press. p. 58. ISBN 978-1-86287-
September 2013). "Unravelling intention: Distal intentions increase the 558-6.
subjective sense of agency". Consciousness and Cognition. 22 (3): 810– 95. ^ Pollock, Joycelyn M. (28 December 2020). Criminal Law . Routledge.
815. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2013.05.003 . PMID 23732190 . p. 68. ISBN 978-1-000-28383-9.
S2CID 206955309 . 96. ^ Lerner, K. Lee; Lerner, Brenda Wilmoth (2006). "Mens Rea". World of
34. ^ a b c Simester, A P (2021). "Distinguishing Intended from Advertent Forensic Science . Thomson/Gale. ISBN 978-1-4144-0295-6.
Action" . Fundamentals of Criminal Law. Oxford University Press. pp. 348– 97. ^ Regensburger, Derek (14 September 2022). Criminal Evidence: From
376. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198853145.003.0015 . ISBN 978-0-19-885314- Crime Scene to Courtroom . Aspen Publishing. pp. 377–8. ISBN 978-1-
5. 5438-4906-6.
35. ^ Nolfi, Kate (2015). "Which Mental States Are Rationally Evaluable, And 98. ^ Miller, J. Mitchell; Wright, Richard A. (17 December 2013). Encyclopedia of
Why?". Philosophical Issues. 25 (1): 41–63. doi:10.1111/phis.12051 . Criminology . Routledge. p. 74. ISBN 978-1-135-45543-9.
36. ^ a b c d e Audi, Robert (2001). "5.1 Desire and intention". The Architecture 99. ^ Stuchlik, Joshua (2013). "From Volitionalism to the Dual Aspect Theory of
of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality . Oxford University Action". Philosophia. 41 (3): 867–886. doi:10.1007/s11406-013-9414-9 .
Press. S2CID 144779235 .
37. ^ Audi, Robert (2003). "Précis of the Architecture of Reason". Philosophy 100. ^ Craig, Edward (1996). "Action". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
and Phenomenological Research. 67 (1): 177–180. doi:10.1111/j.1933- Routledge.
1592.2003.tb00031.x . 101. ^ Audi, Robert (1999). "action theory". The Cambridge Dictionary of
38. ^ a b Bratman, Michael (2009). "Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Philosophy . Cambridge University Press.
Rationality" . Reasons for Action. Cambridge University Press. pp. 13–36. 102. ^ Wilson, George; Shpall, Samuel; Piñeros Glasscock, Juan S. (2016).
39. ^ a b Lee, Wooram (2018). "Willing the End Means Willing the Means: An "Action" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Overlooked Reading of Kant" . Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Research Lab, Stanford University.
Philosophy. 5 (20201214). doi:10.3998/ergo.12405314.0005.016 . 103. ^ a b c Mele, Alfred R. (1996). "Rational Intentions and the Toxin Puzzle" .
40. ^ Speake, Jennifer (17 September 2015). Speake, Jennifer (ed.). "He who Proto Sociology. 8: 39–52.
WILLS the end, wills the means" . Oxford Dictionary of Proverbs. Oxford 104. ^ a b c d e f g Levy, Ken (2009). "On the Rationalist Solution to Gregory
University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780198734901.001.0001 . ISBN 978- Kavka's Toxin Puzzle" . Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 90 (2): 267–289.
0-19-873490-1. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0114.2009.01340.x . S2CID 55654286 .
41. ^ "APA Dictionary of Psychology: unconscious intention" . 105. ^ a b c Rudy-Hiller, Fernando (2019). "So Why Can'T You Intend to Drink the
dictionary.apa.org. Retrieved 11 November 2021. Toxin?" . Philosophical Explorations. 22 (3): 294–311.
42. ^ "APA Dictionary of Psychology: conscious intention" . dictionary.apa.org. doi:10.1080/13869795.2019.1656280 . S2CID 202259118 .
Retrieved 11 November 2021. 106. ^ Fishbein, M., Bandura, A., Triandis, H. C., Kanfer, F. H., Becker, M. H., &
43. ^ a b c d e Hamlyn, D. W. (1971). "Unconscious Intentions". Philosophy. 46 Middlestadt, S. E. (1992). Factors influencing behavior and behavior change
(175): 12–22. doi:10.1017/S0031819100001662 . S2CID 170742495 . (Report prepared for the National Institute of Mental Health).Bethesda, MD:
44. ^ a b Gustafson, Donald (1973). "On Unconscious Intentions". Philosophy. National Institute of Mental Health.
48 (184): 178–182. doi:10.1017/S0031819100060642 . 107. ^ a b Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes.
S2CID 251062551 . Harcourt Brace Jovanovich College Publishers
45. ^ a b c d e Siegler, Frederick A. (1967). "Unconscious Intentions". Inquiry: An 108. ^ Ajzen, I.; Fishbein, M. (1973). "Attitudinal and normative variables as
Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 10 (1–4): 251–267. predictors of specific behaviors". Journal of Personality and Social
doi:10.1080/00201746708601492 . Psychology. 27: 41–57. doi:10.1037/h0034440 .
46. ^ Gorlin, Eugenia I.; Békés, Vera (2021). "Agency via Awareness: A Unifying 109. ^ Sheppard, B. H.; Hartwick, J.; Warshaw, P. R. (1988). "The theory of
Meta-Process in Psychotherapy" . Frontiers in Psychology. 12: 2587. reasoned action: A meta-analysis of past research with recommendations for
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2021.698655 . PMC 8316855 . PMID 34335416 . modifications and future research". Journal of Consumer Research. 15 (3):
47. ^ Lumer, Christoph (2019). "Unconscious Motives and Actions – Agency, 325–343. doi:10.1086/209170 . S2CID 55744406 .
Freedom and Responsibility" . Frontiers in Psychology. 9: 2777. 110. ^ van den Putte, B. (1991). 20 years of the theory of reasoned action of
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.02777 . PMC 6393333 . PMID 30846963 . Fishbein and Ajzen: A meta-analysis. Unpublished manuscript. University of
48. ^ D’Olimpio, Francesca; Mancini, Francesco (November 2014). "Role of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, the Netherlands
Deontological Guilt in Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder–Like Checking and 111. ^ Albarracin, D.; Johnson, B. T.; Fishbein, M.; Muellerleile, P. (2001).
Washing Behaviors". Clinical Psychological Science. 2 (6): 727–739. "Theories of Reasoned Action and Planned Behavior as models of condom
doi:10.1177/2167702614529549 . S2CID 146962812 . use: A meta-analysis" . Psychological Bulletin. 127 (1): 142–161.
49. ^ a b Audi, Robert (2001). "3.6 Desires, Intentions, and Values". The doi:10.1037/0033-2909.127.1.142 . PMC 4780418 . PMID 11271752 .
Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality . 112. ^ Conner, M.; Godin, G.; Norman, P.; Sheeran, P. (2011). "Using the
Oxford University Press. question-behavior effect to promote disease prevention behaviors: two
50. ^ Audi, Robert (2001). "Notes". The Architecture of Reason: The Structure randomized controlled trials". Health Psychology. 30 (3): 300–309.
and Substance of Rationality . Oxford University Press. doi:10.1037/a0023036 . PMID 21553974 .
51. ^ Wallace, R. Jay (2020). "Practical Reason: 1. Practical and Theoretical 113. ^ Östen Dahl, Viveka Velupillai. 2013. Perfective/Imperfective Aspect. In:
Reason" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Dryer, Matthew S. & Haspelmath, Martin (eds.) The World Atlas of Language
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 November 2021. Structures Online. Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary
52. ^ Arpaly, N.; Schroeder, T. (2012). "Deliberation and Acting for Reasons". Anthropology. Retrieved from http://wals.info/chapter/65 on 2015-07-15.
Philosophical Review. 121 (2): 209–239. doi:10.1215/00318108-1539089 . 114. ^ Madden, C.J.; Zwaan, R.A. (2003). "How does verb aspect constrain event
53. ^ Feinfield, Kristin A; Lee, Patti P; Flavell, Eleanor R; Green, Frances L; representations?" . Memory & Cognition. 31 (5): 663–672.
Flavell, John H (July 1999). "Young Children's Understanding of Intention". doi:10.3758/BF03196106 . PMID 12956232 .
Cognitive Development. 14 (3): 463–486. doi:10.1016/S0885- 115. ^ Liroz, F. (2010). Web created by F. Liroz Professor in Spanish Language
2014(99)00015-5 . hdl:2027.42/150591 . Department at American School of Madrid, Spain, (date Feb. 6, 2012), http://
54. ^ Shantz, C.U. (1983). "Social cognition". In Mussen, P.H.; Flavell, J.H.; fernando.liroz.es/m/estverbo.htm
Markman, E.M. (eds.). Handbook of child psychology: Volume III. Cognitive 116. ^ Ajzen, Icek; Fishbein, Martin (2000). "Attitudes and the Attitude-Behavior
Development (4th ed.). New York: Wiley. pp. 495–555. Relation: Reasoned and Automatic Processes". European Review of Social
55. ^ Velleman, J. David; Bratman, Michael E. (April 1991). "Intention, Plans, Psychology. 11: 1–33. doi:10.1080/14792779943000116 .
and Practical Reason" (PDF). The Philosophical Review. 100 (2): 277. S2CID 144702714 .
doi:10.2307/2185304 . JSTOR 2185304 . 117. ^ Albarracin, D.; Wyer, R. S. Jr. (2000). "The cognitive impact of past
56. ^ Bloom, P. (2000). How children learn the meanings of words . behavior: influences on beliefs, attitudes, and future behavioral decisions" .
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262523295. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 79 (1): 5–22.
doi:10.1037/0022-3514.79.1.5 . PMC 4807731 . PMID 10909874 .
57. ^ Tomasello, M. (1999). "Having intentions, understanding intentions, and
understanding communicative intentions" . In Zelazo, P.D.; Astington, J.W.; 118. ^ Carrera, P.; et al. (2012). "The present projects past behavior into the
Olson, D.R. (eds.). Developing theories of intention: Social understanding future while the past projects attitudes into the future: How verb tense
and self-control. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers. moderates predictors of drinking intentions" . Journal of Experimental
pp. 63–75. Social Psychology. 48 (5): 1196–1200. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2012.04.001 .
PMC 3627212 . PMID 23606757 .
58. ^ Jenkins, J.; Greenbuam, R. (1991). "Intention and emotion in child
psychopathology: Building cooperative plans". In Zelazo, P.D.; Astington, 119. ^ a b c d e f g h Liao, S. Matthew (2012). "Intentions and Moral Permissibility:
J.W.; Olson, D.R. (eds.). Developing theories of intention: Social The Case of Acting Permissibly with Bad Intentions". Law and Philosophy.
understanding and self-control. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates 31 (6): 703–724. doi:10.1007/s10982-012-9134-5 . S2CID 144540970 .
Publishers. pp. 269–291. 120. ^ Halpern, Joseph; Kleiman-Weiner, Max (25 April 2018). "Towards Formal
59. ^ a b c d e f Blakemore, Sarah-Jayne; Decety, Jean (August 2001). "From the Definitions of Blameworthiness, Intention, and Moral Responsibility" .
perception of action to the understanding of intention". Nature Reviews Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. 32 (1).
Neuroscience. 2 (8): 561–567. doi:10.1038/35086023 . PMID 11483999 . arXiv:1810.05903 . doi:10.1609/aaai.v32i1.11557 . S2CID 8757799 .
S2CID 53690941 . 121. ^ a b c d e McIntyre, Alison (2019). "Doctrine of Double Effect" . The
60. ^ a b Lee, E.A. (1996). "Young children's representational understanding of Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
intention". Dissertation Abstracts International: Section B: The Sciences and University. Retrieved 10 November 2021.
Engineering. 56 (12–B). ProQuest 618996982 . 122. ^ Haines, William. "Consequentialism" . Internet Encyclopedia of
61. ^ a b c d e Meltzoff, A.N.; Brooks, R. (2001). " "Like me" as a building block Philosophy. Retrieved 10 November 2021.
for understanding other minds: Bodily acts, attention, and intention". In 123. ^ Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2021). "Consequentialism" . The Stanford
Malle, B.F.; Moses, L.J.; Baldwin, D.A. (eds.). Intentions and intentionality: Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
Foundations of social cognition. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. University. Retrieved 10 November 2021.
pp. 171–191. 124. ^ "utilitarianism" . Encyclopædia Britannica. 8 June 2023.
62. ^ a b c Meltzoff, A.N. (1995). "Understanding the intentions of others: Re- 125. ^ a b Johnson, Robert; Cureton, Adam (2021). "Kant's Moral Philosophy: 2.
enactment of intended acts by 18-month-old children" . Developmental Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty" . The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Psychology. 31 (5): 838–850. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.31.5.838 . Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved
PMC 4137788 . PMID 25147406 . 5 May 2021.
63. ^ a b Astington, J.W. (2001). "The paradox of intention: Assessing children's 126. ^ Altwicker, Tilmann. "6.2.2 Praktische Philosophie" . www.rwi.uzh.ch.
metarepresentational understanding" . In Malle, B.F.; Moses, L.J.; Baldwin, Retrieved 9 November 2021.
D.A. (eds.). Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of social cognition. 127. ^ Weigelin, Ernst (1917). "Legalität und Moralität". Archiv für Rechts- und
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. pp. 85–103. ISBN 9780262632676. Wirtschaftsphilosophie. 10 (4): 367–376. JSTOR 23683644 .
64. ^ Liszkowski, Ulf; Carpenter, Malinda; Tomasello, Michael (March 2007). 128. ^ Zaczyk, Rainer (2006). "Einheit des Grundes, Grund der Differenz von
"Pointing out new news, old news, and absent referents at 12 months of Moralität und Legalität". Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik / Annual Review of
age". Developmental Science. 10 (2): F1–F7. doi:10.1111/j.1467- Law and Ethics. 14: 311–321. JSTOR 43593317 .
7687.2006.00552.x . hdl:11858/00-001M-0000-0013-2510-1 . 129. ^ a b Johnson, Robert N. (1996). "Expressing a Good Will: Kant on the
PMID 17286836 . Motive of Duty". Southern Journal of Philosophy. 34 (2): 147–168.
65. ^ a b Woodward, Amanda L.; Guajardo, Jose J. (January 2002). "Infants' doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.1996.tb00783.x .
understanding of the point gesture as an object-directed action". Cognitive
Development. 17 (1): 1061–1084. doi:10.1016/S0885-2014(02)00074-6 .

External links [ edit ]

Media related to Intention at Wikimedia Commons Look up intention in


Online works of Immanuel Kant on Gutenberg Wiktionary, the free
dictionary.

Wikiquote has quotations


related to Intention.

· · Metaphysics [show]

· · Mental processes [show]

Categories: Intention Analytic philosophy Concepts in the philosophy of mind Determinism Free will Mental processes Metaphysics of mind
Thought Concepts in metaphysics

This page was last edited on 8 January 2024, at 08:36 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit
organization.

Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Contact Wikipedia Code of Conduct Developers Statistics Cookie statement Mobile view

You might also like