You are on page 1of 44

pdf version of the entry

Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics


https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/kant-metaphysics/
from the Fall 2022 Edition of the

Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy

Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman


Principal Editor Senior Editor

Colin Allen Hannah Kim Paul Oppenheimer


Associate Editor Associate Editor Associate Editor

Faculty Sponsors: R. Lanier Anderson & Thomas Icard


Editorial Board: https://plato.stanford.edu/board.html
Library of Congress ISSN: 1095-5054

Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem-


bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP
content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized
distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the
SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries,
please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ .
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
c 2022 by the publisher
Copyright
The Metaphysics Research Lab
Department of Philosophy
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305
Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics
Copyright c 2022 by the author
Michelle Grier
All rights reserved.
Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/
Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics
First published Sun Feb 29, 2004; substantive revision Wed Sep 14, 2022

How are synthetic a priori propositions possible? This question is often


times understood to frame the investigations at issue in Kant’s Critique of
Pure Reason. In answer to it, Kant saw fit to divide the question into three:
1) How are the synthetic a priori propositions of mathematics possible? 2)
How are the synthetic a priori propositions of natural science possible?
Finally, 3) How are the synthetic a priori propositions of metaphysics
possible? In systematic fashion, Kant responds to each of these questions.
The answer to question one is broadly found in the Transcendental
Aesthetic, and the doctrine of the transcendental ideality of space and
time. The answer to question two is found in the Transcendental Analytic,
where Kant seeks to demonstrate the essential role played by the
categories in grounding the possibility of knowledge and experience. The
answer to question three is found in the Transcendental Dialectic, and it is
a resoundingly blunt conclusion: the synthetic a priori propositions that
characterize metaphysics are not really possible at all. Metaphysics, that
is, is inherently dialectical. Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is thus as well
known for what it rejects as for what it defends. Thus, in the Dialectic,
Kant turns his attention to the central disciplines of traditional, rationalist,
metaphysics — rational psychology, rational cosmology, and rational
theology. Kant aims to reveal the errors that plague each of these fields.

1. Preliminary Remarks: The Rejection of Ontology (general


metaphysics) and the Transcendental Analytic
2. The Rejection of Special Metaphysics and the Transcendental
Dialectic
2.1 The Theory of Reason and Transcendental Illusion
2.2 Hypostatization and Subreption
3. The Soul and Rational Psychology

1
Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

4. The World and Rational Cosmology


4.1 The Mathematical Antinomies
4.2 The Dynamical Antinomies
5. God and Rational Theology
5.1 The Ontological Argument
5.2 The Other Proofs
6. Reason and the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic
Bibliography
Relevant Works by Kant (includes German editions and
translations):
Selected Secondary Readings on Topics in Kant’s Dialectic
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. Preliminary Remarks: The Rejection of Ontology


(general metaphysics) and the Transcendental
Analytic
Despite the fact that Kant devotes an entirely new section of the Critique
to the branches of special metaphysics, his criticisms reiterate some of the
claims already defended in both the Transcendental Aesthetic and the
Transcendental Analytic. Indeed, two central teachings from these earlier
portions of the Critique — the transcendental ideality of space and time,
and the critical limitation of all application of the concepts of the
understanding to “appearances” — already carry with them Kant’s
rejection of “ontology (metaphysica generalis).” Accordingly, in the
Transcendental Analytic Kant argues against any attempt to acquire
knowledge of “objects in general” through the formal concepts and
principles of the understanding, taken by themselves alone. In this

2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

connection, Kant denies that the principles or rules of either general logic
(e.g., the principle of contradiction), or those of his own “transcendental
logic” (the pure concepts of the understanding) by themselves yield
knowledge of objects. These claims follow from Kant’s well-known “kind
distinction” between the understanding and sensibility, together with the
view that knowledge requires the cooperation of both faculties. This
position, articulated throughout the Analytic, entails that independently of
their application to intuitions, the concepts and principles of the
understanding are mere forms of thought which cannot yield knowledge of
objects.

For if no intuition could be given corresponding to the concept, the


concept would still be a thought, so far as its form is concerned,
but would be without any object, and no knowledge of anything
would be possible by means of it. So far as I could know, there
would be nothing, and could be nothing, to which my thought
could be applied. B146

We thus find one general complaint about efforts to acquire metaphysical


knowledge: the use of formal concepts and principles, in abstraction from
the sensible conditions under which objects can be given, cannot yield
knowledge. Hence, the “transcendental” use of the understanding (its use
independently of the conditions of sensibility) is considered by Kant to be
dialectical, to involve erroneous applications of concepts in order to
acquire knowledge of things independently of sensibility/experience.
Throughout the Analytic Kant elaborates on this general view, noting that
the transcendental employment of the understanding, which aims towards
knowledge of things independently of experience (and thus knowledge of
“noumena”), is illicit (cf. A246/B303). It is in this connection that Kant
states, famously, in the Analytic, that “…the proud name of ontology,
which presumes to offer synthetic a priori cognitions of things in
general… must give way to the more modest title of a transcendental

Fall 2022 Edition 3


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

analytic” (cf. A247/B304). Filling this out, Kant suggests that to take
ourselves to have unmediated intellectual access to objects (to have “non-
sensible” knowledge) correlates with the assumption that there are non-
sensible objects that we can know. To assume this, however, is to conflate
“phenomena” (or appearances) with “noumena” (or things in themselves).
The failure to draw the distinction between appearances and things in
themselves is the hallmark of all those pernicious systems of thought that
stand under the title of “transcendental realism.” Kant’s transcendental
idealism is the remedy for these.

2. The Rejection of Special Metaphysics and the


Transcendental Dialectic
Kant’s rejection of the more specialized branches of metaphysics is
grounded in part on this earlier claim, to wit, that any attempt to apply the
concepts and principles of the understanding independently of the
conditions of sensibility (i.e., any transcendental use of the understanding)
is illicit. Thus, one of Kant’s main complaints is that metaphysicians seek
to deduce a priori synthetic knowledge simply from the unschematized
(pure) concepts of the understanding. The effort to acquire metaphysical
knowledge through concepts alone, however, is doomed to fail, according
to Kant, because (in its simplest formulation) “concepts without intuitions
are empty” (A52/B76).

Although this general charge is certainly a significant part of Kant’s


complaint, the story does not stop there. In turning to the specific
disciplines of special metaphysics (those concerning the soul, the world,
and God), Kant devotes a considerable amount of time discussing the
human interests that nevertheless pull us into the thorny questions and
controversies that characterize special metaphysics. These interests are of
two types, and include theoretical goals of achieving completeness and
systematic unity of knowledge, and practical interests in securing the

4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

immortality of the soul, freedom, and the existence of God. Despite their
contributions to metaphysical illusion, Kant tells us that the goals and
interests in question are unavoidable, inevitable, and inherent in the very
nature of human reason. In the Introduction to the Transcendental
Dialectic Kant thus introduces “reason” as the locus of these metaphysical
interests.

2.1 The Theory of Reason and Transcendental Illusion

The emphasis on reason in this connection is important, and it links up


with the project of Kant’s “critique” of pure reason. A major component of
this critique involves illuminating the basis in reason for our efforts to
draw erroneous metaphysical conclusions (to employ concepts
“transcendentally”), despite the fact that such use has already been shown
(in the Transcendental Analytic) to be illicit. What emerges in the
Dialectic is a more complex story, one in which Kant seeks to disclose and
critique the “transcendental ground” that leads to the misapplications of
thought which characterize specific metaphysical arguments. In
developing the position that our metaphysical propensities are grounded in
the “very nature of human reason,” Kant (in the Introduction to the
Dialectic) relies on a conception of reason as a capacity for syllogistic
reasoning. This logical function of reason resides in the formal activity of
subsuming propositions under ever more general principles in order to
systematize, unify, and “bring to completion” the knowledge given
through the real use of the understanding (A306/B363-A308/B365). Kant
thus characterizes this activity as one which seeks “conditions” for
everything that is conditioned. It is therefore central to this Kantian
conception of reason that it is preoccupied with the “unconditioned which
would stop the regress of conditions by providing a condition that is not
itself conditioned in its turn.”

Fall 2022 Edition 5


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

The demand for the unconditioned is essentially a demand for ultimate


explanation, and links up with the rational prescription to secure
systematic unity and completeness of knowledge. Reason, in short, is in
the business of ultimately accounting for all things. As Kant formulates
this interest of reason in the first Critique, it is characterized by the logical
maxim or precept: “Find for the conditioned knowledge given through the
understanding the unconditioned whereby its unity is brought to
completion” (A308/B364). It is central to Kant’s Dialectic that this
requirement for systematic unity and completeness of knowledge is
inherent in the very nature of our reason. Controversially, Kant does not
take it that this demand for the unconditioned is something we can
dismiss, nor does he take the interests we have in metaphysics to be
merely products of misguided enthusiasm.

Although the demand for the unconditioned is inherent in the very nature
of our reason, although it is unavoidable and indispensably necessary,
Kant nevertheless does not take it to be without problems of a unique sort;
for the very same demand that guides our rational scientific inquiries and
defines our (human) reason is also the locus of error that needs to be
curbed or prevented. In connection with this principle, then, Kant also
identifies reason as the seat of a unique kind of error, one that is essentially
linked up with metaphysical propensities, and one which he refers to as
“transcendental illusion [transzendentale Illusion].” Kant identifies
transcendental illusion with the propensity to “take a subjective necessity
of a connection of our concepts…for an objective necessity in the
determination of things in themselves” (A297/B354). Very generally,
Kant’s claim is that it is a peculiar feature of reason that it unavoidably
takes its own subjective interests and principles to hold “objectively.” And
it is this propensity, this “transcendental illusion,” according to Kant, that
paves the way for metaphysics. Reason plays this role by generating
principles and interests that incite us to defy the limitations of knowledge
already detailed in the Transcendental Analytic. The Introduction to the

6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Transcendental Dialectic is therefore interesting for Kant’s presentation of


reason as a presumably distinct capacity for cognizing in a way that, as
Kant puts it, incites us to tear down the boundaries already enforced in the
Analytic (cf. A296/B352). Kant refers to this capacity of reason as one
that leads to the specifically transcendent judgments that characterize
metaphysics. Thus, the Transcendental Dialectic is said to be concerned
“to expose the illusion in transcendent judgments” (A297/B354). Indeed,
Dialectic is defined as “the logic of illusion [Schein]” (A293/B350).

The central problem is that the above prescription to seek the


unconditioned presents to reason as a metaphysical principle that tells us
that the unconditioned is already given, and is (as it were) “there” to be
found. This problematic principle is formulated by Kant as follows: “If the
conditioned is given, the absolutely unconditioned… is also given”
(A308/B366). This “supreme principle of pure reason” provides the
background assumption under which the metaphysician proceeds. These
claims set the agenda for Kant’s project, which involves showing not
simply that the metaphysical arguments are fallacious, but also exposing
their source in reason’s more general illusions.

Kant has been traditionally taken to be offering a method of avoiding the


insidious “transcendental illusion” that gives rise to metaphysics. Read in
this way, Kant’s Dialectic offers a criticism not only of the specific
arguments of metaphysics, but also of transcendent, metaphysical
(speculative or theoretical) interests and propensities themselves. This
certainly accords with much in the Dialectic, and specifically with Kant’s
well-known claim that knowledge has to be limited to possible experience.
Kant, however, complicates things somewhat by also stating repeatedly
that the illusion that grounds metaphysics (roughly, that the unconditioned
is already given) is unavoidable. Moreover, Kant sometimes suggests that
such illusion is somehow necessary for our epistemological projects (cf.
A645/B673). In this connection, Kant argues that the transcendent ideas

Fall 2022 Edition 7


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

and principles of reason do have a positive role to play in knowledge


acquisition, so long as they are construed “regulatively” and not
“constitutively.” He thus suggests that rather than jettison the ideas of
metaphysical objects (something, it seems, he does not think we are in a
position to do), it is best to identify the proper use and function of these
ideas and principles. This critical reinterpretation involves the claim that
the ideas and principles of reason are to be used “regulatively,” as devices
for guiding and grounding our empirical investigations and the project of
knowledge acquisition. What the ideas do not do, according to Kant, is
provide the concepts through which we might access objects that could be
known through the speculative use of reason.

The need for this critical reinterpretation stems from the fact that reason’s
demand for the unconditioned cannot be met or satisfied. The absolutely
“unconditioned,” regardless of the fact that it presents to reason as
objective, is not an object or state of affairs that could be captured in any
possible human experience. In emphasizing this last point, Kant identifies
metaphysics with an effort to acquire knowledge of “objects” conceived,
but in no wise given (or giveable) to us in experience. In its efforts to
bring knowledge to completion, that is, reason posits certain ideas, the
“soul,” the “world” and “God.” Each of these ideas represents reason’s
efforts to think the unconditioned in relation to various sets of objects that
are experienced by us as conditioned.

It is this general theory of reason, as a capacity to think (by means of


“ideas”) beyond all standards of sense, and as carrying with it a unique
and unavoidable demand for the unconditioned, that frames the Kantian
rejection of metaphysics. At the heart of that rejection is the view that
although reason is unavoidably motivated to seek the unconditioned, its
theoretical efforts to achieve it are inevitably sterile. The ideas which
might secure such unconditioned knowledge lack objective reality (refer to
no object), and our misguided efforts to acquire ultimate metaphysical

8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

knowledge are led astray by the illusion which, according to Kant,


“unceasingly mocks and torments us” (A339/B397).

The Dialectic is concerned to undermine three distinct branches of special


metaphysics in the philosophical tradition: Rational Psychology, Rational
Cosmology and Rational Theology. Each of these disciplines seeks to
acquire knowledge of a particular metaphysical “object” — the “soul,” the
“world,” and “God,” respectively. This being stated, the Dialectic
proceeds systematically to undermine the arguments specific to each of
these disciplines—arguments about, for example, the nature of the soul
and the world, and the existence of God. Despite the difference in their
objects, however, there are a number of problems shared by all the
disciplines of special metaphysics. In its most general terms, the central
problem with each of these attempts has to do with the fact that the alleged
“objects” under consideration are “transcendent.” Although we think the
soul, the world, and God (necessarily) as objects, these ideas actually lack
objective reality (there is no object corresponding to the ideas that is or
could be given to us in any intuition). It is thus not uncommon to find Kant
referring to these alleged metaphysical entities as “mere thought entities,”
“fictions of the brain,” or “pseudo objects.” Although the Dialectic does
not presume to prove that such objects do not or could not exist, Kant is
committed by the strictures of his own transcendental epistemology to the
claim that the ideas of reason do not provide us with concepts of
“knowable” objects. For this reason alone, the efforts of the
metaphysicians are presumptuous, and at the very least, an
epistemological modesty precludes the knowledge that is sought.

For more on Kant’s theory of illusion, see Allison (2004), Butts (1997),
Grier (2001, forthcoming), Neiman (1994), Theis (1985), Bird (2006). See
also Ameriks (2006), Dyck (2014).

Fall 2022 Edition 9


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

2.2 Hypostatization and Subreption

There are two noteworthy themes implicit in Kant’s criticism of


metaphysics. First, Kant offers an account and critique of the ideas of
reason specific to each discipline. In relation to this, the general theory of
reason plays a role in Kant’s efforts to argue against the “hypostatization”
of each of the ideas. More specifically, Kant’s criticism of the
metaphysical disciplines centers on his efforts to show that the ideas of
reason (the soul, the world and God), which are thought in accordance
with the demand for an unconditioned that could unify the relevant
domain of conditions, get erroneously “hypostatized” by reason, or
thought as mind-independent “objects” about which we might seek
knowledge. In the same way, that is, that the prescription to seek the
unconditioned appears to reason as an objective principle, so too, the
subjective ideas appear to reason as objects existing in a mind-independent
way. Kant’s aim is to secure the subjective ideas while enforcing their
subjective status, and thereby defusing the metaphysics that attends to
them.

Thus, Kant’s criticism of metaphysics simultaneously involves denying


the pure use of theoretical reason as an instrument for knowledge of
transcendent objects, and defending reason’s ideas as projections or goals
that have some significant role to play in the overall project of knowledge
acquisition. As we shall see, Kant unfortunately is not as clear as we might
like on this issue. Sometimes, he seems to argue that the ideas and
principles of reason play a merely heuristic role in guiding and
systematizing the knowledge already obtained. Other times, he suggests
that these ideas are deeply essential to the project of knowledge
acquisition, and that their presupposition is utterly necessary if we are to
acquire knowledge. Regardless of how the matter is to be resolved, it is
clear that Kant’s criticism of metaphysics does not entail any
straightforward rejection of the ideas and principles of reason. Indeed, it

10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

appears to be precisely the rational constraint to move to the ideas of


reason that binds us to our metaphysical propensities and which thus
demands a critique of the kind offered by Kant.

In addition to criticizing the “hypostatization” of the ideas of reason, Kant


seeks to expose the “subreptions” involved in the use of the ideas. The
term “subreption” refers to a fallacy that specifically involves the
surreptitious substitution of different kinds of terms and concepts. Kant
usually uses the term to refer to the error of confusing or substituting
concepts and principles meant for use in experience (those which properly
apply to appearances) with principles of “pure reason.” By this means, a
concept or principle which is a condition of our experience (e.g., the
principle of apperception) is used in a way that assumes its applications to
“objects in general” or things in themselves. Alternatively, a most general,
formal, principle that would only hold for things in general is taken, by
itself alone, to yield knowledge about appearances. This second kind of
criticism found throughout the Dialectic thus pertains to Kant’s efforts to
expose the subreptions that ground the illusory metaphysical arguments.
Ultimately, Kant will also seek to reveal the very specific formal fallacies
that vitiate the metaphysical arguments, to demonstrate that (although they
have the appearance of soundness) the positions in each case are implicitly
grounded in, or deploy, dialectical uses of terms and concepts,
misapplications of principles, and conflations of appearances with things
in themselves. What we find in Kant’s criticism of metaphysics, in other
words, is a complex account, one grounded in a fairly robust theory of
human reason. Accordingly, he identifies reason as the locus of certain
principles and propensities, and certain “illusions,” which cooperate with
misapplications of concepts and principles to create the errors already
exposed in the Transcendental Analytic. Although this variety of aims and
complaints certainly complicates Kant’s discussions in the Dialectic, it
also makes for a richer and more penetrating criticism of metaphysics.

Fall 2022 Edition 11


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

3. The Soul and Rational Psychology


One historically predominant metaphysical interest has to do with
identifying the nature and the constitution of the soul. Partly for practical
reasons, partly for theoretical explanation, reason forms the idea of a
metaphysically simple being, the soul. Such an idea is motivated by
reason’s demand for the unconditioned. Kant puts this point in a number
of ways, suggesting that the idea of the soul is one to which we are led
necessarily insofar as we are constrained by reason to seek the “totality” of
the “synthesis of conditions of a thought in general” (A397), or insofar as
we seek to represent “the unconditioned unity” of “subjective conditions
of representations in general” (A406/B433). More straightforwardly, Kant
states that a metaphysics of the soul is generated by the demand for the
“absolute (unconditioned) unity of the thinking subject itself”
(A334/B391). The branch of metaphysics devoted to this topic is Rational
Psychology. Rational psychologists, among whom Descartes or Leibniz
would serve as apt historical examples, seek to demonstrate, for example,
the substantiality, simplicity, and personal identity of the soul. Each such
inference, however, involves concluding “from the transcendental concept
of the subject, which contains nothing manifold, the absolute unity of this
subject itself, of which I possess no concept whatsoever” (A340/B398). In
other words, Kant takes the rational psychologist to slide (mistakenly)
from formal features of our self concept to material or substantive
metaphysical claims about an alleged (super-sensible) object (the soul).

An essential aspect of all these arguments, according to Kant, is their


attempt to derive conclusions about the nature and constitution of the
“soul” a priori, simply from an analysis of the activity of thinking. A
classic example of such an attempt is provided by Descartes, who deduced
the substantiality of the self from the proposition (or, perhaps better, the
activity) “I think.” This move is apparent in the Cartesian inference from
“I think” to the claim that the “I” is therefore “a thing” that thinks. For

12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Descartes, this move is unproblematic: thought is an attribute, and thus


presupposes a substance in which it inheres. Kant emphasizes the a priori
basis for the metaphysical doctrine of the soul by claiming that in rational
psychology, the “I think” is supposed to provide the “sole text” (A343–
4/B401–02). It is this feature of the discipline that serves to distinguish it
from any empirical doctrine of the self (any empirical psychology), and
which secures its status as a “metaphysics” that purports to provide
synthetic a priori knowledge.

Kant’s criticisms of rational psychology draw on a number of distinct


sources, one of which is the Kantian doctrine of apperception, or
transcendental self-consciousness (often formulated in terms of the
necessary possibility of attaching the “I think” to all my representations
(B132)). Kant denies that the metaphysician is entitled to his substantive
conclusions on the grounds that the activity of self-consciousness does not
yield any object for thought. Nevertheless, reason is guided by its
projecting and objectifying propensities. In accordance with these, self-
consciousness is “hypostatized,” or objectified. Here again, Kant claims
that a “natural illusion” compels us to take the apperceived unity of
consciousness as an intuition of an object (A402). The ineliminably
subjective nature of self-consciousness, and the elusiveness of the “I” in
the context of that activity, are thus the well known bases for Kant’s
response to rational psychology, and the doctrine of apperception plays an
important role in Kant’s rejection. For in each case, Kant thinks that a
feature of self-consciousness (the essentially subjectival, unitary and
identical nature of the “I” of apperception) gets transmuted into a
metaphysics of a self (as an object) that is ostensibly “known” through
reason alone to be substantial, simple, identical, etc. This slide from the
“I” of apperception to the constitution of an object (the soul) has received
considerable attention in the secondary literature, and has fueled a great
deal of attention to the Kantian theory of mind and mental activity.

Fall 2022 Edition 13


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

The claim that the ‘I’ of apperception yields no object of knowledge (for it
is not itself an object, but only the “vehicle” for any representation of
objectivity as such) is fundamental to Kant’s critique of rational
psychology. Kant thus spends a considerable amount of time arguing that
no object is given in transcendental self-consciousness, and thus that the
rational psychologist’s efforts to discern features of the self, construed as a
metaphysical entity, through reason alone are without merit. To elucidate
the ways in which the rational psychologist is nevertheless seduced into
making this slide from formal representations of self consciousness to a
metaphysics of the self, Kant examines each of the psychological
arguments, maintaining that all such arguments about the soul are
dialectical. He refers to the arguments designed to draw such conclusions,
“transcendental paralogisms”, and hence the chapter of the Critique that
criticizes rational psychology goes by the name “The Paralogisms of Pure
Reason.” A transcendental paralogism, according to Kant, is a “syllogism
in which one is constrained, by a transcendental ground, to draw a
formally invalid conclusion” (A341/B399). Kant’s subsequent efforts are
thus directed towards demonstrating the paralogistic (fallacious) nature of
the arguments about the soul.

Kant’s diagnosis of the fallacies has received considerable attention, and


has generated considerable controversy. In each case, Kant tells us, the
argument is guilty of the fallacy of sophisma figurae dictionis, or the
fallacy of equivocation/ambiguous middle. Kant suggests that in each of
the syllogisms, a term is used in different senses in the major and minor
premises. Consider the first paralogism, the argument that allegedly
deduces the substantiality of the soul. In the A edition, Kant formulates the
argument as follows:

That the representation of which is the absolute subject of our


judgments and cannot be employed as determination of any other
thing, is substance.

14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

I, as thinking being, am the absolute subject of all my possible


judgments and this representation of myself cannot be employed as
determination of any other thing.

Therefore, I, as thinking being (soul), am substance. (A349)

Kant locates the equivocation contained in the argument in the use of the
term “substance.” According to Kant, the major premise uses this term
“transcendentally” whereas the minor premise and conclusion use the
same term “empirically.” (A403). What Kant appears to mean is this: the
major premise deploys the term “substance” in a very general way, one
which abstracts from the conditions of our sensible intuition (space and
time). As such, the major premise simply offers the most general
definition of substance, and thus expresses the most general rule in
accordance with which objects might be able to be thought as substances.
Nevertheless, in order to apply the concept of substance in such a way as
to determine an object, the category would have to be used empirically.
Unfortunately, such an empirical use is precluded by the fact that the
alleged object to which it is being applied is not empirical. Even more
problematically, on Kant’s view, there is no object given at all. In Kantian
jargon, the category only yields knowledge of objects if it is
“schematized,” applied to given objects under the conditions of time.

This same kind of complaint is lodged against each of the paralogistic


syllogisms that characterize Rational Psychology. Thus, Kant argues
against the inference to the simplicity of the soul, by remarking that the
psychologist surreptitiously deduces the actual simplicity of a
metaphysical object simply from the formal features of subjectivity (the
fact that the “I” is unitary in our representational economy). The personal
identity of the soul is attacked on similar grounds. In each case the
metaphysical conclusion is said to be drawn only by an equivocation in the
use or meaning of a concept of the understanding.

Fall 2022 Edition 15


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

This illustrates Kant’s efforts to demonstrate the fallacious nature of the


arguments that characterize metaphysics, as well as his interest in
identifying the sources of such errors. Given this, Kant’s criticisms of
rational psychology are not as straightforward as one might expect, for
embedded in his criticisms of rational psychology are actually a number of
distinct charges: 1) The idea of the soul, although it is one to which we are
naturally led in our quest for the unconditioned ground of thought, does
not correspond to any object that is (or could be) actually given to us in
intuition. The hypostatization of this idea, therefore, although it may be
natural, is deeply problematic. 2) Because the idea of the soul does not
yield, by itself alone, any knowable object, the arguments about it,
although they may have the appearance of being legitimate, in fact involve
dialectical applications of concepts. The arguments, in other words,
involve fallacies that vitiate their conclusions. 3) The arguments are
traceable back to certain features of human reason that may not be
eradicated, but that can and ought to be curbed and critically reinterpreted.
More specifically, the demand for the unconditioned, and the idea of the
soul to which it gives rise, may be construed regulatively as devices for
guiding inquiries, but never constitutively — never, that is, as yielding
grounds for any a priori synthetic knowledge of a metaphysical self given
immediately to pure reason.

Kant’s Paralogisms have received considerable and focused attention in


the secondary literature. See Ameriks (1992), Brook (1994), Kitcher,
Patricia (1990), Powell (1990), Sellars (1969, 1971), Wolff, R. P. (1963).
There are also excellent discussions to be found in Allison (1983, 2004),
Bennett (1974), Buroker (2006), Grier (2001, forthcoming), Guyer (1987),
Wuerth (2010, 2021) (2010), Bird (2006), Ameriks (2006), Melnick
(2006), Dyck (2014), Proops (2010), Willaschek (2018)

16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

4. The World and Rational Cosmology


The second discipline of rationalist metaphysics rejected by Kant is
Rational Cosmology. Rational cosmology is concerned with the arguments
about the nature and constitution of the “world,” understood as the sum-
total of all appearances (objects and events in space and time)
(A420/B448). The arguments about the world occupy an especially
important place in Kant’s rejection of metaphysics. Not only does Kant
address himself to the task of discounting the metaphysical arguments in
cosmology, but the resolution to some of these conflicts provides, he
claims, an indirect argument for his own transcendental idealism.

The arguments about the world are referred to by Kant as “antinomies”


because in the field of cosmology, reason gives rise to sets of opposing
arguments (the “thesis” and the “antithesis”) with respect to each issue.
Thus, the case here differs from the paralogisms (and, as we shall see,
from the Ideal). The reason for this difference resides in the nature of the
idea of reason in question. The idea of the “world” purports to be an idea
of an unconditioned but somehow still sensible object (cf. A479/B509).
Unlike the soul and God, which are clearly supposed to be non-sensible
metaphysical entities, the sum total of all appearances refers specifically to
spatio-temporal objects or events. Kant highlights this unique feature of
the idea of the world by noting that whereas the ideas of the soul and God
are “pseudo-rational,” the idea of the world is “pseudo-empirical.” It is
precisely this feature of the idea (that it both purports to refer to a
somehow sensible object AND that it involves thinking that object as
already given in its unconditioned totality) that leads to the two opposed
sets of arguments. For with respect to each problem addressed (the finitude
vs. the infinitude of the world, freedom vs. causality, etc.), one can either
adopt a broadly “dogmatic” (Platonic) or broadly “empiricist” (Epicurean)
approach, each reflecting a different way of thinking the totality of
conditions (See A471–2/B499–500). More specifically, one can either

Fall 2022 Edition 17


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

think the unconditioned as an intelligible ground of appearances, or as the


total (even if infinite) set of all appearances. Unfortunately, each of these
conceptual strategies is unsatisfying. To accommodate the thesis interest in
ultimate (intelligible) beginnings is to posit something “too big” for the
understanding, something that is never to be met with empirically (e.g.,
freedom, ultimately simple substances). Thus, although the thesis
positions satisfy reason’s demand for the unconditioned, they do so by
fleeing (however unwittingly) into an intelligible realm, by providing
explanations that abstract from that which is or could be given in any
spatio-temporal experience. But adopting the empiricist approach is no
more rewarding, in the final analysis; although the antithesis positions
remain securely lodged within “nature’s own resources,” they can never
measure up to the demands of reason’s ideas. Such a strategy is “too
small” for reason which, even despite its capacity to think beyond all
standards of sense and by its demand for more thorough explanation.
Worse, the antithesis arguments, in refusing to go beyond the spatio-
temporal realm, end up being just as dogmatic as their opposites, for the
assumption is that whatever holds within space and time also holds
generally. To assume this is to take what are for Kant merely subjective
features of our intuition (forms of sensibility, space and time) to be
universal ontological conditions holding of everything whatsoever.

Because both sides to the cosmological disputes seem to be able to argue


successfully against the opposite, Kant finds in the antinomies a dramatic
exhibition of the “conflict” into which reason inevitably falls (and in
which it will remain) so long as it fails to adopt his own transcendental
distinction between appearances and things in themselves. The historical
debacle of reason’s conflict with itself provides Kant with a dramatic
exhibition of the vacillation of reason between two alternatives, neither of
which it can accept (or dismiss) without dissatisfaction. Left unresolved,
this conflict leads to the “euthanasia of pure reason” (A407/B434), in the
sense of provoking skeptical despair.

18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

4.1 The Mathematical Antinomies

There are four “antinomies” of pure reason, and Kant divides them into
two classes. The first two antinomies are dubbed “mathematical”
antinomies, presumably because in each case, we are concerned with the
relation between what are alleged to be sensible objects (either the world
itself, or objects in it) and space and time. An important and fundamental
aspect of Kant’s rejection of each of these sets of arguments rests on his
view that each of these conflicts is traceable back to a fundamental error,
an error that can be discerned, according to Kant, in the following
dialectical syllogism:

If the conditioned is given, then the whole series of conditions, a


series which is therefore itself absolutely unconditioned, is also
given

Objects of the senses are given as conditioned

Consequently, the entire series of all conditions of objects of the


senses is already given. (cf. A497/B525).

There are a number of problems with this argument, according to Kant.


Obviously, one problem is located in the major premise, in the assumption
that the unconditioned is “already given.” The problem, maintains Kant, is
that such a totality is never to be met with in experience. The rational
assumption that the total series of all conditions is already given would
hold only for things in themselves. In the realm of appearances, the totality
is never given to us, as finite discursive knowers. The most we are entitled
to say, with respect to appearances, is that the unconditioned is set as a
task, that there is a rational prescription to continue to seek explanations
(A498/B526-A500/B528). As finite (sensible) cognizers, however, we
shall never achieve an absolute completion of knowledge. To assume that

Fall 2022 Edition 19


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

we can do so is to adopt the theocentric model of knowledge characteristic


of the dreaded transcendental realist.

This hypostatization of the idea of the world, the fact that it is taken to be
a mind-independent object, acts as the underlying assumption motivating
both parties to the two mathematical antinomies. The first antinomy
concerns the finitude or infinitude of the spatio-temporal world. The thesis
argument seeks to show that the world in space and time is finite, i.e., has
a beginning in time and a limit in space. The antithesis counters that it is
infinite with regard to both space and time. The second antinomy concerns
the ultimate constitution of objects in the world, with the thesis arguing for
ultimately simple substances, whereas the antithesis argues that objects are
infinitely divisible. In this, the thesis positions are each concerned to bring
the explanatory effort to a close, by arguing for ultimate or, as Kant says,
“intelligible beginnings” (cf. A466/B494). The claim that there is a “first
beginning” or an ultimately simple substance is sustained only by
abstracting from the spatio-temporal framework. The alleged proponent of
the antithesis arguments, on the other hand, refuses any conclusion that
goes beyond the sensible conditions of space and time. According to the
antithesis arguments, the world is infinite in both space and time (these
being infinite as well), and bodies are (in accordance with the infinite
divisibility of space) also infinitely divisible.

In each of these antinomial conflicts, reason finds itself at an impasse.


Satisfying the demands placed by our rational capacity to think beyond
experience, the thesis arguments offer what appears to be a satisfying
resting-place for explanation. The antithesis charges that such a strategy
fails to find any confirmation, and, citing the unjustified flight into an
intelligible realm, lodges itself squarely in the domain of “experience.” In
each of these cases, the conflicts are resolved by demonstrating that the
conclusions drawn on both sides are false.

20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

How does Kant demonstrate this? Both the thesis and antithesis arguments
are apagogic, i.e., that they constitute indirect proofs. An indirect proof
establishes its conclusion by showing the impossibility of its opposite.
Thus, for example, we may want to know, as in the first antinomy, whether
the world is finite or infinite. We can seek to show that it is finite by
demonstrating the impossibility of its infinitude. Alternatively, we may
demonstrate the infinitude of the world by showing that it is impossible
that it is finite. This is exactly what the thesis and antithesis arguments
purport to do, respectively. The same strategy is deployed in the second
antinomy, where the proponent of the thesis position argues for the
necessity of some ultimately simple substance by showing the
impossibility of infinite divisibility of substance, etc.

Obviously, the success of the proofs depends on the legitimacy of the


exclusive disjunction agreed to by both parties. Both parties, that is,
assume that “there is a world,” and that it is, for example, “either finite or
infinite.” Herein lies the problem, according to Kant. The world is, for
Kant, neither finite nor infinite. The opposition between these two
alternatives is merely dialectical. In the cosmological debates, each party
to the dispute falls prey to the ambiguity in the idea of the world.

Kant thus structures his analysis of the mathematical antinomies by


appealing to the general dialectical syllogism presented at the end of
section 4.0 (If the conditioned is given, the unconditioned is given,
Objects of the senses are given as conditioned....etc.). Problems stem from
the application of the principle expressed in the first premise to the objects
of the senses (appearances). Here again, Kant diagnoses the error or
fallacy contained in this syllogism as that of ambiguous middle. He claims
that the major premise uses the term “the conditioned” transcendentally, as
a pure concept, whereas the minor premise uses the term ‘empirically’ –
that is as a “concept of the understanding applied to mere appearances”
(cf. A499–500/B527–528). What Kant means is that the major premise

Fall 2022 Edition 21


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

uses the term “the conditioned” in a very general way, one that considers
things in abstraction from the sensible conditions of our intuition. The
minor premise, however, which specifically refers to objects in space and
time (appearances), is committed to an empirical use of the term. Indeed,
such an empirical use would have to be deployed, if the conclusion is to be
reached. The conclusion is that the entire series of all conditions of
appearances is actually given. Put in other terms, the conclusion is that
there is a world, understood as the sum total of all appearances and their
conditions (A420/B448).

4.2 The Dynamical Antinomies


In the dynamical antinomies, Kant changes his strategy somewhat. Rather
than arguing (as in the mathematical antinomies) that both conclusions are
false, Kant suggests that both sides to the dispute might turn out to be
correct. This option is available here, and not in the two mathematical
antinomies, because the proponents of the thesis arguments are not
committing themselves solely to claims about spatio-temporal objects. In
the third antinomy, the thesis contends that in addition to mechanistic
causality, we must posit some first uncaused causal power (Transcendental
Freedom), while the antithesis denies anything but mechanistic causality.
Here, then, the debate is the standard (though in this case, the specifically
cosmological) dispute between freedom and determinism. Finally, in the
fourth antinomy, the requirement for a necessary being is pitted against its
opposite. The thesis position argues for a necessary being, whereas the
antithesis denies that there is any such being.

In both cases the thesis opts for a position that is abstracted from the
spatio-temporal framework, and thus adopts the broadly Platonic view.
The postulation of freedom amounts to the postulation of a non-temporal
cause, a causality outside the series of appearances in space and time
(A451/B479). Similarly, in its efforts to argue for a “necessary being,”

22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

reason is forced (against its own argument) into a non-sensible realm. If


there is a necessary being, it will have to be “outside” the series of
appearances: “Either, therefore, reason through its demand for the
unconditioned must remain in conflict with itself, or this unconditioned
must be posited outside the series, in the intelligible” (A564/B592). The
rational necessity of postulating such a necessary being or a causality of
freedom satisfies the rational demand for intelligible explanation. Against
this, the antithesis rightly notes that the conception of transcendental
freedom, or a necessary being, again represents an attempt to abstract from
“nature’s own resources” (A451–2/B479–80). Insofar as the antithesis
denies the justification for doing this, of course, it is said to adopt a
broadly Epicurean standpoint. The problem here, however, is that in
refusing to move beyond “nature’s own resources,” the antithesis
surreptitiously smuggles in spatio-temporal conditions as the basis for a
universal ontological claim that nevertheless transcends all experience. If
space and time were things in themselves, then of course the application of
the demand for this unconditioned would be warranted. Kant’s view,
however, is that space and time are not conditions of things in themselves.

The resolution to these antinomies here consists in giving each side its
due, but simultaneously limiting the domain over which the claims hold.
The thesis demand for an absolute causal beginning or a necessary being
might well be allowed to stand, but certainly not as “part of” or as an
explication of appearances in nature. Similarly, the antithesis conclusions
can stand, but only in relation to objects in nature, considered as
appearances. Here, the conflict seems irresolvable only on the assumption
that appearances are things in themselves. If appearances were things in
themselves, for example, then it would certainly seem true that either they
are one and all subject to mechanistic causality, or not. In such a case, it
makes sense both to argue for a non-temporal beginning and to deny such
a beginning. Left unresolved, then, this antinomy leaves us wit the
following dilemma: on the assumption of transcendental realism, both

Fall 2022 Edition 23


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

nature and freedom seem to be undermined. To avoid this, Kant appeals to


transcendental idealism, which is supposed to rescue reason from the
conflict. Given transcendental idealism (with its distinction between
appearances and things in themselves) it remains possible that in addition
to the mechanism of nature, or contingent existence, there is an intelligible
causal power, or a necessary being.

Detailed discussions of Kant’s antinomies can be found in Al-Azm (1972),


Bennett, (1974), Grier (2001, 2006, forthcoming), Guyer (1987),
Heimsoeth (1967), Strawson (1966), Thiel (2006), Watkins (1998, 2000),
Van Cleve (1984). See also Allison (1983), and Walsh (1975). See also
Bird (2006), Wood (2010), Wuerth (2021), Willaschek (2018).

5. God and Rational Theology


The metaphysical drive, and the demand for the unconditioned, seem to
find their natural resting place in the idea of God, an absolutely necessary
and supremely real being, the concept of which “contains a therefore for
every wherefore” (A585/B613). It is here, in the concept of God, that the
demands for systematic unity and completeness of knowledge find their
“objective correlate.” Kant refers to this idea as an Ideal, suggesting it
defines itself as a “concept of an individual object which is completely
determined through the mere idea” (A574/B602). The Ideal represents the
highest singular manifestation of reason’s demand for the unconditioned.

The last area of metaphysics under attack, then, is Rational Theology.


Kant’s criticism of rational theology is complicated by his desire to
elucidate the sources of the dialectical errors, which he will expose in
relation to the specific arguments for God’s existence. (“…Merely to
describe the procedure of our reason and its dialectic does not suffice; we
must also endeavor to discover the sources of this dialectic, that we may
explain…the illusion to which it has given rise” (A581/B607).) Kant thus

24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

spends a considerable amount of time tracing the idea of God back to its
rational, speculative, sources. According to Kant, “….the Ideal …is based
on a natural, not a merely arbitrary idea” (A581/B607). On this score,
Kant wants to tell us that we are compelled to think the idea of God (the
ens realissimum) when pursuing certain speculative or philosophical
interests. More specifically, the idea of a supremely real being (the ens
realissimum) is one to which we are inevitably led during our attempts to
account for the pure possibility of things in general. The upshot that the
idea of the ens realissimum is not an arbitrary or easily dispensable one.
Instead, Kant suggests that reason is philosophically constrained to move
to such an idea in its efforts to thoroughly determine every thing. Such
efforts require thinking the totality, or “All” of reality (the omnitudo
realitatis). Such an idea is philosophically required because, in our efforts
to thoroughly determine each thing (to know it completely, specify it
exhaustively), we must be able to say, of every possible predicate and its
contradictory (p v ˜p) which of the two holds of the thing in question. (For
every object, it is either A or not A, either B or not B, etc., and this process
is iterated until each predicate pair (each positive reality) is exhausted —
Kant clearly has a Leibnizian procedure of complete determination in
mind here.) This process is parasitic upon the idea of “sum total of all
predicates of things in general.” Or, put in another way, we represent
“every thing as deriving its own possibility from the share it has in the
whole of possibility” (A572/B600). Such an idea, the All of reality,
however, defines itself as an individual thing, and leads us to the
representation of the “supremely real being.” The problem seems to come
in, according to Kant, when the “All” of reality gets hypostatized, and
(eventually) personified, thus yielding the ens realissimum (cf.
A583/B611n). Here again, Kant thinks that this idea itself gets transmuted
into the notion of a given object by virtue of a unique subreption, whereby
we dialectically substitute for a principle that is only meant for empirical
employment one which holds of things in general. The argument Kant

Fall 2022 Edition 25


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

offers is excruciating, but the essential point is that, just as the idea of the
soul involved the subreption of the hypostatized consciousness, so too, the
idea of the ens realissimum is generated by both a subrepted principle and
a hypostatization.

As in the cases of both rational psychology and rational cosmology, then,


one central problem thus has to do with the assumption that pure
(speculative) reason yields any access to a transcendent object (in this
case, God) about which it is entitled to seek a priori knowledge. Despite
his insistence that the idea of God is indispensable and “inescapable” (cf.
A584/B612), Kant again denies that we can acquire any theoretical
knowledge of the alleged “object” thought through such an idea. On the
one hand, then, the idea of God is “the crown of our endeavors.” On the
other, as in the cases of both rational psychology and cosmology, the idea
answers to no given and theoretically knowable object (A339/B397).
Indeed, according to Kant, the idea of God should not lead us to
“presuppose the existence of a being that corresponds to this ideal, but
only the idea of such a being, and this only for the purpose of deriving
from an unconditioned totality of complete determination the conditioned
totality. i.e., the limited…” (A578/B606). As in the other disciplines of
metaphysics, Kant suggests that we are motivated (perhaps even
constrained) to represent the idea as a real object, to hypostatize it, in
accordance the demand for the unconditioned:

Notwithstanding this pressing need of reason to presuppose


something that may afford the understanding a sufficient
foundation for the complete determination of its concepts, it is yet
too easily conscious of the ideal and merely fictitious character of
such a presuppostion to allow itself, on this ground alone, to be
persuaded that a mere creature of its own thought is a real being —
were it not that it is impelled from another direction to seek a
resting place in the regress from the conditioned, which is given, to

26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

the unconditioned (A584/B612)

This demand for the unconditioned, according to Kant, links up with a


demand for some ultimately necessary being. Reason, that is, ceaselessly
demands the ground of all the contingent beings in existence, and will not
rest until it settles on the absolutely necessary being which grounds them.
The idea of the ens realissimum plays a singular role in satisfying this
desire of reason, for of all concepts, it is that “which best squares with the
concept of an unconditionally necessary being” (A586/B614). In fact,
according to Kant rational theology is based on the coincidence of the
rational demands for a supremely real being and for a being with
absolutely necessary existence. If the movement to the idea of God, as the
unconditioned ground, is inevitable, it is nevertheless as troublesome as
the other rational ideas:

This unconditioned is not, indeed, given as being in itself real, nor


as having a reality that follows from its mere concept; it is,
however, what alone can complete the series of conditions when
we proceed to trace these conditions to their grounds. This is the
course which our human reason, by its very nature, leads all of us
(A584/B612; cf. A584/B612n).

Thus, although Kant is most well known for his attacks on the specific
arguments for God’s existence, his criticisms of rational theology are in
fact more detailed, and involve a robust critique of the idea of God itself.
This account of the rational origin and the importance of the idea of God
clears the way for Kant’s rejection of the metaphysical arguments about
God’s existence. Kant identifies three traditional arguments, the
ontological, the cosmological, and the physico-theological (the argument
from design). What all such arguments do is attempt to wed the idea of the
ens realissimum with the notion of necessary existence. Whereas the
Ontological argument moves from the concept of the ens realissimum to

Fall 2022 Edition 27


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

the claim that such a being exists necessarily, the Cosmological and
physico-theological arguments move from some necessary being to the
conclusion that such a being must be the ens realissimum.

5.1 The Ontological Argument

Kant’s formulation of the ontological argument is fairly straightforward,


and may be summarized as follows:

1. God, the ens realissimum, is the concept of a being that contains all
reality/predicates.
2. Existence is a reality/predicate.
3. Therefore God exists.

Kant’s identification of the errors involved in this argument are so varied


that it seems surprising that he is so often simply said to have argued
against the use of “existence” as a predicate. His first complaint is that it is
“contradictory” insofar as it introduces “existence” into the “concept of a
thing which we profess to be thinking solely in reference to its possibility”
(A597/B625). This suggests that he thinks that in taking “all reality” to
mean or include “existence,” the rational theologist begs the question, and
already posits the analytic connection between the concept of the ens
realissimum and necessary existence.

At the heart of this complaint is a more general one, to wit, that there is a
problem with the attempt to infer anything as necessarily existing.
Although, according to Kant, reason is unavoidably led to the notion of an
absolutely necessary being, the understanding is in no position to identify
any candidate answering to the idea. (cf. A592/B620). Clearly, the
ontological argument is designed to show that, in fact, there is one (and
only one) candidate answering to this idea, namely, the ens realissimum.
But it does so by deducing the necessary existence from the concept of the

28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

ens realissimum (a being that contains all reality or predicates) only via
the minor premise that “existence” is a predicate or reality. Kant, however,
famously denies that existence is a “real predicate,” or determination.
Thus, one criticism is that the argument conflates merely logical with real
(determining) predicates. A real (determining) predicate is one that
enlarges the concept to which it is attached. It seems clear that the locus of
the error here, as in the other metaphysical disciplines, is the view that the
idea of the ens realissimum provides us with a concept of an “object” to
which it would be appropriate to apply categories or concepts in a
determining way. Thus, included in Kant’s criticism is the claim that the
category of existence is being subject to a transcendental misemployment
(A598/B626). This misapplication of the category is problematic precisely
because, according to Kant, we are dealing only with an object of pure
thought, whose existence cannot be known (A602/B630).

5.2 The Other Proofs

If the ontological argument seeks to move from the concept of the ens
realissimum to the concept of an absolutely necessary being, both the
cosmological and physicotheological proofs move in the opposite
direction. Each, that is, argues that there is something that must exist with
absolute necessity and concludes that this being is the ens realissimum.
Because these proofs aim to identify the ens realissimum with the
necessary being, and because the attempt to do this requires an a priori
argument (it cannot be demonstrated empirically), Kant thinks that they
are both (ultimately) vitiated by their reliance on the ontological proof.
More specifically, they are both mitigated by their assumption that the ens
realissimum is the only object or candidate that can do the job of existing
necessarily. Since he thinks that the ontological argument is in some sense
implicitly relied upon in making such a claim, these arguments stand or
fall with it. On Kant’s view, as we shall see, they fall.

Fall 2022 Edition 29


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

The cosmological proof has, according to Kant, two parts. As above, the
proponent of the argument first seeks to demonstrate the existence of an
absolutely necessary being. Second, the rational cosmologist seeks to
show that this absolutely necessary being is the ens realissimum.

As Kant formulates it, the cosmological argument is as follows:

If something exists, then an absolutely necessary being must also


exist.

I myself, at least, exist.

Therefore an absolutely necessary being exists.

As above, the theist will ultimately want to identify this necessary being
with the ens realissimum, an identification which Kant thinks
surreptitiously smuggles in the (dialectical) ontological argument. The
claim here is that the proponent of the cosmological argument is
committed ultimately to accepting the ontological argument, given her
attempt to identify the necessary being with the ens realissimum. Although
this suggests that the cosmological argument relies on the ontological,
Kant also indicates that the effort to produce a purely a priori argument
for God’s existence (the ontological argument) itself gets momentum from
reason’s need to find the necessary ground for existence in general, a need
expressed in the cosmological argument (cf. A603–04/B631–32). This
suggests that Kant takes the ontological and cosmological arguments to be
complementary expressions of the one underlying rational demand for the
unconditioned.

Even aside from its alleged commitment to the ontological argument, Kant
has a number of complaints about the cosmological argument. Indeed,
according to Kant, the cosmological argument is characterized by an
“entire nest of dialectical presumptions” which must be illuminated and

30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

“destroyed” (A609/B637). These dialectical presumptions include the


attempt to infer from the contingent (within experience) to some cause
lying outside the world of sense altogether, an effort involving a
transcendental misapplication of the categories. It also includes, Kant
claims, the dialectical effort to infer from the conceptual impossibility of
an infinite series of causes to some actual first cause outside of sense.
Such efforts involve a “false self-satisfaction” according to which reason
feels itself to have finally landed on a truly necessary being.
Unfortunately, according to Kant, this is only achieved by conflating the
merely logical possibility of a concept (that it is not self-contradictory)
with the transcendental (real) possibility of a thing. In short, the
cosmological argument gets its momentum by confusing rational or
subjective necessities with real or objective ones, and thus involves
transcendental illusion (cf. A605/B633).

We come finally to the physicotheological proof, which argues from the


particular constitution of the world, specifically its beauty, order, and
purposiveness, to the necessary existence of an intelligent cause (God).
Such an argument goes beyond the cosmological one by moving not from
existence in general but from some determinate experience in order to
demonstrate the existence of God (A621/B649). Although this might seem
to be a strength, this strategy is doomed to fail, according to Kant. No
experience could ever be adequate to the idea of a necessary, original
being: “The transcendental idea of a necessary all-sufficient original being
is so overwhelmingly great, so sublimely high above everything empirical,
which is at all times conditioned, that partly one can never even procure
enough material in experience to fill such a concept, and partly if one
searches for the unconditioned among conditioned things, then one will
seek forever and always in vain” (A621/B649).

Kant’s claim is that even if we could grant that the order and
purposiveness of nature gives us good reason to suppose some intelligent

Fall 2022 Edition 31


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

designer, it does not warrant the inference to an ens realissimum. At most,


Kant tells us, the proof could establish a “highest architect of the world….,
but not a creator of the world.” (A627/B655). The last inference, that to
the ens realissimum, is only drawn by moving far away from any
consideration of the actual (empirical) world. In other words, here too,
Kant thinks that the rational theologist is relying on a transcendental (a
priori) argument. Indeed, according to Kant, the physicotheological proof
could never, given its empirical starting point, establish the existence of a
highest being by itself alone, and must rely on the ontological argument at
crucial stages (cf. A625/B653). Since, according to Kant, the ontological
argument fails, so does the physicotheological one.

Although Kant rejects the physiciotheological argument as a theoretical


proof for God’s existence, he also sees in it a powerful expression of
reason’s need to recognize in nature purposive unity and design (cf.
A625/B651). In this, the physicotheological argument’s emphasis on the
purposiveness and systematic unity of nature illuminates an assumption
that Kant takes to be essential to our endeavors in the natural sciences. The
essential role played by the assumption of purposive and systematic unity,
and the role it plays in scientific inquiries, is taken up by Kant in the
Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic. To this topic we now turn.

For some discussions of the Ideal of Pure Reason and Rational Theology,
see Caimi (1995). England (1968), Grier (2001, forthcoming), Henrich
(1960), Longuenesse (1995, 2005), Rohs (1978), Walsh (1975), and Wood
(1978), Chignell (2009), Grier (2010), Chignell (2014), Wuerth (2021),
Willaschek (2018)

32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

6. Reason and the Appendix to the Transcendental


Dialectic
The criticisms of the metaphysical arguments offered in the
Transcendental Dialectic do not bring Kant’s discussion to a close. Indeed,
in an “Appendix” to the Transcendental Dialectic, Kant returns to the issue
of reason’s positive or necessary role. The curious “Appendix” has
provoked a great deal of confusion, and not without reason. After all, the
entire thrust of the Dialectic seemed to be directed at “critiquing” and
curbing pure reason, and undermining its pretense to any real use.
Nevertheless, Kant goes on to suggest that the very reason that led us into
metaphysical error is also the source of certain necessary ideas and
principles, and moreover, that these rational postulations play an essential
role in scientific theorizing (A645/B673; A671/B699). Exactly what role
they are supposed to play in this regard is less clear.

The Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic is divided into two parts. In


the first, “On the Regulative Use of the Ideas of Pure Reason,” Kant
attempts to identify some proper “immanent” use for reason. In its most
general terms, Kant is here concerned to establish a necessary role for
reason’s principle of systematic unity. This principle was first formulated
by Kant in the Introduction to the Transcendental Dialectic in two forms,
one prescriptive, and the other in what sounded to be a metaphysical
claim. In the first, prescriptive form, the principle enjoins us to “Find for
the conditioned knowledge given through the understanding the
unconditioned whereby its unity is brought to completion.” The
complementary metaphysical principle assures us that the “unconditioned”
is indeed given and there to be found. Taken together, these principles
express reason’s interests in securing systematic unity of knowledge and
bringing such knowledge to completion.

Fall 2022 Edition 33


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

Kant is quite clear that he takes reason’s demand for systematicity to play
an important role in empirical inquiry. In connection with this, Kant
suggests that the coherent operation of the understanding somehow
requires reason’s guiding influence, particularly if we are to unify the
knowledge given through the real use of the understanding into scientific
theory (cf. A651–52/B679–80). To order knowledge systematically, for
Kant, means to subsume or unify it under fewer and fewer principles in
light of the idea of one “whole of knowledge” so that its parts are
exhibited in their necessary connections (cf. 646/B674). The idea of the
form of a whole of knowledge is thus said to postulate “complete unity in
the knowledge obtained by the understanding, by which this knowledge is
to be not a mere contingent aggregate, but a system connected according
to necessary laws” (A646/B676). Having said this, it should be noted that
Kant’s position is, in its details, difficult to pin down. Sometimes Kant
suggests merely that we ought to seek systematic unity of knowledge, and
this merely for own theoretical convenience (A771/B799-A772/B800).
Other times, however, he suggests that we must assume that the nature
itself conforms to our demands for systematic unity, and this necessarily, if
we are to secure even an empirical criterion of truth (cf. A651–53/B679–
81). The precise status of the demand for systematicity is therefore
somewhat controversial.

Regardless of these more subtle textual issues Kant remains committed to


the view that reason’s proper use is always only “regulative” and never
constitutive. The distinction between the regulative and the constitutive
may be viewed as describing two different ways in which the claims of
reason may be interpreted. A principle of reason is constitutive, according
to Kant, when it is taken to supply a concept of a real object (A306/B363;
A648/B676). Throughout the Dialectic Kant argued against this
(constitutive) interpretation of the ideas and principles of reason, claiming
that reason so far transcends possible experience that there is nothing in
experience that corresponds with its ideas. Although Kant denies that

34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

reason is constitutive he nevertheless, as we have seen, insists that it has


an “indispensably necessary” regulative use. In accordance with reason’s
demand, the understanding is guided and led to secure systematic unity
and completion of knowledge. In other words, Kant seeks to show that
reason’s demand for systematic unity is related to the project of empirical
knowledge acquisition. Indeed, Kant links the demand for systematicity up
with three other principles — those of homogeneity, specification and
affinity — which he thinks express the fundamental presumptions that
guide us in theory formation. The essential point seems to be that the
development and expansion of empirical knowledge is always, as it were,
“already” guided by the rational interests in securing unity and completion
of knowledge. Without such a guiding agenda, and without the assumption
that nature conforms to our rational demands for securing unity and
coherence of knowledge, our scientific pursuits would lack orientation.
Thus, the claim that reason’s principles play a necessary “regulative” role
in science reflects Kant’s critical reinterpretation of the traditional
rationalist ideal of arriving at complete knowledge.

It is connection with this that Kant argues, in the second part of the
Appendix (“On the Final Aim of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason”
(A669/B697)), that the three highest ideas of reason have an important
theoretical function. More specifically, in this section Kant turns from a
general discussion of the important (regulative) use of the principle of
systematicity, to a consideration of the three transcendental ideas (the
Soul, the World, and God) at issue in the Dialectic. As examples of the
unifying and guiding role of reason’s ideas, Kant had earlier appealed to
the ideas of “pure earth” and “pure air” in Chemistry, or the idea of a
“fundamental power” in psychological investigations (cf. A650/B678).
His suggestion earlier was that these ideas are implicit in the practices
governing scientific classification, and enjoin us to seek explanatory
connections between disparate phenomena. As such, reason’s postulations
serve to provide an orienting point towards which our explanations strive,

Fall 2022 Edition 35


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

and in accordance with which our theories progressively achieve


systematic interconnection and unity. Similarly, Kant now suggests that
each of the three transcendental ideas of reason at issue in the Dialectic
serves as an imaginary point (focus imaginarius) towards which our
investigations hypothetically converge. More specifically, he suggests that
the idea of the soul serves to guide our empirical investigations in
psychology, the idea of the world grounds physics, and the idea of God
grounds the unification of these two branches of natural science into one
unified Science (cf. A684/B712-A686/B714). In each of these cases, Kant
claims, the idea allows us to represent (problematically) the systematic
unity towards which we aspire and which we presuppose in empirical
studies. In accordance with the idea of God, for example, we “consider
every connection in the world according to principles [Principien] of a
systematic unity, hence as if they had all arisen from one single all-
encompassing being, as supreme and all-sufficient cause” (A686/B714).
Such a claim, controversial as it is, illuminates Kant’s view that empirical
inquiries are one and all undertaken in light of the rational goal of a single
unified body of knowledge. It also points towards the Kantian view, later
emphasized in the Transcendental Doctrine of Method, that reason’s
theoretical and practical interests ultimately form a higher unity.

For discussions on the Appendix and the role of reason and systematicity,
see Allison (2004), Brandt (1989), Buchdahl (1967), Britton (1978),
Forster (2000), Friedman (1992), Ginsborg (1990), Grier (2001,
forthcoming), Guyer (1990a, 1990b), Horstmann (1989), O’Neill (1992),
Patricia Kitcher (1991), Philip Kitcher (1984), Nieman (1994),
MacFarland (1970), Walker (1990), Walsh (1975), Wartenberg (1979,
1992), Rauscher (2010), Willaschek (2018).

For an important discussion on the “unity” of theoretical and practical


reason, see again Forster (2000). See also Velkley (1989).

36 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Bibliography
Relevant Works by Kant (includes German editions and
translations):

Critique of Practical Reason, 1956, trans. L. W. Beck, Indianapolis:


Bobbs-Merrill.
Critique of Pure Reason, 1929, trans. N. Kemp Smith, New York: St.
Martin’s Press
Gesammelte Schriften, 1922, Koniglich Preussischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften edition, Berlin and Leipzig: de Gruyter
Kant: Philosophical Correspondence , 1759–99, 1970, ed. and trans. A.
Zweig, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 1954, ed. R. Schmidt, Hamburg: Felix Meiner
Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, trans. J. Ellington,
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, 1950, trans. L.W. Beck,
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Kant: Selected Pre-Critical Writings and Correspondence with Beck,
1968, trans. G. B. Kerferd and D. E. Walford, Manchester:
Manchester University Press
Lectures on Philosophical Theology, 1978, trans. Allen Wood and
Gertrude M. Clark, Ithaca: Cornell University Press
First Introdcution to the Critique of Judgment, 1965, trans. James haden,
New York: Bobbs-Merrill Press
The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: Lectures on
Metaphysics, 1997, trans. and ed. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragan,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Lectures on
Logic, 1992, trans. and ed. J. Michael Young, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press

Fall 2022 Edition 37


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant: The Critique of


Pure Reason, 1998, trans. and ed. Paul Guyer and Allen Wood,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Selected Secondary Readings on Topics in Kant’s Dialectic

Al-Azm, S., 1972, The Origins of Kant’s Argument in the Antinomies,


Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ameriks, K., 1992, “The Critique of Metaphysics: Kant and Traditional
Ontology,” in Cambridge Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
–––, 2006, “The Critique of Metaphysics: The structure and Fate of Kant’s
Dialectic,” in P. Guyer (ed.), Kant and Modern Philosophy,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 269–302.
–––, 1982, Kant’s Theory of Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press
Allison, H., 1983, Kant’s Transcendental Idealism, New Haven: Yale
University Press
–––, 2004, Kant’s Transcendental Idealism, revised and expanded version,
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Bennett, J., 1974, Kant’s Dialectic, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Bird, G., 2006, The Revolutionary Kant, Chicago: Open Court.
Bird, G. (ed.), 2006, A Companion to Kant, Oxford: Blackwell.
Buroker, J., 2006, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: An Introduction,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brandt, Reinhardt, 1989, “The Deductions in the Critique of Judgment:
Comments on Hampshire and Horstmann,” in Kant’s Transcendental
Deductions, Eckhard Forster (ed.), Stanford: Stanford University
Press, pp. 177–190.
Brook, A., 1994, Kant and the Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press

38 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Brittan, Gordon G., 1978, Kant’s Theory of Science, Princeton: Princeton


University Press.
Buchdahl, Gerd, 1969, Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Butts, R., 1997, “Kant’s Dialectic and the Logic of Illusion,” in Logic and
the Workings of the Mind, ed. Patricia Easton, Atascadero, California:
Ridgeview,
Caimi, M., 1995, “On a Non-Regulative Function of the Ideal of Pure
Reason,” Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress, ed.
Hoke Robinson, Volume 1, Part 2 (3A-3L): 539–549.
Dyck, C., 2014, Kant and Rational Psychology, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
England, F. E., 1968, Kant’s Conception of God, New York: Humanities
Press.
Forster, Eckhard, 2000, Kant’s Final Synthesis: An Essay on the Opus
Postumum, Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.
Friedman, M., 1992, “Causal Laws and Foundations of Natural Science,”
in Cambridge Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press: 161–199.
Ginsborg, H., 1990, The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition. New
York and London: Garland Publishing Company.
Grier, M. , 2001, Kant’s Doctrine of Transcendental Illusion, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
–––, 2006, “The Logic of Illusion and the Antinomies,” in Bird (ed.) 2006,
Oxford: Blackwell: 192–207.
–––, 2010, “The Ideal of Pure Reason,” in P. Guyer (ed.) 2010, pp. 266–
289.
–––, forthcoming, “The Transcendental Dialectic,” in S. Baiasu and M.
Timmons (eds.), The Kantian Mind, London: Routledge.
Guyer, P., 1987, Kant and the Claims of Knowledge, Cambridge:
Cambridge University press

Fall 2022 Edition 39


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

–––, 1990a, “Kant’s Conception of Empirical law,” Proceedings of the


Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 64: 220–242.
–––, 1990b, “Reason and Reflective Judgment: Kant on the Significance of
Systematicity,” Noûs, 24: 17–43.
Guyer, P. (ed.), 1992, The Cambridge Companion to Kant, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press
––– (ed.), 2010, The Cambridge Companion to the Critique of Pure
Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heimsoeth, H., 1967, Transzendentale Dialektik. Ein Commentar su Kants
Kritik d. reinen Vernunft. Berlin: de Gruyter
Henrich, D., 1960, Der Ontologische Gottesbeweis. Sein Problem und
seine Geschichte In der Neuzeit, Tubingen: Morh.
Horstmann, Rolph P., 1989, “Why must there be a Deduction in Kant’s
Critique of Judgment?” in Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, ed. E.
Forster, pp. 157–176. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Kitcher, P., 1990, Kant’s Transcendental Psychology, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
Longuenesse, B., 1995, “Transcendental Ideal and the Unity of the Critical
System,” in Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress,
ed. Hoke Robinson, Volume 1, Part 2 (3A-3L), Milwaukee:
Marquette University Press.
–––, 2005, Kant on the Human Standpoint, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Loparic, Z., 1990, “The Logical Structure of the First Antinomy,” Kant-
Studien, 81: 280-303.
MacFarland, P., 1970, Kant’s Concept of Teleology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University press.
Nieman, S., 1994, The Unity of Reason, New York: Oxford University
Press
O’Neill, Onora, 1992, “Vindicating Reason,” in The Cambridge
Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge

40 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Unviersity press.
Rauscher, F., 2010, “The Appendix to the Dialectic and the Canon of Pure
Reason: The Positive Role of Reason,” in P. Guyer (ed.) 2010, pp.
290–309.
Rohs, P., 1978, “Kants Prinzip der durchgangigen Bestimmung alles
Seienden,” Kant-Studien, 69: 170-180.
Sellers, W., 1969, “Metaphysics and the Concept of a Person,” in The
Logical Way of Doing Things, ed. K. Lambert, New Haven: Yale
University Press: 219–232
–––, 1971, “…This I of He or It (the Thing) which Thinks…” Proceedings
and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 44: 5–31
Powell, C. T., 1990, Kant’s Theory of Self-Consciousness, Oxford:
Clarendon Press
Proops, I., 2010, “Kant’s First Paralogism,” Philosophical Review, 119:
449–95.
Strawson, P.F., 1966, The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of
Pure Reason, London: Methuen.
Theis, R., 1985, “De L’illusion transcendentale,” Kant-Studien, 76: 119-
137.
Theil, U., 2006, “The Critique of Rational Psychology,” in Bird (ed.)
2006: 207–222.
Van Cleve, J., 1981, “Reflections on Kant’s Second Antinomy,” Synthese,
47: 481–494.
Velkley, R. 1989, Freedom and the End of Reason: On the Moral
Foundations of Kant’s Critical Philosophy, Chicago and London:
University of Chicago Press.
Walker, R., 1990, “Kant’s Conception of Empirical Law,” Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 64: 243–258.
Walsh, W. H., 1975, Kant’s Criticisms of Metaphysics, Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Wartenberg, T., 1979, “Order Through Reason,” Kant-Studien, 70: 409-

Fall 2022 Edition 41


Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics

424.
–––, 1992, “Reason and the Practice of Science,” in Cambridge
Companion to Kant, ed. Paul Guyer, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press: 228–248.
Watkins, E., 1998, “Kant’s Antinomies: Sections 3–8,” Kooperativer
Kommentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft, G. Mohr & M.
Willaschek (eds.), Berlin: Akademie Verlag: 445–462
–––, 2000, “Kant on Rational Cosmology” in Kant and the Sciences, ed E.
Watkins, New York: Oxford University Press: 70–89.
Wilson, M., 1974, “Leibniz and Materialism,” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 3: 495–513
Willaschek, M., 2018, Kant on the Sources of Metaphysics: The Dialectic
of Pure Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wuerth, J., 2010, “The Paralogisms of Pure Reason,” in P. Guyer (ed.)
2010, pp. 210–244.
–––, 2021, The Cambridge Kant Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wolff, Robert Paul, 1963, Kant’s Theory of Mental Activity, Cambridge,
Mass: Harvard University Press
Wood, A., 1975, “Kant’s Dialectic,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 5
(4): 595–614.
–––, 1978, Kant’s Rational Theology, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
–––, 2010, “The Antinomies of Pure Reason,” in P. Guyer (ed.) 2010, pp.
245–265.
Wood, A. (ed.), 1984, Self and Nature in Kant’s Philosophy, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP
Society.

42 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy


Michelle Grier

Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet


Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links
to its database.

Other Internet Resources


Mainz Kant Site
Steve Palmquist’s Kant Site
Society of German Idealism

Related Entries
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb | Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich | Hume, David

Copyright © 2022 by the author


Michelle Grier

Fall 2022 Edition 43

You might also like