You are on page 1of 6

Shame, Guilt, and Embarrassment: Will the Real Emotion Please Stand Up?

Author(s): June Price Tangney, Debra Mashek and Jeff Stuewig


Source: Psychological Inquiry, Vol. 16, No. 1 (2005), pp. 44-48
Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd.
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20447260 .
Accessed: 15/06/2014 18:52

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Psychological
Inquiry.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES

tion,what we want to thinkof ourselves. Here is one tions between theway we identify and ascribe emo
of my examples. Jane is deeply resentful of her room tions and the individuation of emotional experience.
mate Mary, who is smarter and prettier.But she also
insists that she "hates" Mary. She refuses to accept the
suggestion that she resents her. I think that the same Note
sort of explanation serves here. Because resentment is
an emotion of defensiveness and inferiority (as the Robert Solomon, Department of Philosophy, WAG
philosopher Nietzsche argued at great length). Ha 316, University of Texas, 1Univ. Sta. C3500, Austin,
tred, by contrast, is a more noble emotion, not an TX 78712. E-mail: rsolomon@mail.utexas.edu
emotion of inferioritybut an emotion of righteous
ness, carrying with it even the implications of good
versus evil. So how would Jane want to thinkof her
References
self, as inferior or as righteous? But it is not as if the
emotions are the same. It is the pragmatics of the as Bedford, E. (1963). Emotions. In D. Gustafson (Ed.), Essays inPhilo
cription thatprovide the interesting story. sophical Psychology (pp. 77-90). New York: Doubleday-Anchor.
Sabini and Silver (this issue) are on something im Damasio, A. (1999). The Feeling ofWhat Happens: Body and Emo
tion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt
portant, something never adequately developed by
Brace.
Bedford and others, who got an early glimmer of the
James, W. (1890). Emotion. Principles of Psychology. New York:
extent towhich emotion ascription is not just naming Dover.
private inner states but saying something in part deter Nietzsche, F. (1997). Human, All to human (R. J. Hollingdale,

mined by the linguistic environment. But the authors Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Sabini, J.,& Silver,M. (1997). On thepossible non-existence of emotions:
can pursue this thesis in a great many interesting and
The passions. Journalfor theTheory of Social Behavior, 27(1).
valuable directions, so long as theydo not insiston first
Schachter, S., & Singer, J. (1962). The interaction of cognitive and
over-simplifying the emotions or the rich nature of physiological determinants of emotional state. Psychological
emotional experience and the fascinating interconnec Review, 69, 379-399.

Shame,Guilt, and Embarrassment:


Will theReal Emotion Please Stand Up?

June Price Tangney, Debra Mashek, and JeffStuewig


Department ofPsychology
George Mason University

Sabini and Silver's (this issue) targetarticle under lexicalized emotion termnames a differentexperiential
scores the complexity of human emotion-and human state. The wide variety of emotion words no doubt
cognition about human emotion. Citing numerous em arises not only from the diversity of human internal
pirical and theoretical examples, Sabini and Silver ar emotional experiences, per se, but also from differ
gue that the relationship between emotional experience ences in situational context, observer's perspective,
and language is not isomorphic. There is not a and unfolding tertiaryappraisals-of theemotion-elic
one-to-one correspondence between the emotions we iting situation, of the emotional experience, or of the
experience and thewords we use to describe those ex initial appraisals that gave shape to the ensuing emo
periences. With this observation, the authors have put tion.We are especially intrigued by the notion that the
their finger on one of themost challenging aspects of lexicon of human emotion is rich, in part, because of
conducting research on emotion. Much emotion re the unique perspectives of observers. Third party ob
search, especially research on the self-conscious emo servers often have access to unique types of informa
tions, hinges on self-report.Yet, in thedomain of emo tion thatmay give them special insight,particularly in
tion,we can be easily misled by words. instances likely to engender defensive, self-protective
reactions (e.g., as in the case of shame and envy). At
the same time,when interpretingand labeling the emo
What is a "Real" Emotion? tional experiences of others, observers ultimatelymust
refer back to their own personal emotional experi
We agree with Sabini and Silver (this issue) that ences. If an observer does not personally have a subjec
there is good reason to question whether each tive sense of how sadness is distinct frommelancholy

44

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES

(or how envy is distinct from anger), it is unlikely the ment differed from shame on fully 22 (71%) of the 31
observer will interpretand describe someone else's in experiential dimensions. Results indicated that al
ner experience as melancholic (or angry). That is, the though embarrassment was less painful and more fleet
richness of the self's emotional world informsour abil ing than shame, embarrassment was more likely to be
ity tomake nuanced judgments of others' emotional accompanied by physiological changes (e.g. blushing,
worlds. The factwe are able to do this suggests that the increased heart rate). There were fewermoral implica
nuanced language may reflect real and importantvaria tions in embarrassment than in either guilt or shame.
tions in emotional experiences. Embarrassment followed events forwhich people felt
Which pairs of emotion terms represent "true" dis less responsible and thatwere more unexpected. In ad
tinctionsbetween "real" emotions? Scientists have yet dition, embarrassment involved a greater sense of ex
to come to any consensus as to what constitutes the posure.When embarrassed, people were more likely to
"basic" emotions, nor is thereany emerging consensus feel thatothers were looking, and theywere more fo
regarding the specific criteria by which one would ele cused on others' judgments. Nonetheless, participants
vate an affective term to the class of "real" emotion, as perceived others' evaluations tobe more benign in em
opposed to minor emotion variants and mere syn barrassing situations. In particular, participants be
onyms (Ekman, 1994; Ortony & Turner, 1990; Tracy & lieved thatothers were likely to be amused by the em
Robins, 2004b). Our position regarding the classifica barrassing events, whereas shame- or guilt-inducing
tion of emotions is more pragmatic. Distinctions be events were amusing to no one. Perhaps of most im
tween emotion terms are important to the extent that port, people's motivation or "action tendencies" dif
theycontribute to thedevelopment of a coherent useful fered depending on which emotion was experienced.
scientific understanding of human emotion. Relative to embarrassment, when feeling shame, peo
ple were more motivated to hide from others.When
feeling guilt, they were more motivated to make
Are Shame, Guilt, and Embarrassment amends.
DistinctEmotions? Intensity of affect failed to account for these ob
served differences.When ratings of emotional inten
In 1988 (the year of the firstorganized meeting of sity were factored out, striking differences between
empirical researchers interested in shame-the Mac shame and embarrassment remained. In short, the fact
Arthur Asilomar Conference), the answer was by no that shame is a stronger feeling than embarrassment
means clear. Little systematic research had been con does not account for the shamed individual's inclina
ducted on these self-conscious emotions, and virtually tion tohide, to feel isolated fromothers, and to feel dis
none of theextant empirical work had been integrated. gusted with themselves.Moreover, compared to those
Today, there is considerable empirical research experiencing guilt, shamed individuals remainedmore
(drawing on multiple methods) indicating that these likely to feel small and inferior to others, to experience
are indeed useful distinctions. Phenomenological rat physiological changes, and to feel exposed, even when
ings of physiological reactions, affective experiences, the intensityof the affectwas controlled for.
perceptions of self and others, and motivations for sub Similarly, experiential differences among these
sequent action argue strongly against the notion that emotions could not be explained simply by the degree
shame and embarrassment are merely "different inter to which shame, embarrassment, and guilt-eliciting
pretations of the same raw feeling," and that"the expe events were perceived as involving moral transgres
riences underlying shame and embarrassment are the sions (vs., say, violations of social norms). Consistent
same" differingonly in interpretationof the situational with theory, shame and guilt were more likely to in
conditions that surround them. Furthermore, these volve a sense of moral transgression thanwas embar
emotions are associated with differentways of experi rassment. But when themorality dimension was fac
encing interpersonal contexts, differentways of con tored out, differences among the emotions along the
struingemotion-eliciting situations, and, perhaps most other experiential dimensions were, if anything,more
important,differentmotivations for subsequent action. pronounced.
Research drawing on multiple methods indicate that The evidence that shame and guilt are distinct emo
shame and embarrassment are not simply synonyms tions is even more substantial and comes from empiri
describing slight incarnations of the same construct cal studies employing a range of methodologies -in
(Keltner, 1995; Keltner & Busswell, 1996; Miller, cluding qualitative case study analyses (Lewis, 1971;
1996; Miller & Tangney, 1994; Tangney, Miller, Lindsay-Hartz, 1984; Lindsay-Hartz, Mascolo, &
Flicker, & Barlow, 1996). They are conceptually, em DeRivera, 1995), content analyses of shame and guilt
pirically, and phenomenologically distinct. narratives (Ferguson, Stegge, & Damhuis, 1990;
For example, whenyoungadultswere asked tode Tangney, 1992; Tangney,Marschall, Rosenberg,
scribeand ratepersonalshame,guilt,and embarrass Barlow,& Wagner, 1994), participants'
quantitative
ment experiences(Tangneyet al., 1996), embarrass ratings
of personalshameandguiltexperiences(e.g.,

45

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES

Ferguson, Stegge, & Damhuis, 1991; Tangney, 1993; this in spite of the probability thatmost of the partici
Tangney et al., 1996; Wallbott & Scherer, 1988, 1995; pants are legally guilty of criminal transgression.
Wicker, Payne, & Morgan, 1983), analyses of partici There are very few types of situations that reliably re
pants' counterfactual thinking (Niedenthal, Tangney, sult in the same emotion for all of humanity. Insults
& Gavanski, 1994) and psychological and behavioral may result in anger formany people, but insults can
correlatesof emotiondispositions,shame-proneness also elicit shame, embarrassment, pride (e.g., Al
and guilt-proneness (Stuewig & McCloskey, 2004; Franken may take pride in Bill O'Reilly's accusation
Tangney, 1991; Tangney & Dearing, 2002; Tangney & thathe is a knee-jerk liberal) or no emotional reaction
Mashek, 2004; Tangney & Stuewig, 2004; Tangney, at all! On the flip side, insults are not the only type of
Stuewig, Kendall, Reinsmith, & Dearing, 2004; event that causes feelings of anger (e.g., Averill,
Tangney,Wagner, Fletcher, & Gramzow, 1992). 1988; Berkowitz, 1989). People become angry when
This is not just a question of semantics. These are frustrated, thwarted, treated unjustly, or when simply
real differences with real implications formotivation stung by a bee-all in the absence of any hint of an
and behavior. For example, research indicates thatfeel insult. Suggesting the need for a one-to-one relation
ings of guilt are apt to prompt apologies and repara ship between eliciting event and emotional experi
tion,whereas feelings of shame are apt to prompt de ence is bound to be problematic, theoretically and
nial and escape. People appear better able toempathize empirically.
with others when experiencing guilt than shame. In
contrast, shame is uniquely associated anger and a pro
pensity to externalize blame. Moving Forward
It is difficult to reconcile the above findings with
Sabini and Silver's (this issue) assertion that "Shame, We are pleased to see Sabini and Silver (this issue)
guilt, and embarrassment are not, then, the names of presenting new and interesting ideas relating to some
three,distinct experiential states." All told, in the case of the self-conscious emotions. We agree with Tracy
of shame, guilt, and embarrassment, the semantics of and Robins (2004a) that these emotions, while central
emotion seem to capture meaningful variations along to psychological functioning, have been under-re
multiplerelevant -including physiologi
dimensions searched, and that"... the time is ripe to devote greater
cal reactions, subjective "raw" experience, attributions attention to self-conscious emotions" (p. 104).
and appraisals, audience perceptions and concerns, What is needed tomove forward our knowledge of
and, not least,motivations for subsequent behavior. emotional experience, and thewords used to describe
these experiences? In our view, systematic empirical
inquiry building on clear theoryusing multiple meth
Guilty is as Guilty Does? ods would be most helpful. Answers to the pressing
questions about emotion are not likely to be found just
Sabini and Silver (this issue) also argue for dis in the face, nor just in thenature of the emotion-elicit
pensing with guilt as an emotion distinct from shame, ing situation, nor just in the cognitive appraisals.
largely because there is another dictionary definition Multi-pronged, interdisciplinary investigation offers
of the noun "guilt"-guilt in a factual sense. Essen tremendous promise.
tially,Sabini and Silver argue thatone dictionary def In the 1960's and 1970's, emotion researchers cham
inition drives and defines another dictionary defini pioned thenotion thatone kind of arousal served as the
tion. That is, guilt the feeling is what people base forall emotional experiences-a position thatcon
experience when they are guilty in the factual sense. tributed to and was informed by the now famous
And because guilt the feeling (Meaning #1) doesn't Schacter and Singer (1962) studies. At that time, re
bear a one-to-one correspondence (or co-occurrence) searchers were focusing on a narrow set of biological
with the fact of guilt (Meaning #2), guilt the feeling markers-primarily those involving autonomic arousal.
(Meaning #1) ismeaningless. But this state of affairs With the increasing availability of powerful
should not arouse too much suspicion. Many, many psychobiological measurement tools, now is an exciting
words in the English language have multiple mean time in the study of emotions-many other biological
ings. Some are more closely related than others. We markers can now be assessed. Whether employing the
may use the term "guilt" to refer to a particular feel methods of neuroimaging or psychoneuroimmunology,
ing thatwe thinkpeople should (or believe people of researchers can evaluate a number of differentphysio
ten do) experience upon having committed a crime or logical concomitants of emotional variants. For exam
transgression. But it is also not necessary to insist ple, Kemeny, Gruenewald, and Dickerson (2004) have
that the fact of guilt unerringly results in the feeling argued that the self-conscious emotions are related to
of guilt,inorderforthelattertobe meaningful.In important psychobiological
processesand thatshame
fact,in our ongoingresearchwith jail inmateswe and guiltmay be differentiated
physiologically.
More
findmeaningfulvariationin theirfeelingsofguilt specific,ina recent
experimental
studytheyfoundthat

46

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES

induced shame, but not guilt or general negative emo cedents and facial expressions of emotion. Cognition and Emo
tion, 10, 155-171.
tion,was related to higher levels of proinflammatory
Kemeny, M. E., Gruenewald, T. L., & Dickerson, S. S. (2004).
cytokine activity (Dickerson, Kemeny, Aziz, Kim, & Shame as the emotional response to threat to the social self: Im
Fahey, 2004). Although, none of us are experts in plications for behavior, physiology, and health. Psychological
biopsychology or neuropsychology we expect thatstud Inquiry, 15(2), 153-160.

ies employing brain-based measurement strategieswill Kemeny, M., Gruenewald, T., & Dickerson, S. (2004, January). The

further inform the debate. Of course, knowing what physiological impact of threats to the social self and shame. In
J.L. Tracy & R. W. Robins (Chairs), Current Directions in re
brain areas are associated with a particular experience is
search on self-conscious emotions. Symposium conducted at
only a piece of the larger puzzle. For example, if one themeetings of the Society of Personality and Social Psychol
were to find that shame and guilt are indeed associated ogy, Austin, TX.
with the same brain areas, the debate over the unique Lewis, H. B. (1971). Shame and guilt in neurosis. New York: Inter
national Universities Press.
ness of these emotional experiences would nevertheless
Lindsay-Hartz, J. (1984). Contrasting experiences of shame and
continue. After all, we already know these two experi
guilt. American Behavioral Scientist, 27, 689-704.
ences are profoundly differenton the subjective level.
Lindsay-Hartz, J., de Rivera, J.,& Masc?lo, M. (1995). Differenti
The subjective interpretationof physiology may be just ating shame and guilt and their effects on motivation. In J. P.
as important-if notmore so-than thebase physiology Tangney & K. W. Fischer (Eds.), Self-conscious emotions:
Shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride (pp. 274-300). New
(e.g., Schacter & Singer). Again, thebest bet is to tackle
York: Guilford.
these questions on multiple levels ranging from the
Miller, R. S. (1996). Embarrassment: Poise and peril in everyday
brain, to the subjective, to theobserved.
life.New York: Guilford.
Moreover, the fieldof emotion researchwould bene Miller, R. S., & Tangney, J.P. (1994). Differentiating embarrassment
fitfroma clearer linguistical frameworkwhen referring and shame. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 13,

to the construct of "emotion." As evidenced by Sabini 273-287.


Niedenthal, P. M., Tangney, J. P., & Gavanski, I. (1994). "If only I
and Silver, phrases such as "mental state," "bodily
weren't" versus "If only I hadn't": Distinguishing shame and
state," "emotion," "feeling," "raw feeling," "emotional
guilt in counterfactual thinking. Journal of Personality and So
experience," and "experiential state" are often used in cial Psychology, 67, 585-595.
terchangeably.Ultimately, the semantic struggle to dif Ortony, A., & Turner, T. J. (1990). What's basic about basic emo
ferentiate"real" emotions will be more productive once tions? Psychological Review, 97, 315-331.
Schacter, S. & Singer, J.E. (1962). Cognitive, social, and physiologi
experimental domain of interest is clearly articulated.
cal determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review, 69,
379-399.

Stuewig, J.,& McCloskey, L. A. (2004). The impact ofmaltreatment


on adolescent shame and guilt: Psychological routes todepres
Note
sion and delinquency. Manuscript submitted for publication.

Tangney, J. P. (1991). Moral affect: The good, the bad, and the
June Tangney, George Mason University, Depart
ugly. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 61,
ment of Psychology,, 3F5, 4400 University Drive, 598-607.

Fairfax, VA 22030. E-mail: jtangney@gmu.edu Tangney, J.P. (1992). Situational determinants of shame and guilt in
young adulthood. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
18, 199-206.
Tangney, J. P. (1993). Shame and guilt. In C. G. Costello (Ed.),
References Symptoms of depression, (pp. 161-180). New York: Wiley.
Tangney, J. P., & Dealing, R. (2002). Shame and Guilt. New York:
Averill, J.R.(1988). Disorders of emotion. Journal of Social & Clini Guilford.
cal Psychology, 6, 247-268. Tangney, J. P., Marschall, D. E., Rosenberg, K., Barlow, D. H., &
Berkowitz, L. (1989). Frustration-aggression hypothesis: Examina Wagner, P. E. (1994). Children's and Adults' Autobiographical
tion and reformulation. Psychological Bulletin, 106, 59-73. Accounts of Shame, Guilt and Pride Experiences: An Analysis

Dickerson, S. S., Kemeny, M. E., Aziz, N., Kim, K. H., & Fahey, J.L. of Situational Determinants and Interpersonal Concerns. Un

(2004). Immunological effects of induced shame and guilt. Psy published manuscript.
chosomatic Medicine, 66, 124-131. Tangney, J.P., & Mashek, D. J. (2004). In search of themoral person:
Ekman, P (1994). All emotions are basic. In P. Ekman & J.Davidson Do you have to feel really bad to be good? In J.Greenberg, S. L.

(Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. Koole, & T. Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimental ex
15-19). New York: Oxford University Press. istential psychology (pp. 156-166). New York: Guilford.

Ferguson, T. J., Stegge, H., & Damhuis, I. (1990). Guilt and shame Tangney, J. P., Miller, R. S., Flicker, L., & Barlow, D. H. (1996).
experiences in elementary school-age children. In R. J.Takens Are shame, guilt and embarrassment distinct emotions? Jour

(Ed.), European perspectives in psychology (Vol. 1, pp. nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70, 1256-1269.

195-218). New York: Wiley. Tangney, J.P., & Stuewig, J. (2004). A moral emotional perspective
Ferguson, T. J., Stegge, H., & Damhuis, I. (1991). Children's under on evil persons and evil deeds. In A. Miller (Ed.), The social

standing of guilt and shame. Child Development, 62, 827-839. psychology of good and evil: Understanding our capacity for
Keltner, D. (1995). Signs of appeasement: Evidence for the distinct kindness and cruelty (pp. 327-355). New York: Guilford.

displays of embarrassment, amusement, and shame. Journal of Tangney, J., Stuewig, J.,Kendall, S., Reinsmith, C. L., & Dealing, R.
Personality and Social Psychology, 68, 441^54. (2005). Implications of Childhood Shame and Guilt for Risky
Keltner, D., & Buswell, B. N. (1996). Evidence for the distinctness and Illegal Behaviors in Young Adulthood. Unpublished
of embarrassment, shame, and guilt: A study of recalled ante manuscirpt.

47

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
COMMENTARIES

Tangney, J. P.,Wagner, P. E., Fletcher, C, & Gramzow, R. (1992). five continents. In K. R. Scherer (Ed.), Facets of emotion: Re
Shamed into anger? The relation of shame and guilt to anger cent research (pp. 31-56). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
and self-reported aggression. Journal of Personality and Social Associates, Inc.

Psychology, 62, 669-675. Wallbott, H. G., & Scherer, K. R. (1995). Cultural determinants in
Tracy, J.L., & Robins, R. W. (2004a). Putting the self into self-conscious experiencing shame and guilt. In J.P. Tangney & K. W. Fischer
emotions: A theoreticalmodel. Psychological Inquiry, 15, 103-125. (Eds.), Self-conscious emotions: The psychology of shame,

Tracy, J. L., & Robins R. W. (2004b). Keeping the self in self-con guilt, embarrassment, and pride (pp. 465-487). New York:
scious emotions: Further arguments for a theoretical model. Guilford.

Psychological Inquiry, 15, 171-177. Wicker, F.W., Payne, G. C, & Morgan, R. D. (1983). Participant de
Wallbott, H. G., & Scherer, K. R. (1988). How universal and spe scriptions of guilt and shame. Motivation and Emotion, 7,
cific is emotional experience? Evidence from 27 countries and 25-39.

48

This content downloaded from 62.122.79.78 on Sun, 15 Jun 2014 18:52:31 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like