You are on page 1of 60

Bioethics: Principles, Issues, and

Cases (5th Ed.) 5th Edition Lewis


Vaughn
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/bioethics-principles-issues-and-cases-5th-ed-5th-editi
on-lewis-vaughn/
VAUGHN
The #1 bioethics book on the market, combining
a wide variety of current readings and classic and
contemporary cases with extensive explanations
and more robust pedagogy than any other text.
“Vaughn’s Bioethics is the best product on the market. It ofers an excellent variety
of essays on a broad range of topics, provides excellent supplementary information
BIOETHICS
on each of the topics, and does so at a cost about half that of its competitors.”
—David Paul, Western Michigan University

NEW TO THIS EDITION


• New chapter: “Pandemic Ethics,” includes prioritizing who gets vaccines, ICUs, and personal
protective equipment; refusal to wear masks and to social distance; and science denial and the
spreading of misinformation.

• New chapter: “Race, Racial Bias, and Health Care,” includes myths about race and racism; race as
a factor in medical treatment; and racial disparities in allocation of medical and health resources.

• Expanded Chapter 1 (“Moral Reasoning in Bioethics”) to include a section on obstacles to critical


thinking, covering confrmation bias, denying contrary evidence, motivated reasoning, the
availability error, and the Dunning-Kruger efect.

• Updated Chapters: 7 (“Abortion”), 10 (“Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide”), and 11


(“Dividing Up Health Care Resources”).

• New readings, including those from Michael Sandel with Colleen Walsh; Angela Ballantyne;
Michael Root; and Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Govind Persad, and Ross Upshur, et al.

FIFTH EDITION
Visit www.oup.com/he/vaughn-bioethics5e for student and instructor resources.

ABOUT THE AUTHOR


Lewis Vaughn is the author or coauthor of numerous books, including Te Power of Critical Tinking,
Seventh Edition (2021), Philosophy Here and Now, Fourth Edition (2021), Living Philosophy, Tird
Edition (2020), and Bioethics, Fourth Edition (2019), all published by Oxford University Press.

PRINCIPLES , ISSUES , AND CASES


ISBN 978-0-19-760902-6
1
www.oup.com/us/he
90000 2
LEWIS VAUGHN
Cover Photo: © lone army/Shutterstock
Cover Design: T. Williams
9 780197 609026
3 FIFTH EDITION

Vaughn_9780197609026_finalCover.indd 1 2/11/22 11:58 AM


Bioethics
Bioethics
Principles, Issues, and Cases
Fifh Edition

Lewis Vaughn
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford
University Press in the UK and certain other countries.
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.
© 2023, 2020, 2017, 2013, 2010 by Oxford University Press

For titles covered by Section 112 of the US Higher Education Opportunity


Act, please visit www.oup.com/us/he for the latest information about
pricing and alternate formats.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,


stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press,
or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with
the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning
reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights
Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.
CIP data is on fle at the Library of Congress.
ISBN 978-0-19-760902-6
Library of Congress Control Number: 2022931400

987654321
Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America
B R I E F CO N T E N T S

Preface xii

Part 1. Principles and Theories 1


Chapter 1 moral reasoning in bioethics 3
Chapter 2 bioethics and moral theories 38

Part 2. Medical Professional and Patient 95


Chapter 3 paternalism and patient autonomy 97
Chapter 4 truth-telling and confidentiality 170
Chapter 5 informed consent 200
Chapter 6 human research 238

Part 3. Life and Death 303


Chapter 7 abortion 305
Chapter 8 reproductive technology 391
Chapter 9 genetic choices 466
Chapter 10 euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide 551

Part 4. Justice and Health Care 629


Chapter 11 dividing up health care resources 631
Chapter 12 pandemic ethics 697
Chapter 13 race, racial bias, and health care 725

Appendix 749
Glossary 751
Index 755

v
CO N T E N T S

Preface xii Summary 34


Argument Exercises 35
Part 1. Principles and Theories 1 Further Reading 36
Notes 37
Chapter 1
moral reasoning in bioethics 3 Chapter 2
Ethics and Bioethics 3 bioethics and moral
Ethics and the Moral Life 5 theories 38
In Depth: Morality and the Law 7
Te Nature of Moral Teories 38
Moral Principles in Bioethics 8
Infuential Moral Teories 39
Autonomy 9
Utilitarianism 40
Nonmalefcence 10
In Depth: Utilitarianism and the Golden
Benefcence 10 Rule 42
Utility 11 Kantian Ethics 42
Justice 12 Principlism 44
Ethical Relativism 13 Natural Law Teory 45
In Depth: Anthropology and Moral Diversity 14 Rawls’s Contract Teory 47
Ethics and Religion 17 Virtue Ethics 49
Moral Arguments 19 In Depth: Can Virtue Be Taught? 50
Argument Fundamentals 19 Te Ethics of Care 50
Patterns of Moral Arguments 22 Feminist Ethics 51
Review: Valid and Invalid Argument Forms 23 Casuistry 52
In Depth: Fallacies in Moral Reasoning 24 Criteria for Judging Moral Teories 53
Evaluating Premises 26 Review: Evaluating Moral Teories: Criteria of
Assessing Whole Arguments 28 Adequacy 54
Obstacles to Critical Reasoning 29 Applying the Criteria 54
Denying Contrary Evidence 30 Utilitarianism 55
Looking for Confrming Evidence 30 Kant’s Teory 56
Motivated Reasoning 31 Key Terms 57
Preferring Available Evidence 32 Summary 57
Te Dunning-Kruger Efect 33 Further Reading 58
Key Terms 34 Notes 58
Contents vii

readings 59 “Confronting Death: Who Chooses, Who


“Utilitarianism,” John Stuart Mill 59 Controls? A Dialogue Between Dax Cowart
“Te Moral Law,” Immanuel Kant 62 and Robert Burt,” Dax Cowart and Robert
Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle 67 Burt 146
“Te Need for More Tan Justice,” Annette C. Bouvia v. Superior Court, California Court of
Baier 78 Appeal 156
“Moral Saints,” Susan Wolf 86 “Fundamental Elements of the Patient-Physician
Relationship,” AMA Council on Ethical and
Part 2. Medical Professional and Patient 95 Judicial Afairs 161
“Advocacy or Subservience for the Sake of
Chapter 3
Patients?” Helga Kuhse 162
paternalism and patient
autonomy 97 Chapter 4
Shades of Autonomy and Paternalism 97 truth-telling and
Refusing Treatment 98 confidentiality 170
In Depth: Physician Autonomy 100
Paternalism and Deception 170
Futile Treatment 100
In Depth: Do Patients Want the Truth? Do
Legal Brief: Advance Directives 101 Physicians Tell It? 171
Legal Brief: Refusing Treatment for Children on Confdential Truths 173
Religious Grounds 102
Legal Brief: Confdentiality and a Duty to
In Depth: CPR and DNR 103 Warn 174
In Depth: Moral Conficts in Nursing 103 In Depth: Truth-Telling and Cultural
Classic Case File: Elizabeth Bouvia 104 Diversity 175
Applying Major Teories 105 Classic Case File: Carlos R. 176
Key Terms 106 Applying Major Teories 177
Summary 106 Key Terms 178
Cases for Evaluation 107 Summary 178
Further Reading 109 Cases for Evaluation 178
Notes 110 Further Reading 180
Notes 180
readings 110
“Paternalism,” Gerald Dworkin 110 readings 181
“Te Refutation of Medical Paternalism,” Alan “On Telling Patients the Truth,” Mack Lipkin 181
Goldman 120 “Is It Ever OK to Lie to Patients?” Shelly K.
“Why Doctors Should Intervene,” Terrence F. Schwartz 183
Ackerman 126 “Why Privacy Is Important,” James Rachels 186
“Autonomy, Futility, and the Limits of Medicine,” “Confdentiality in Medicine—A Decrepit
Robert L. Schwartz 131 Concept,” Mark Siegler 192
“Four Models of the Physician-Patient Relationship,” Tarasof v. Regents of the University of California,
Ezekiel J. Emanuel and Linda L. Emanuel 136 Supreme Court of California 195
viii Contents

Chapter 5 Classic Case File: Te UCLA Schizophrenia


informed consent 200 Study 252
Cases for Evaluation 253
Autonomy and Consent 200
Further Reading 257
Conditions of Informed Consent 201
Notes 257
In Depth: Decision-Making Capacity 203
In Depth: Two Views of Informed Consent 205 readings 258
Legal Brief: Important Informed Consent Te Nuremberg Code 258
Cases 206 Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for
Applying Major Teories 207 Medical Research Involving Human Subjects,
Classic Case File: Jerry Canterbury 208 World Medical Association 259
Key Terms 209 “Te Belmont Report,” Te National Commission
Summary 209 for the Protection of Human Subjects of
Cases for Evaluation 210 Biomedical and Behavioral Research 262
Further Reading 212 “Final Report: Human Radiation Experiments,”
Notes 212 Advisory Committee on Human Radiation
Experiments 265
readings 212
“Of Mice but Not Men: Problems of the
“Te Concept of Informed Consent,” Ruth R. Faden
Randomized Clinical Trial,” Samuel Hellman
and Tom L. Beauchamp 212
and Deborah S. Hellman 271
“Informed Consent—Must It Remain a Fairy Tale?”
“A Response to a Purported Ethical Difculty with
Jay Katz 217
Randomized Clinical Trials Involving Cancer
“Transparency: Informed Consent in Primary
Patients,” Benjamin Freedman 277
Care,” Howard Brody 227
“Racism and Research: Te Case of the Tuskegee
Canterbury v. Spence, United States Court of
Syphilis Study,” Allan M. Brandt 281
Appeals 234
“Te Ethics of Clinical Research in the Tird
World,” Marcia Angell 293
Chapter 6
“Ethical Issues in Clinical Trials in Developing
human research 238 Countries,” Baruch Brody 297
Te Science of Clinical Trials 239
In Depth: Te Tuskegee Tragedy 240 Part 3. Life and Death 303
Benefcence, Science, and Placebos 241
Chapter 7
Science and Informed Consent 244
In Depth: Women in Clinical Trials 245 abortion 305
Research on the Vulnerable 246 Starting Point: Te Basics 305
In Depth: Why Enter a Clinical Trial? 247 Fact File: U.S. Abortions 306
Applying Major Teories 250 In Depth: Abortion and Public Opinion
Key Terms 251 2021 309
Summary 251 Te Legal Struggle 310
In Depth: Abortions Performed Later in
Pregnancy 311
Contents ix

Persons and Rights 312 Cases for Evaluation 407


In Depth: Does a Fetus Feel Pain? 315 Further Reading 409
Applying Major Teories 316 Notes 410
Key Terms 317
Summary 317 readings 411
“IVF: Te Simple Case,” Peter Singer 411
Classic Case File: Nancy Klein 318
“Te Presumptive Primacy of Procreative Liberty,”
Cases for Evaluation 319
John A. Robertson 415
Further Reading 322
“Surrogate Mothering: Exploitation or
Notes 322
Empowerment?” Laura M. Purdy 422
readings 323 “Is Women’s Labor a Commodity?” Elizabeth S.
“A Defense of Abortion,” Judith Jarvis Tomson 323 Anderson 432
“Why Abortion Is Immoral,” Don Marquis 334 “Egg Donation and Commodifcation,” Bonnie
“On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion,” Mary Steinbock 445
Anne Warren 346 “Cloning Human Beings: An Assessment of the
“Abortion and the Concept of a Person,” Jane Ethical Issues Pro and Con,” Dan W. Brock 454
English 357
“Abortion,” Margaret Olivia Little 364 Chapter 9
“Abortion Trough a Feminist Ethics Lens,” Susan genetic choices 466
Sherwin 369
Genes and Genomes 466
Roe v. Wade, United States Supreme Court 378
Genetic Testing 467
Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v.
Gene Terapy 473
Casey, United States Supreme Court 384
Fact File: Genetic Testing for Cancer Risk 475
Stem Cells 478
Chapter 8
Fact File: New Developments in Gene Terapy 479
reproductive technology 391 Applying Major Teories 481
In Vitro Fertilization 391 Classic Case File: Te Kingsburys 482
Fact File: Assisted Reproduction 392 Key Terms 483
In Depth: “Savior Siblings” 395 Summary 483
Surrogacy 397 Cases for Evaluation 483
In Depth: IVF and Children’s Future Further Reading 486
Children 398 Notes 486
Cloning 400
In Depth: Cloning Time Line 403 readings 487
Applying Major Teories 404 “Genetics and Reproductive Risk: Can Having
Key Terms 404 Children Be Immoral?” Laura M. Purdy 487
In Depth: Sherri Shepherd: How Surrogacy Can “Te Morality of Screening for Disability,” Jef
Go Wrong 405 McMahan 494
Summary 405 “Genetic Dilemmas and the Child’s Right to an
Classic Case File: Baby M 406 Open Future,” Dena S. Davis 498
x Contents

“Disowning Knowledge: Issues in Genetic Testing,” readings 568


Robert Wachbroit 509 “Death and Dignity: A Case of Individualized
“Te Non-Identity Problem and Genetic Harms— Decision Making,” Timothy E. Quill 568
Te Case of Wrongful Handicaps,” Dan W. “Voluntary Active Euthanasia,” Dan W. Brock 572
Brock 513 “When Self-Determination Runs Amok,” Daniel
“Is Gene Terapy a Form of Eugenics?” John Callahan 584
Harris 518 “Active and Passive Euthanasia,” James
“Genetic Enhancement,” Walter Glannon 524 Rachels 589
“Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of “Dying at the Right Time: Refections on (Un)
Enhancement of Human Beings,” Julian Assisted Suicide,” John Hardwig 593
Savulescu 529 “Te Philosophers’ Brief,” Ronald Dworkin, Tomas
“Germ-Line Gene Terapy,” LeRoy Walters and Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls, Tomas
Julie Gage Palmer 538 Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis Tomson 604
“What Does ‘Respect for Embryos’ Mean in the “Legalizing Assisted Dying Is Dangerous for
Context of Stem Cell Research?” Bonnie Disabled People,” Liz Carr 613
Steinbock 546 “‘For Now Have I My Death’ 1: Te ‘Duty to Die’
Declaration on the Production and the Scientifc and Versus the Duty to Help the Ill Stay Alive,”
Terapeutic Use of Human Embryonic Stem Felicia Ackerman 615
Cells, Pontifcal Academy for Life 549 Vacco v. Quill, United States Supreme Court 626

Chapter 10 Part 4. Justice and Health Care 629


euthanasia and physician- Chapter 11
assisted suicide 551
dividing up health care
Deciding Life and Death 552
resources 631
Legal Brief: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide:
Major Developments 554 Health Care in Trouble 631
In Depth: Assisted Suicide: What Do Doctors Fact File: U.S. Health Care 634
Tink? 555 Teories of Justice 635
Autonomy, Mercy, and Harm 556 In Depth: Comparing Health Care Systems:
In Depth: Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act 558 United States, Canada, and Germany 636
In Depth: End-of-Life Decisions in the A Right to Health Care 638
Netherlands 560 In Depth: Public Health and Bioethics 639
Applying Major Teories 560 Te Ethics of Rationing 640
In Depth: Physician-Assisted Suicide and Public Classic Case File: Christine deMeurers 642
Opinion 561 Key Terms 644
Classic Case File: Nancy Cruzan 562 Summary 644
Key Terms 563 Cases for Evaluation 645
Summary 563 Further Reading 648
Cases for Evaluation 564 Notes 648
Further Reading 567
Notes 568
Contents xi

readings 649 readings 712


“Is Tere a Right to Health Care and, If So, What “Why Some Americans Refuse to Social Distance
Does It Encompass?,” Norman Daniels 649 and Wear Masks,” Michael Sandel with Colleen
“Te Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care,” Walsh 712
Allen E. Buchanan 656 “Fair Allocation of Scarce Medical Resources in the
“Rights to Health Care, Social Justice, and Fairness Time of Covid-19,” Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Govind
in Health Care Allocations: Frustrations in the Persad, Ross Upshur, et al. 715
Face of Finitude,” H. Tristram Engelhardt, “ICU Triage: How Many Lives or Whose Lives?”
Jr. 662 Angela Ballantyne 722
“Mirror, Mirror 2017: International Comparison
Refects Flaws and Opportunities for Better U.S. Chapter 13
Health Care,” Eric C. Schneider, Dana O. race, racial bias, and health
Sarnak, David Squires, et al. 670 care 725
“Public Health Ethics: Mapping the Terrain,” James
Race and Racism 725
F. Childress, Ruth R. Faden, Ruth D. Gaare,
Health Disparities and Race 731
et al. 675
Implicit Bias in Health Care 733
“Human Rights Approach to Public Health Policy,”
In Depth: Can Implicit Biases Be Changed? 735
D. Tarantola and S. Gruskin 686
Racial Profling in Medicine 735
Key Terms 737
Chapter 12
Summary 737
pandemic ethics 697 Cases for Evaluation 738
Pandemic Facts 698 Further Reading 739
When Resources Are Scarce 699 Notes 739
Personal Choices 702
reading 740
In Depth: Te Privilege of Social
Distancing 704 “Racial Profling in Medicine,” Michael Root 740

COVID Falsehoods 705 Appendix 749


In Depth: Against Pandemic Falsehoods 707 Glossary 751
Key Terms 708 Index 755
Summary 708
Cases for Evaluation 709
Further Reading 711
Notes 711
P R E FAC E

Tis ffh edition of Bioethics embodies all the 6. Writing that strives hard for clarity and
features that have made it a best-selling text- concision to convey both the excitement
book and includes all the most important and complexity of issues without
changes and improvements that dozens of sacrifcing accuracy
teachers have asked for recently and over the
years. Te book is, therefore, better than ever. topics and readings
And if it isn’t, let even more good teachers say so Eleven chapters cover many of the most contro-
and let the corrections and enhancements con- versial issues in bioethics, detailing the main
tinue. And may the book remain, as so many arguments and flling out the discussions with
teachers have said, exactly suitable to their background on the latest medical, legal, and
teaching approach. social developments. Te main issues include
Bioethics provides in-depth discussions of paternalism and patient autonomy, truth-tell-
the philosophical, medical, scientifc, social, and ing, confdentiality, informed consent, research
legal aspects of controversial bioethical issues ethics, clinical trials, abortion, assisted repro-
and combines this material with a varied collec- duction, surrogacy, cloning, genetic testing,
tion of thought-provoking readings. But on this gene therapy, stem cells, euthanasia, physician-
foundation are laid elements that other texts assisted suicide, the just allocation of health
sometimes forgo: care, pandemic ethics, and racial bias in health
and medicine.
1. An extensive introduction to ethics,
Every issues chapter contains one to twelve
bioethics, moral principles, critical
readings, with each selection prefaced by a brief
thinking, and moral reasoning
summary. Te articles—old standards as well as
2. Full coverage of infuential moral theories,
new ones—refect the major arguments and
including criteria and guidelines for
latest thinking in each debate. Tey present a di-
evaluating them (the focus is on
versity of perspectives on each topic, with pro
utilitarianism, Kantian ethics, natural law
and con positions well represented. In most
theory, Rawls’s contract theory,
cases, the relevant court rulings are also
principlism, virtue ethics, the ethics of
included.
care, and feminist ethics)
3. Detailed examinations of the classic cases
special features
that have helped shape debate in major
A two-chapter introduction to bioethics, moral
issues
reasoning, moral theories, and critical think-
4. Collections of current, news-making cases
ing. Tese chapters are designed not only to in-
for evaluation
troduce the subject matter of bioethics but also
5. Many pedagogical features to engage
to add coherence to subsequent chapter material
students and reinforce lessons in the main
and to provide the student with a framework for
text
thinking critically about issues and cases.
Preface xiii

Chapter 1 is an introduction to basic ethical A diverse package of pedagogical aids. Each


concepts, the feld of bioethics, moral principles issues chapter contains a chapter summary, sug-
and judgments, moral reasoning and argu- gestions for further reading, and a variety of
ments, the challenges of relativism, and the rela- text boxes. Te boxes are mainly of three types:
tionship between ethics and both religion and
1. “In Depth”—additional information,
the law. Chapter 2 explores moral theory, shows
illustrations, or analyses of matters
how theories relate to moral principles and
touched on in the main text.
judgments, examines infuential theories (in-
2. “Fact File”—statistics on the social,
cluding virtue ethics, the ethics of care, and
medical, and scientifc aspects of the
feminist ethics), and demonstrates how they can
chapter’s topic.
be applied to moral problems. It also explains
3. “Legal Brief”—summaries of important
how to evaluate moral theories using plausible
court rulings or updates on the status of
criteria of adequacy.
legislation.
Helpful chapter elements. Each issues chap-
ter contains:
new to this edition
1. Analyses of the most important arguments A Chapter on Pandemic Ethics
ofered by the various parties to the Chapter 12 covers many of the most important
debate. Tey reinforce and illustrate the life-and-death issues and moral debates that
lessons on moral reasoning in Chapter 1. have occurred during the COVID-19 pandemic:
2. A section called “Applying Major emergency triage and the allocation of scarce
Teories” showing how the moral theories medical resources (ICU beds, ventilators, medi-
can be applied to the issues. It ties the cations, vaccines), the safety and welfare of
discussions of moral theories in Chapter 2 health care workers, disparities in health care
to the moral problems and illustrates the for racial and ethnic minorities, personal mo-
theories’ relevance. rality (whether to wear a mask, practice social
3. A section labeled “Classic Case File” that distancing, get vaccinated, and self-isolate), the
examines in detail a famous bioethics spreading of pandemic misinformation, cutting
case. Te stories covered in these sections corners in coronavirus research, and contact
include those of Elizabeth Bouvia, Jerry tracing versus privacy rights.
Canterbury, Nancy Klein, Baby M, Nancy
Cruzan, the Kingsburys, Christine A Chapter on Race, Racial Bias, and
deMeurers, and the UCLA Schizophrenia Health Care
Study. Tese are in addition to many other Chapter 13 delves into the insidious efects of
controversial cases covered elsewhere in racial and ethnic bias on the health status of mi-
the book—for example, the Terri Schiavo norities and on nearly every facet of health care.
controversy, the Tuskegee tragedy, the It discusses prevailing misconceptions about
Willowbrook experiments, and the U.S. race and provides philosophically sound defni-
government’s human radiation studies. tions of racism (both individual and structural),
4. A bank of “Cases for Evaluation” at the racial prejudice, and racial discrimination. It
end of each chapter. Tese are recent news debunks the myth that racism and racial dis-
stories followed by discussion questions. crimination are things of the past, shows how
Tey give students the chance to test their structural racism has caused large-scale racial
moral reasoning on challenging new inequalities in society, and documents the
scenarios that range across a broad health disparities—the diferences in mortality
spectrum of current topics. and disease—between Whites and minorities.
xiv Preface

It examines the evidence of widespread racial University Press—especially my editor Andrew


and ethnic bias in health care, explores the pow- Blitzer, assistant editors Rachel Boland and
erful efects of implicit bias in clinical practice, Lacey Harvey—and many reviewers:
and surveys the problem of racial profling in
Keith Abney, Polytechnic State University at
diagnosis and treatment.
San Luis Obispo
Kim Amer, DePaul University
Updates
Jami L. Anderson, University of Michigan
• Abortion and public opinion (survey)
Carol Isaacson Barash, Boston University
• Abortions performed later in pregnancy
Deb Bennett-Woods, Regis University
• Statistics on assisted reproduction
Don Berkich, Texas A&M University
• “Savior siblings”
Stephan Blatti, University of Memphis
• New developments in gene therapy
William Bondeson, University of Missouri,
• Te fve main ways to do gene therapy
Columbia
• Genetic testing for cancer risk
Lori Brown, Eastern Michigan University
• Euthanasia and assisted suicide: major
Paul Benjamin Cherlin, Minneapolis College
developments
David W. Concepción, Ball State University
• Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act
Catherine Coverston, Brigham Young
• U.S. health care: the uninsured, per capita
University
spending, and health care quality
Russell DiSilvestro, California State
• Comparing health care systems: U.S.,
University, Sacramento
Canada, and Germany
John Doris, Washington University in
St. Louis
New Readings
Denise Dudzinski, University of Washington
• Michael Sandel with Colleen Walsh, “Why
School of Medicine
Some Americans Refuse to Social Distance
Craig Duncan, Ithaca College
and Wear Masks”
Anne Edwards, Austin Peay State University
• Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Govind Persad, Ross
John Elia, University of Georgia
Upshur, et al., “Fair Allocation of Scarce
Christy Flanagan-Feddon, Regis University
Medical Resources in the Time of Covid-19”
Jacqueline Fox, University of South Carolina
• Angela Ballantyne, “ICU Triage: How
School of Law
Many Lives or Whose Lives?”
Leslie P. Francis, University of Utah
• Michael Root, “Racial Profling in Medicine”
Devin Frank, University of Missouri–
Columbia
ancillaries Kathryn M. Ganske, Shenandoah University
Te Oxford University Press Learning Link houses Martin Gunderson, Macalester College
a wealth of instructor and student resources, in- Helen Habermann, University of Arizona
cluding an Instructor’s Manual, Test Bank, and Stephen Hanson, University of Louisville
both Lecture and Art PowerPoint Presentations Karey Harwood, North Carolina State
for instructor use. Te site also includes Self- University
Quizzes, Videos and Video Quizzes, and Flash- Sheila R. Hollander, University of Memphis
cards for student use. Please visit www.oup.com/ Chad Horne, Northwestern University
he/vaughn-bioethics5e to access these resources. Scott James, University of North Carolina,
Wilmington
acknowledgments James Joiner, Northern Arizona University
Tis edition of the text is measurably better than William P. Kabasenche, Washington State
the frst, thanks to the good people at Oxford University
Preface xv

Kristen Kringle-Baer, University of North Steve Odmark, Century College


Carolina Wilmington Assya Pascalev, Howard University
Susan Levin, Smith College Viorel Pâslaru, University of Dayton
Margaret Levvis, Central Connecticut State David J. Paul, Western Michigan University
University Anthony Preus, Binghamton University
Burden S. Lundgren, Old Dominion Susan M. Purviance, University of Toledo
University Sara Schuman, Washtenaw Community
John T. Meadors, Mississippi College College
Joan McGregor, Arizona State University David Schwan, Bowling Green State
Tristram McPherson, Virginia Tech University
Jonathan K. Miles, Bowling Green State Anita Silvers, San Francisco State University
University M. Josephine Snider, University of Florida
James Lindemann Nelson, Michigan State Joseph Wellbank, Northeastern University
University Gladys B. White, Georgetown University
Tomas Nenon, University of Memphis David Yount, Mesa Community College
Laura Newhart, Eastern Kentucky
University
1
Principles and Teories
CHAP TER 1

Moral Reasoning in Bioethics


Any serious and rewarding exploration of bio- Second, it would be difcult to imagine moral
ethics is bound to be a challenging journey. issues more important—more closely gathered
What makes the trip worthwhile? As you might around the line between life and death, health
expect, this entire text is a long answer to that and illness, pain and relief, hope and despair—
question. You therefore may not fully appreciate than those addressed by bioethics. Whatever
the trek until you have already hiked far along our view of these questions, there is little doubt
the trail. Te short answer comes in three parts. that they matter immensely. Whatever answers
First, bioethics—like ethics, its parent we give will surely have weight, however they
discipline—is about morality, and morality is fall.
about life. Morality is part of the unavoidable, Tird, as a systematic study of such ques-
bittersweet drama of being persons who think tions, bioethics holds out the possibility of an-
and feel and choose. Morality concerns beliefs swers. Te answers may or may not be to our
regarding morally right and wrong actions and liking; they may confrm or confute our precon-
morally good and bad persons or character. ceived notions; they may take us far or not far
Whether we like it or not, we seem confronted enough. But, as the following pages will show,
continually with the necessity to deliberate the trail has more light than shadow—and
about right and wrong, to judge someone mor- thinking critically and carefully about the prob-
ally good or bad, to agree or disagree with the lems can help us see our way forward.
moral pronouncements of others, to accept or
reject the moral outlook of our culture or com- ethics and bioethics
munity, and even to doubt or afrm the exis-
tence or nature of moral concepts themselves. Morality is about people’s moral judgments,
Moral issues are thus inescapable—including principles, rules, standards, and theories—all of
(or especially) those that are the focus of bioeth- which help direct conduct, mark out moral
ics. In the twenty-frst century, few can remain practices, and provide the yardsticks for mea-
entirely untouched by the pressing moral ques- suring moral worth. We use morality to refer
tions of fair distribution of health care resources, generally to these aspects of our lives (as in “Mo-
abortion and infanticide, euthanasia and as- rality is essential”) or more specifcally to the
sisted suicide, exploitative research on children beliefs or practices of particular groups or per-
and populations in developing countries, human sons (as in “American morality” or “Kant’s mo-
cloning and genetic engineering, assisted repro- rality”). Moral, of course, pertains to morality as
duction and surrogate parenting, prevention just defned, though it is also sometimes em-
and treatment of HIV/AIDS, the confdentiality ployed as a synonym for right or good, just as
and consent of patients, the refusal of medical immoral is ofen meant to be equivalent to
treatment on religious grounds, experimenta- wrong or bad. Ethics, as used in this text, is not
tion on human embryos and fetuses, and the synonymous with morality. Ethics is the study
just allocation of scarce life-saving organs. of morality using the tools and methods of

3
4 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

philosophy. Philosophy is a discipline that sys- principles, rules, virtues, and theories, and the
tematically examines life’s big questions through lofy aim of this branch is to establish rationally
critical reasoning, logical argument, and careful some or all of these as proper guides for our ac-
refection. Tus, ethics—also known as moral tions and judgments. In normative ethics, we
philosophy—is a reasoned way of delving into ask questions like these: What moral principles,
the meaning and import of moral concepts and if any, should inform our moral judgments?
issues and of evaluating the merits of moral What role should virtues play in our lives? Is the
judgments and standards. (As with morality and principle of autonomy justifed? Are there any
moral, we may use ethics to say such things as exceptions to the moral principle of “do not
“Kant’s ethics” or may use ethical or unethical to kill”? How should we resolve conficts between
mean right or wrong, good or bad.) Ethics seeks moral norms? Is contractarianism a good moral
to know whether an action is right or wrong, theory? Is utilitarianism a better theory?
what moral standards should guide our con- A branch that deals with much deeper ethical
duct, whether moral principles can be justifed, issues is metaethics. Metaethics is the study of
what moral virtues are worth cultivating and the meaning and justifcation of basic moral be-
why, what ultimate ends people should pursue liefs. In normative ethics we might ask whether
in life, whether there are good reasons for ac- an action is right or whether a person is good,
cepting a particular moral theory, and what the but in metaethics we would more likely ask what
meaning is of such notions as right, wrong, good, it means for an action to be right or for a person
and bad. Whenever we try to reason carefully to be good. For example, does right mean has the
about such things, we enter the realm of ethics: best consequences, or produces the most happi-
We do ethics. ness, or commanded by God? It is the business of
Science ofers another way to study morality, metaethics to explore these and other equally
and we must carefully distinguish this approach fundamental questions: What, if anything, is
from that of moral philosophy. Descriptive the diference between moral and nonmoral be-
ethics is the study of morality using the meth- liefs? Are there such things as moral facts? If so,
odology of science. Its purpose is to investigate what sort of things are they, and how can they
the empirical facts of morality—the actual be- be known? Can moral statements be true or
liefs, behaviors, and practices that constitute false—or are they just expressions of emotions
people’s moral experience. Tose who carry out or attitudes without any truth value? Can moral
these inquiries (usually anthropologists, sociol- norms be justifed or proven?
ogists, historians, and psychologists) want to Te third main branch is applied ethics, the
know, among other things, what moral beliefs a use of moral norms and concepts to resolve
person or group has, what caused the subjects to practical moral issues. Here, the usual challenge
have them, and how the beliefs infuence behav- is to employ moral principles, theories, argu-
ior or social interaction. Very generally, the dif- ments, or analyses to try to answer moral ques-
ference between ethics and descriptive ethics is tions that confront people every day. Many such
this: In ethics we ask, as Socrates did, How ought questions relate to a particular professional feld
we to live? In descriptive ethics we ask, How do such as law, business, or journalism, so we have
we in fact live? specialized subfelds of applied ethics like legal
Ethics is a big subject, so we should not be ethics, business ethics, and journalistic ethics.
surprised that it has three main branches, each Probably the largest and most energetic subfeld
dealing with more or less separate but related is bioethics.
sets of ethical questions. Normative ethics is the Bioethics is applied ethics focused on health
search for, and justifcation of, moral standards, care, medical science, and medical technology.
or norms. Most ofen the standards are moral (Biomedical ethics is ofen used as a synonym,
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 5

and medical ethics is a related but narrower term prescribe the form of moral conduct. Tere are,
used most ofen to refer to ethical problems in of course, other sorts of norms we apply in
medical practice.) Ranging far and wide, bio- life—nonmoral norms. Aesthetic norms help us
ethics seeks answers to a vast array of tough eth- make value judgments about art; norms of eti-
ical questions: Is abortion ever morally quette about polite social behavior; grammati-
permissible? Is a woman justifed in having an cal norms about correct use of language;
abortion if prenatal genetic testing reveals that prudential norms about what is in one’s inter-
her fetus has a developmental defect? Should ests; and legal norms about lawful and unlawful
people be allowed to select embryos by the em- acts. But moral norms difer from these non-
bryos’ sex or other genetic characteristics? moral kinds. Some of the features they are
Should human embryos be used in medical re- thought to possess include the following.
search? Should human cloning be prohibited?
Should physicians, nurses, physicians’ assis- Normative Dominance. In our moral practice,
tants, and other health care professionals always moral norms are presumed to dominate other
be truthful with patients whatever the conse- kinds of norms, to take precedence over them.
quences? Should severely impaired newborns be Philosophers call this characteristic of moral
given life-prolonging treatment or be allowed to norms overridingness because moral consider-
die? Should people in persistent vegetative states ations so ofen seem to override other factors. A
be removed from life support? Should physi- maxim of prudence, for example, may suggest
cians help terminally ill patients commit sui- that you should steal if you can avoid getting
cide? Is it morally right to conduct medical caught, but a moral prohibition against stealing
research on patients without their consent if the would overrule such a principle. An aesthetic
research would save lives? Should human stem- (or pragmatic) norm implying that homeless
cell research be banned? How should we decide people should be thrown in jail for blocking the
who gets life-saving organ transplants when view of a beautiful public mural would have to
usable organs are scarce and many patients who yield to moral principles demanding more
do not get transplants will die? Should animals humane treatment of the homeless. A law man-
be used in biomedical research? dating brutal actions against a minority group
Te ethical and technical scope of bioethics is would confict with moral principles of justice
wide. Bioethical questions and deliberations now and would therefore be deemed illegitimate. We
fall to nonexpert and expert alike—to patients, usually think that immoral laws are defective,
families, and others as well as to philosophers, that they need to be changed, or that, in rare
health care professionals, lawyers, judges, scien- cases, they should be defed through acts of civil
tists, clergy, and public policy specialists. Tough disobedience.
the heart of bioethics is moral philosophy, fully
informed bioethics cannot be done without a good Universality. Moral norms (but not exclusively
understanding of the relevant nonmoral facts and moral norms) have universality: Moral princi-
issues, especially the medical, scientifc, techno- ples or judgments apply in all relevantly similar
logical, and legal ones. situations. If it is wrong for you to tell a lie in a
particular circumstance, then it is wrong for ev-
ethics and the moral life eryone in relevantly similar circumstances to
tell a lie. Logic demands this sort of consistency.
Morality, then, is a normative, or evaluative, en- It makes no sense to say that Maria’s doing
terprise. It concerns moral norms or standards action A in circumstances C is morally wrong,
that help us decide the rightness of actions, but John’s doing A in circumstances relevantly
judge the goodness of persons or character, and similar to C is morally right. Universality,
6 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

however, is not unique to moral norms; it’s a the director’s “discrimination” would not be arbi-
characteristic of all normative spheres. trary and so would not be open to criticism.1
Reasonableness. To participate in morality—to
Impartiality. Implicit in moral norms is the
engage in the essential, unavoidable practices of
notion of impartiality—the idea that everyone
the moral life—is to do moral reasoning. If our
should be considered equal, that everyone’s in-
moral judgments are to have any weight at all, if
terests should count the same. From the per-
they are to be anything more than mere per-
spective of morality, no person is any better
sonal taste or knee-jerk emotional response,
than any other. Everyone should be treated the
they must be backed by the best of reasons. Tey
same unless there is a morally relevant difer-
must be the result of careful refection in which
ence between persons. We probably would be
we arrive at good reasons for accepting them,
completely bafed if someone seriously said
reasons that could be acknowledged as such by
something like “murder is wrong . . . except
any other reasoning persons.
when committed by myself,” when there was no
Both logic and our commonsense moral ex-
morally relevant diference between that person
perience demand that the thorough sifing of
and the rest of the world. If we took such a state-
reasons constitutes the main work of our moral
ment seriously at all, we would likely not only
deliberations—regardless of our particular
reject it but also would not even consider it a
moral outlook or theory. We would think it odd,
bona fde moral statement.
perhaps even perverse, if someone asserted that
Te requirement of moral impartiality pro-
physician-assisted suicide is always morally
hibits discrimination against people merely be-
wrong—and then said she has no reasons at all
cause they are diferent—diferent in ways that
for believing such a judgment but just does.
are not morally relevant. Two people can be dif-
Whatever our views on physician-assisted sui-
ferent in many ways: skin color, weight, gender,
cide, we would be justifed in ignoring her judg-
income, age, occupation, and so forth. But these
ment, for we would have no way to distinguish it
are not diferences relevant to the way they
from personal whim or wishful thinking. Like-
should be treated as persons. However, if there
wise she herself (if she genuinely had no good
are morally relevant diferences between people,
reasons for her assertion) would be in the same
then we may have good reasons to treat them
boat, adrif with a frm opinion moored to noth-
diferently, and this treatment would not be a
ing solid.
violation of impartiality. Tis is how philoso-
Our feelings, of course, are also part of our
pher James Rachels explains the point:
moral experience. When we ponder a moral
Te requirement of impartiality, then, is at bottom issue we care about (abortion, for example), we
nothing more than a proscription against arbi- may feel anger, sadness, disgust, fear, irritation,
trariness in dealing with people. It is a rule that or sympathy. Such strong emotions are normal
forbids us from treating one person diferently and ofen useful, helping us empathize with
from another when there is no good reason to do so. others, deepening our understanding of human
But if this explains what is wrong with racism, it sufering, and sharpening our insight into the
also explains why, in some special kinds of cases, consequences of our moral decisions. But our
it is not racist to treat people diferently. Suppose a feelings can mislead us by refecting not moral
flm director was making a movie about the life of truth but our own psychological needs, our own
Martin Luther King, Jr. He would have a perfectly personal or cultural biases, or our concern for
good reason for ruling out Tom Cruise for the star- personal advantage. Troughout history, some
ring role. Obviously, such casting would make no people’s feelings led them to conclude that
sense. Because there would be a good reason for it, women should be burned for witchcraf, that
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 7

economic. Thus, murder and embezzlement are both


I N D E P TH immoral and illegal, backed by social disapproval and
severe sanctions imposed by law. Controversy often
MORALITY AND THE LAW
arises when an action is not obviously or seriously
harmful but is considered immoral by some who want
the practice prohibited by law. The contentious
Some people confuse morality with the law, or iden- notion at work is that something may be made illegal
tify the one with the other, but the two are distinct solely on the grounds that it is immoral, regardless of
though they may often coincide. Laws are norms en- any physical or economic harm involved. This view of
acted or enforced by the state to protect or pro- the law is known as legal moralism, and it sometimes
mote the public good. They specify which actions are underlies debates about the legalization of abortion,
legally right or wrong. But these same actions can euthanasia, reproductive technology, contraception,
also be judged morally right or wrong, and these two and other practices.
kinds of judgments will not necessarily agree. Lying Many issues in bioethics have both a moral and
to a friend about a personal matter, deliberately legal dimension, and it is important not to confuse
trying to destroy yourself through reckless living, or the two. Sometimes the question at hand is a moral
failing to save a drowning child (when you easily one (whether, for example, euthanasia is ever mor-
could have) may be immoral—but not illegal. Racial ally permissible); whether a practice should be legal
bias, discrimination based on gender or sexual orien- or illegal then is beside the point. Sometimes the
tation, slavery, spousal rape, and unequal treatment question is about legality. And sometimes the discus-
of minority groups are immoral—but, depending on sion concerns both. A person may consider physi-
the society, they may not be illegal. cian-assisted suicide morally acceptable but argue
Much of the time, however, morality and the law that it should nevertheless be illegal because allowing
overlap. Often what is immoral also turns out to be the practice to become widespread would harm
illegal. This is usually the case when immoral actions both patients and the medical profession.
cause substantial harm to others, whether physical or

whole races should be exterminated, that Black Moral obligations concern our duty, what we
men should be lynched, and that adherents of a are obligated to do. Tat is, obligations are about
diferent religion were evil. Critical reasoning conduct, how we ought or ought not to behave.
can help restrain such terrible impulses. It can In this sphere, we talk primarily about actions.
help us put our feelings in proper perspective We may look to moral principles or rules to
and achieve a measure of impartiality. Most of guide our actions, or study a moral theory that
all, it can guide us to moral judgments that are purports to explain right actions, or make judg-
trustworthy because they are supported by the ments about right or wrong actions.
best of reasons. Moral values, however, generally concern
Te moral life, then, is about grappling with a those things that we judge to be morally good,
distinctive class of norms marked by normative bad, praiseworthy, or blameworthy. Normally
dominance, universality, impartiality, and rea- we use such words to describe persons (as in “He
sonableness. As we saw earlier, these norms can is a good person” or “She is to blame for hurting
include moral principles, rules, theories, and them”), their character (“He is virtuous”; “She is
judgments. We should notice that we commonly honest”), or their motives (“She did wrong but
apply these norms to two distinct spheres of our did not mean to”). Note that we also attribute
moral experience—to both moral obligations nonmoral value to things. If we say that a book
and moral values. or bicycle or vacation is good, we mean good in
8 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

a nonmoral sense. Such things in themselves said about moral theories, which we explore in
cannot have moral value. the next chapter.) Certainly to be useful, moral
Strictly speaking, only actions are morally principles must be interpreted, ofen flled out
right or wrong, but persons are morally good or with specifcs, and balanced with other moral
bad (or some degree of goodness or badness). concerns. But both in everyday life and in bio-
With this distinction we can acknowledge a ethics, moral principles are widely thought to be
simple fact of the moral life: A good person can indispensable to moral decision-making.
do something wrong, and a bad person can do We can see appeals to moral principles in
something right. A Gandhi can tell a lie, and a countless cases. Confronted by a pain-racked,
Hitler can save a drowning man. terminally ill patient who demands to have his
In addition, we may judge an action right or life ended, his physician refuses to comply, rely-
wrong depending on the motive behind it. If ing on the principle that “it is wrong to inten-
John knocks a stranger down in the street to pre- tionally take a life.” Another physician makes a
vent her from being hit by a car, we would deem diferent choice in similar circumstances, insist-
his action right (and might judge him a good ing that the relevant principle is “ending the suf-
person). But if he knocks her down because he fering of a hopelessly ill patient is morally
dislikes the color of her skin, we would believe permissible.” An infant is born anencephalic
his action wrong (and likely think him evil). (without a brain); it will never have a conscious
Te general meaning of right and wrong life and will die in a few days. Te parents decide
seems clear to just about everyone. But we should to donate the infant’s organs to other children
be careful to diferentiate degrees of meaning in so they might live, which involves taking the
these moral terms. Right can mean either “oblig- organs right away before they deteriorate. A
atory” or “permissible.” An obligatory action is critic of the parents’ decision argues that “it is
one that would be wrong not to perform. We are unethical to kill in order to save.” But someone
obligated or required to do it. A permissible else appeals to the principle “save as many chil-
action is one that is permitted. It is not wrong to dren as possible.”2 In such ways moral principles
perform it. Wrong means “prohibited.” A help guide our actions and inform our judg-
prohibited action is one that would be wrong to ments about right and wrong, good and evil.
perform. We are obligated or required not to do As discussed in Chapter 2, moral principles
it. A supererogatory action is one that is “above are ofen drawn from a moral theory, which is a
and beyond” our duty. It is praiseworthy—a moral standard on the most general level. Te
good thing to do—but not required. Giving all principles are derived from or supported by the
your possessions to the poor is generally consid- theory. Many times we simply appeal directly to
ered a supererogatory act. a plausible moral principle without thinking
much about its theoretical underpinnings.
moral principles in bioethics Philosophers make a distinction between ab-
solute and prima facie principles (or duties). An
As noted earlier, the main work of bioethics is absolute principle applies without exceptions.
trying to solve bioethical problems using the An absolute principle that we should not lie de-
potent resources and methods of moral philoso- mands that we never lie regardless of the cir-
phy, which include, at a minimum, critical rea- cumstances or the consequences. In contrast, a
soning, logical argument, and conceptual prima facie principle applies in all cases unless
analysis. Many, perhaps most, moral philoso- an exception is warranted. Exceptions are justi-
phers would be quick to point out that beyond fed when the principle conficts with other
these tools of reason we also have the consider- principles and is thereby overridden. W. D. Ross
able help of moral principles. (Te same could be is given credit for drawing this distinction in his
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 9

1930 book Te Right and the Good.3 It is essen- general we are not permitted to violate people’s
tial to his account of ethics, which has a core of autonomy just because we disagree with their
several moral principles or duties, any of which decisions, or because society might beneft, or
might come into confict. because the violation is for their own good. We
Physicians have a prima facie duty to be cannot legitimately impair someone’s autonomy
truthful to their patients as well as a prima facie without strong justifcation for doing so. Con-
duty to promote their welfare. But if these duties ducting medical experiments on patients with-
come in confict—if, for example, telling a pa- out their consent, treating competent patients
tient the truth about his condition would some- against their will, physically restraining or con-
how result in his death—a physician might fning patients for no medical reason—such
decide that the duty of truthfulness should yield practices constitute obvious violations of per-
to the weightier duty to do good for the patient. sonal autonomy.
Moral principles are many and varied, but in Not all restrictions on autonomy, however,
bioethics the following have traditionally been are of the physical kind. Autonomy involves the
extremely infuential and particularly relevant capacity to make personal choices, but choices
to the kinds of moral issues that arise in health cannot be considered entirely autonomous
care, medical research, and biotechnology. In unless they are fully informed. When we make
fact, many—perhaps most—of the thorniest decisions in ignorance—without relevant infor-
issues in bioethics arise from conficts among mation or blinded by misinformation—our au-
these basic principles. In one formulation or an- tonomy is diminished just as surely as if someone
other, each one has been integral to major moral physically manipulated us. If this is correct,
theories, providing evidence that the principles then we have a plausible explanation of why
capture something essential in our moral expe- lying is generally prohibited: Lying is wrong be-
rience. Te principles are (1) autonomy, (2) non- cause it undermines personal autonomy. En-
malefcence, (3) benefcence, (4) utility, and (5) shrined in bioethics and in the law, then, is the
justice.4 precept of informed consent, which demands
that patients be allowed to freely consent to or
Autonomy decline treatments and that they receive the in-
Autonomy refers to a person’s rational capacity formation they need to make informed judg-
for self-governance or self-determination—the ments about them.
ability to direct one’s own life and choose for In many ways, autonomy is a delicate thing,
oneself. Te principle of autonomy insists on easily compromised and readily thwarted. Ofen
full respect for autonomy. One way to express a person’s autonomy is severely undermined not
the principle is: Autonomous persons should be by other people but by nature, nurture, or his or
allowed to exercise their capacity for self-deter- her own actions. Some drug addicts and alco-
mination. According to one major ethical tradi- holics, people with serious psychiatric illness,
tion, autonomous persons have intrinsic worth and those with severe mental impairment are
precisely because they have the power to make thought to have drastically diminished auton-
rational decisions and moral choices. Tey omy (or to be essentially nonautonomous). Bio-
therefore must be treated with respect, which ethical questions then arise about what is
means not violating their autonomy by ignoring permissible to do to them and who will repre-
or thwarting their ability to choose their own sent their interests or make decisions regarding
paths and make their own judgments. their care. Infants and children are also not fully
Te principle of respect for autonomy places autonomous, and the same sorts of questions
severe restraints on what can be done to an au- are forced on parents, guardians, and health
tonomous person. Tere are exceptions, but in care workers.
10 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

Like all the other major principles discussed widely recognized moral principle. Its aphoris-
here, respect for autonomy is thought to be tic expression has been embraced by practi-
prima facie. It can sometimes be overridden by tioners of medicine for centuries: “Above all, do
considerations that seem more important or no harm.” A more precise formulation of the
compelling—considerations that philosophers principle is: We should not cause unnecessary
and other thinkers have formulated as princi- injury or harm to those in our care. In whatever
ples of autonomy restriction. Te principles are form, nonmalefcence is the bedrock precept of
articulated in various ways, are applied widely countless codes of professional conduct, institu-
to all sorts of social and moral issues, and are tional regulations, and governmental rules and
themselves the subject of debate. Chief among laws designed to protect the welfare of patients.
these is the harm principle: a person’s autonomy A health care professional violates this prin-
may be curtailed to prevent harm to others. To ciple if he or she deliberately performs an action
prevent people from being victimized by thieves that harms or injures a patient. If a physician in-
and murderers, we have a justice system that tentionally administers a drug that she knows
prosecutes and imprisons the perpetrators. To will induce a heart attack in a patient, she obvi-
discourage hospitals and health care workers ously violates the principle—she clearly does
from hurting patients through carelessness or something that is morally (and legally) wrong.
fraud, laws and regulations limit what they can But she also violates it if she injures a patient
do to people in their care. To stop someone from through recklessness, negligence, or inexcusable
spreading a deadly, contagious disease, health ignorance. She may not intend to hurt anyone,
ofcials may quarantine him against his will. but she is guilty of the violation just the same.
Another principle of autonomy restriction is Implicit in the principle of nonmalefcence is
paternalism. Paternalism is the overriding of a the notion that health professionals must exer-
person’s actions or decision-making for her own cise “due care.” Te possibility of causing some
good. Some cases of paternalism (sometimes pain, sufering, or injury is inherent in the care
called weak paternalism) seem permissible to and treatment of patients, so we cannot realisti-
many people—when, for example, seriously de- cally expect health professionals never to harm
pressed or psychotic patients are temporarily anyone. But we do expect them to use due care—
restrained to prevent them from injuring or kill- to act reasonably and responsibly to minimize
ing themselves. Other cases are more controver- the harm or the chances of causing harm. If a
sial. Researchers hoping to develop a life-saving physician must cause patients some harm to
treatment give an experimental drug to some- efect a cure, we expect her to try to produce the
one without his knowledge or consent. Or a least amount of harm possible to achieve the re-
physician tries to spare the feelings of a compe- sults. And even if her treatments cause no actual
tent, terminally ill patient by telling her that she pain or injury in a particular instance, we expect
will eventually get better, even though she in- her not to use treatments that have a higher
sists on being told the truth. Te paternalism in chance of causing harm than necessary. By the
such scenarios (known as strong paternalism) is lights of the nonmalefcence principle, subject-
usually thought to be morally objectionable. ing patients to unnecessary risks is wrong even
Many controversies in bioethics center on the if no damage is done.
morality of strong paternalism.
Benefcence
Nonmalefcence Te principle of benefcence has seemed to many
Te principle of nonmalefcence asks us not to to constitute the very soul of morality—or very
intentionally or unintentionally infict harm on close to it. In its most general form, it says that
others. In bioethics, nonmalefcence is the most we should do good to others. (Benevolence is
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 11

diferent, referring more to an attitude of good- substitute for, the principles of autonomy, benef-
will toward others than to a principle of right icence, and justice.
action.) Benefcence enjoins us to advance the In ethics this maxim comes into play in sev-
welfare of others and prevent or remove harm eral ways. Most famously it is the defning pre-
to them. cept of the moral theory known as utilitarianism
Benefcence demands that we do more than (discussed in Chapter 2). But it is also a stand-
just avoid inficting pain and sufering. It says alone moral principle applied everywhere in
that we should actively promote the well-being of bioethics to help resolve the kind of dilemmas
others and prevent or remove harm to them. In just mentioned. A physician, for example, must
bioethics, there is little doubt that physicians, decide whether a treatment is right for a patient,
nurses, researchers, and other professionals and that decision ofen hinges on whether the
have such a duty. Afer all, helping others, pro- possible benefts of the treatment outweigh its
moting their good, is a large part of what these risks by an acceptable margin. Suppose a man’s
professionals are obliged to do. clogged artery can be successfully treated with
But not everyone thinks that we all have a open-heart surgery, a procedure that carries a
duty of active benefcence. Some argue that considerable risk of injury and death. But imag-
though there is a general (applicable to all) duty ine that the artery can also be successfully
not to harm others, there is no general duty to opened with a regimen of cholesterol-lowering
help others. Tey say we are not obligated to aid drugs and a low-fat diet, both of which have a
the poor, feed the hungry, or tend to the sick. much lower chance of serious complications.
Such acts are not required, but are supereroga- Te principle of utility seems to suggest that the
tory, beyond the call of duty. Others contend latter course is best and that the former is mor-
that though we do not have a general duty of ally impermissible.
active benefcence, we are at least sometimes ob- Te principle also plays a major role in the
ligated to look to the welfare of people we care creation and evaluation of the health policies of
about most—such as our parents, children, institutions and society. In these large arenas,
spouses, and friends. In any case, it is clear that most people aspire to fulfll the requirements of
in certain professions—particularly medicine, benefcence and malefcence, but they recognize
law, and nursing—benefting others is ofen not that perfect benefcence or malefcence is im-
just supererogatory but obligatory and basic. possible: Trade-ofs and compromises must be
made, scarce resources must be allotted, help
Utility and harm must be balanced, life and death must
Te principle of utility says that we should pro- be weighed—tasks almost always informed by
duce the most favorable balance of good over bad the principle of utility.
(or beneft over harm) for all concerned. Te Suppose, for example, we want to mandate
principle acknowledges that in the real world, the immunization of all schoolchildren to pre-
we cannot always just beneft others or just avoid vent the spread of deadly communicable dis-
harming them. Ofen we cannot do good for eases. Te cost in time and money will be great,
people without also bringing them some harm, but such a program could save many lives. Tere
or we cannot help everyone who needs to be is a down side, however: A small number of
helped, or we cannot help some without also children—perhaps as many as 2 for every
hurting or neglecting others. In such situations, 400,000 immunizations—will die because of a
the principle says, we should do what yields the rare allergic reaction to the vaccine. It is impos-
best overall outcome—the maximum good and sible to predict who will have such a reaction
minimum evil, everyone considered. Te utility (and impossible to prevent it), but it is almost
principle, then, is a supplement to, not a certain to occur in a few cases. If our goal is
12 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

social benefcence, what should we do? Children will deter further unacceptable behavior.
are likely to die whether we institute the pro- Distributive justice concerns the fair distribu-
gram or not. Guided by the principle of utility tion of society’s advantages and disadvantages—
(as well as other principles), we may decide to for example, jobs, income, welfare aid, health
proceed with the program since many more care, rights, taxes, and public service. Distribu-
lives would likely be saved by it than lost be- tive justice is a major issue in bioethics, where
cause of its implementation. many of the most intensely debated questions
Again, suppose governmental health agen- are about who gets health care, what or how
cies have enough knowledge and resources to much they should get, and who should pay for it.
develop fully a cure for only one disease—either Distributive justice is a vast topic, and many
a rare heart disorder or a common form of skin theories have been proposed to identify and jus-
cancer. Trying to split resources between these tify the properties, or traits, of just distributions.
two is sure to prevent development of any cure A basic precept of most of these theories is what
at all. Te heart disorder kills 200 adults each may plausibly be regarded as the core of the
year; the cancer occurs in thousands of people, principle of justice: Equals should be treated
causing them great pain and distress, but it is equally. (Recall that this is one of the defning
rarely fatal. How best to maximize the good? On elements of ethics itself, impartiality.) Te idea
which disease should the government spend its is that people should be treated the same unless
time and treasure? Answering this question there is a morally relevant reason for treating
(and others like it) requires trying to apply the them diferently. We would think it unjust for a
utility principle—a job ofen involving complex physician or nurse to treat his White diabetic
calculations of costs and benefts and frequently patients more carefully than he does his Black
generating controversy. diabetic patients—and to do so without a sound
medical reason. We would think it unfair to
Justice award the only available kidney to the trans-
In its broadest sense, justice refers to people get- plant candidate who belongs to the “right” polit-
ting what is fair or what is their due. In practice, ical party or has the best personal relationship
most of us seem to have a rough idea of what with hospital administrators.
justice entails in many situations, even if we Te principle of justice has been at the heart
cannot articulate exactly what it is. We know, of debates about just distribution of benefts and
for example, that it is unjust for a bus driver to burdens (including health care) for society as a
make a woman sit in the back of the bus because whole. Te disagreements have generally not
of her religious beliefs, or for a judicial system to been about the legitimacy of the principle, but
arbitrarily treat one group of citizens more about how it should be interpreted. Diferent
harshly than others, or for a doctor to care for theories of justice try to explain in what respects
some patients but refuse to treat others just be- equals should be treated equally.
cause he dislikes them. Libertarian theories emphasize personal
Questions of justice arise in diferent spheres freedoms and the right to pursue one’s own
of human endeavor. Retributive justice, for ex- social and economic well-being in a free market
ample, concerns the fair meting out of punish- without interference from others. Ideally
ment for wrongdoing. On this matter, some the role of government is limited to
argue that justice is served only when people are night-watchman functions—the protection of
punished for past wrongs, when they get their society and free economic systems from coer-
just deserts. Others insist that justice demands cion and fraud. All other social or economic
that people be punished not because they de- benefts are the responsibility of individuals.
serve punishment, but because the punishment Government should not be in the business of
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 13

helping the socially or economically disadvan- idea that at least some moral standards are ob-
taged, for that would require violating people’s jective. Moral objectivism, however, is distinct
liberty by taking resources from the haves to from moral absolutism, the belief that objective
give to the have-nots. So universal health care moral principles allow no exceptions or must be
is out of the question. For the libertarian, then, applied the same way in all cases and cultures. A
people have equal intrinsic worth, but this does moral objectivist can be absolutist about moral
not entitle them to an equal distribution of principles, or she can avoid absolutism by ac-
economic advantages. Individuals are entitled cepting that moral principles are prima facie. In
only to what they can acquire through their any case, most people probably assume some
own hard work and ingenuity. form of moral objectivism and would not take
Egalitarian theories maintain that a just dis- seriously any claim implying that valid moral
tribution is an equal distribution. Ideally, social norms can be whatever we want them to be.
benefts—whether jobs, food, health care, or But moral objectivism is directly challenged
something else—should be allotted so that ev- by a doctrine that some fnd extremely appeal-
eryone has an equal share. Treating people ing and that, if true, would undermine ethics
equally means making sure everyone has equal itself: ethical relativism. According to this view,
access to certain minimal goods and services. moral standards are not objective but are rela-
To achieve this level of equality, individual lib- tive to what individuals or cultures believe.
erties will have to be restricted, measures that Tere simply are no objective moral truths, only
libertarians would never countenance. In a pure relative ones. An action is morally right if en-
egalitarian society, universal health care would dorsed by a person or culture and morally wrong
be guaranteed. if condemned by a person or culture. So eutha-
Between strict libertarian and egalitarian nasia is right for person A if he approves of it but
views of justice lie some theories that try to wrong for person B if she disapproves of it, and
achieve a plausible fusion of both perspectives. the same would go for cultures with similarly
With a nod toward libertarianism, these theo- diverging views on the subject. In this way,
ries may exhibit a healthy respect for individual moral norms are not discovered but made; the
liberty and limit governmental interference in individual or culture makes right and wrong.
economic enterprises. But leaning toward egali- Ethical relativism pertaining to individuals is
tarianism, they may also mandate that the basic known as subjective relativism, more precisely
needs of the least well-of citizens be met. stated as the view that right actions are those
In bioethics, the principle of justice and the sanctioned by a person. Ethical relativism re-
theories used to explain it are constantly being garding cultures is called cultural relativism,
marshaled to support or reject health care poli- the view that right actions are those sanctioned
cies of all kinds. Tey are frequently used— by one’s culture.
along with other moral principles—to evaluate, In some ways, subjective relativism is a com-
design, and challenge a wide range of health forting position. It relieves individuals of the
care programs and strategies. Tey are, in other burden of serious critical reasoning about mo-
words, far from being merely academic. rality. Afer all, determining right and wrong is
a matter of inventorying one’s beliefs, and any
ethical relativism sincerely held beliefs will do. Morality is essen-
tially a matter of personal taste, which is an
Te commonsense view of morality and moral extremely easy thing to establish. Determining
standards is this: Tere are moral norms or what one’s moral views are may indeed in-
principles that are valid or true for everyone. volve deliberation and analysis—but neither of
Tis claim is known as moral objectivism, the these is a necessary requirement for the job.
14 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

is a promise to commit a crime. . . . It has been


customary to hold that diverse evaluations of
I N D E P TH
the same act are automatic evidence for the
ANTHROPOLOGY presence of different principles of evaluation.
AND MORAL DIVERSITY The preceding examples point to an error in
this interpretation. Indeed, an examination of
the relational factors points to the operation
Many moral philosophers have been quick to point
of constant principles in situations that differ in
out that differences in moral judgments from cul-
concrete details. . . . Anthropological evidence
ture to culture do not in themselves prove a differ-
does not furnish proof of relativism. We do
ence in moral standards. Some anthropologists have
not know of societies in which bravery is
made the same argument. Solomon Asch, for exam-
despised and cowardice held up to honor, in
ple, says,
which generosity is considered a vice and
We consider it wrong to take food away from ingratitude a virtue. It seems rather that the
a hungry child, but not if he is overeating. We relations between valuation and meaning are
consider it right to fulfll a promise, but not if it invariant. 5

Subjective relativism also helps people short- of it. If he endorses infanticide as a method of
circuit the unpleasantness of moral debate. Te population control, then infanticide is morally
subjective relativist’s familiar refrain—“Tat permissible. His sincere approval settles the
may be your truth, but it’s not my truth”—has a issue, and he cannot be in error. But our com-
way of stopping conversations and putting an monsense moral experience suggests that this
end to reasoned arguments. relativist account is absurd. Our judgments
Te doctrine, however, is difcult to main- about moral matters—actions, principles, and
tain consistently. On issues that the relativist people—are ofen wide of the mark. We are
cares little about (the moral rightness of gam- morally fallible, and we are rightly suspicious of
bling, say), she may be content to point out that anyone who claims to be otherwise.
moral norms are relative to each individual and Tere is a more disturbing way to frame this
that “to each his own.” But on more momentous point. Suppose former Iraqi leader Saddam
topics (such as genocide in Africa or the Middle Hussein approved of slaughtering thousands of
East), she may slip back into objectivism and de- Iraqis during his reign. Suppose Hitler approved
clare that genocide is morally wrong—not just of killing millions of Jews during World War II.
wrong for her but wrong period. Suppose American serial killer and cannibal
Such inconsistencies hint that there may be Jefrey Dahmer approved of his murdering 17
something amiss with subjective relativism, and men and boys. Ten by the lights of subjective
indeed there is: It seems to confict violently relativism, all these mass killings were morally
with commonsense realities of the moral life. right because their perpetrators deemed them
For one thing, the doctrine implies that each so. But we would fnd this conclusion almost
person is morally infallible. An action is morally impossible to swallow. We would think these
right for someone if he approves of it—if he sin- actions morally wrong whether the killers ap-
cerely believes it to be right. His approval makes proved of their own actions or not.
the action right, and—if his approval is Subjective relativism also implies that another
genuine—he cannot be mistaken. His believing commonplace of the moral life is an illusion:
it to be right makes it right, and that’s the end moral disagreement. Consider: Hernando tells
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 15

Sophia that allowing seriously impaired infants Let us look frst at premise 2. All sorts of em-
to die is morally right. Sophia replies that allow- pirical evidence—including a trove of anthro-
ing seriously impaired infants to die is morally pological and sociological data—show that the
wrong. We may think that Hernando and Sophia premise is in fact true. Clearly, the moral beliefs
are having a straightforward disagreement over of people from diverse cultures ofen do difer
an important moral issue. But according to sub- drastically on the same moral issue. Some soci-
jective relativism, no such disagreement is hap- eties condone infanticide; others condemn it.
pening or could ever happen. In stating his Some approve of the killing of wives and daugh-
approval of the actions in question, Hernando is ters to protect a family’s honor; others think this
essentially expressing his personal taste on the tradition evil. Some bury their dead; others cre-
issue, and Sophia is expressing her personal taste. mate them. Some judge the killing of one’s elders
He is saying he likes something; she says she does to be a kindly act; others say it is cold-hearted
not like it—and they could both be correct. Sub- murder. Some think polygamy morally permis-
jective relativism implies that they are not utter- sible; others believe it deplorable. Some consider
ing conficting claims at all—they are discussing it a solemn duty to surgically remove the clito-
diferent subjects, their own personal feelings or rises of young girls; others say this is immoral
preferences. But this strange dance is not at all and cruel. Some commend the killing of people
what we think we are doing when we have a who practice a diferent religion; others believe
moral disagreement. Because subjective relativ- such intolerance is morally reprehensible. We
ism conficts with what we take to be a basic fact are forced to conclude that diversity of moral
of the moral life, we have good reason to doubt it. judgments among cultures is a reality.
Cultural relativism seems to many to be a But what of premise 1—is it also true? It says
much more plausible doctrine. In fact, many that because cultures have diferent moral be-
people think it obviously true, supported as it is liefs, they must also have diferent moral stan-
by a convincing argument and the common con- dards, which means morality is relative to
viction that it is admirably consistent with social cultures. If diverse moral standards arise from
tolerance and understanding in a pluralistic each culture, then morality cannot be objective,
world. Te argument in its favor goes like this: applying to all people everywhere. Tere is no
objective morality, just moralities.
1. If people’s moral judgments difer from
Premise 1, however, is false. First, from the
culture to culture, moral norms are
fact that cultures have divergent moral beliefs
relative to culture (there are no objective
on an issue, it does not logically follow that there
moral standards).
is no objective moral truth to be sought, that
2. People’s moral judgments do difer from
there is no opinion that is objectively correct.
culture to culture.
People may disagree about the existence of bio-
3. Terefore, moral norms are relative to
logical life on Mars, but the disagreement does
culture (there are no objective moral
not demonstrate that there is no fact of the
standards).
matter or that no statement on the subject could
Is this a good argument? Tat is, does it pro- be objectively true. Disagreements on a moral
vide us with good reason to accept the conclu- question may simply indicate that there is an ob-
sion (statement 3)? For an argument to be good, jective fact of the matter but that someone (or
its conclusion must follow logically from the everyone) is wrong about it.
premises, and the premises must be true. In this Second, a confict between moral beliefs does
case, the conclusion does indeed follow logically not necessarily indicate a fundamental confict
from the premises (statements 1 and 2). Te between basic moral norms. Moral disagree-
truth of the premises is another matter. ments between cultures can arise not just
16 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

because their basic moral principles clash, but cannot legitimately criticize other cultures. If a
because they have difering nonmoral beliefs culture approves of its actions, then those ac-
that put those principles in a very diferent light. tions are morally right—and it does not matter
From the annals of anthropology, for example, one bit whether another culture disapproves of
we have the classic story of a culture that sanc- them. Remember, there is no objective moral
tions the killing of parents when they become code to appeal to. Each society is its own maker
elderly but not yet enfeebled. Our society would of the moral law. It makes no sense for society X
condemn such a practice, no doubt appealing to to accuse society Y of immorality, for what soci-
moral precepts urging respect for parents and ety Y approves of is moral. Some may be willing
for human life. But consider: Tis strange (to us) to accept this consequence of cultural relativ-
culture believes that people enter heaven when ism, but look at what it would mean. What if the
they die and spend eternity in the same physical people of Germany approved of the extermina-
condition they were in when they passed away. tion of millions of Jews, Gypsies, and others
Tose who kill their parents are doing so be- during World War II? Ten the extermination
cause they do not want their elders to spend was morally right. Suppose the people of Libya
eternity in a state of senility but rather in good approved of the terrorist bombing of Pan Am
health. Tis culture’s way is not our way; we are fight 103 over Lockerbie, Scotland, killing 270
unlikely to share these people’s nonmoral be- people (a tragedy for which the Libyan govern-
liefs. But it is probable that they embrace the ment eventually took responsibility). Ten the
same moral principles of respect for parents and bombing was morally right, and those who
life that we do. According to some anthropolo- placed the bomb on board did no wrong. But all
gists, diverse cultures ofen share basic moral this seems very much at odds with our moral
standards while seeming to have little or noth- experience. We think it makes perfect sense
ing in common. sometimes to condemn other cultures for mor-
Te argument we are considering, then, fails ally wrong actions.
to support cultural relativism. Moreover, many Now consider the notion of moral progress.
considerations count strongly against the view. We sometimes compare what people did in the
Specifcally, the logical implications of the doc- past with what they do now, noting that current
trine give us substantial reasons to doubt it. practices are morally better than they used to
Like subjective relativism, cultural relativism be. We no longer countenance such horrors as
implies moral infallibility, a very hard implica- massacres of native peoples, slavery, and lynch-
tion to take seriously. As the doctrine would ings, and we think that these changes are signs
have it, if a culture genuinely approves of an of moral progress. But cultural relativism im-
action, then there can be no question about the plies that there cannot be any such thing as
action’s moral rightness: It is right, and that’s moral progress. To claim legitimately that there
that. Cultures make moral rightness, so they has been moral progress, there must be an ob-
cannot be mistaken about it. But is it at all plau- jective, transcultural standard for comparing
sible that cultures cannot be wrong about moral- cultures of the past and present. But according
ity? Troughout history, cultures have approved to cultural relativism, there are no objective
of ethnic cleansing, slavery, racism, holocausts, moral standards, just norms relative to each cul-
massacres, mass rape, torture of innocents, ture. However, if there is moral progress as we
burning of heretics, and much more. Is it reason- think there is, then there must be objective
able to conclude that the cultures that approved moral standards.
of such deeds could not have been mistaken? Cultural relativism also has a difcult time
Related to the infallibility problem is this dif- explaining the moral status of social reformers.
fculty: Cultural relativism implies that we We tend to believe they are at least sometimes
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 17

right and society is wrong. When we contem- tolerance is morally right for that society. But if
plate social reform, we think of such moral ex- a society approves of intolerance, then intoler-
emplars as Martin Luther King, Jr., Mahatma ance is morally right for that society—and the
Gandhi, and Susan B. Anthony, all of whom ag- society cannot be legitimately criticized for en-
itated for justice and moral progress. But one of dorsing such an attitude. According to cultural
the consequences of cultural relativism is that relativism, intolerance can be morally permissi-
social reformers could never be morally right. ble just as tolerance can. In addition, though
By defnition, what society judges to be morally moral relativists may want to advocate universal
right is morally right, and since social reformers tolerance, they cannot consistently do so. To say
disagree with society, they could not be right— that all cultures should be tolerant is to endorse
ever. But surely on occasion it’s the reformers an objective moral norm, but cultural relativists
who are right and society is wrong. insist that there are no objective moral norms.
Tere is also the serious difculty of using To endorse universal tolerance is to abandon
cultural relativism to make moral decisions. cultural relativism.
Cultural relativism says that moral rightness is
whatever a culture or society approves of, but ethics and religion
determining which culture or society one truly
belongs to seems almost impossible. Te prob- How is ethics related to religion? One obvious
lem is that we each belong to many social groups, connection is that historically religion has
and there is no fact of the matter regarding always had moral content—mostly in the form
which one is our “true” society. Suppose you are of moral precepts, codes, or commandments to
an African American Catholic Republican guide the conduct of adherents. In Western civ-
living in an artists’ colony in Alabama and en- ilization, this content has been so infuential in
joying the advantages of membership in an ex- moral (and legal) matters that many now take
tremely large extended family. What is your true for granted that religion is the fundamental
society? If you cannot identify your proper soci- basis of morality. Secular or nontheistic systems
ety, you cannot tell which cultural norms apply of ethics (for example, the ethics of Stoicism,
to you. Confucianism, Buddhism, utilitarianism, and
Some people may be willing to overlook these contractarianism) have also shaped how we
problems of cultural relativism because they think about morality. But for millions of people,
believe it promotes cultural tolerance, an atti- religion is the fountainhead of the moral law.
tude that seems both morally praiseworthy and Many religious people, however, do not em-
increasingly necessary in a pluralistic world. brace a moral theory related to a religious tradi-
Afer all, human history has been darkened tion. Tey are comfortable being guided by one
repeatedly by the intolerance of one society of the nontheistic systems. Others prefer the
toward another, engendering vast measures of very infuential moral perspective known as
bloodshed, pain, oppression, injustice, and natural law theory (discussed in Chapter 2)—a
ignorance. Te thought is that because all view that comes in both secular and religious
cultures are morally equal, there is no objective versions but has been nurtured and adopted by
reason for criticizing any of them. Tolerance is the Roman Catholic Church. Still others accept
then the best policy. the pervasive idea that morality itself comes
Cultural relativism, however, does not neces- from God.
sarily lead to tolerance and certainly does not An important query in ethics is whether this
logically entail it. In fact, cultural relativism can latter view of morality is correct: whether mo-
easily justify either tolerance or intolerance. It rality depends fundamentally on religion,
says that if a society sanctions tolerance, then whether—to state the question in its traditional
18 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

form—the moral law is constituted by the will of the traditional religious idea of the goodness of
God. Te view that morality does have this kind God would become an empty notion. If God
of dependence is known as the divine command makes the moral law, then the moral term good
theory. It says that right actions are those com- would mean “commanded by God.” But then
manded by God, and wrong actions are those “God is good” would mean something like “God
forbidden by God. God is the author of the does what God commands” or even “God is
moral law, making right and wrong by his will. what God is,” which tells us nothing about the
But many people—both religious and goodness of God. Likewise, “God’s commands
nonreligious—have found this doctrine trou- are good” would translate as “God’s commands
bling. Philosophers have generally rejected it, are God’s commands.” Tis attempt to escape
including some famous theistic thinkers such as the charge of arbitrariness seems to have intol-
Tomas Aquinas (1225–1274), Gottfried Leibniz erable implications.
(1646–1710), and Immanuel Kant (1724–1804). Teists and nontheists alike fnd this horn of
Te problem is that the theory presents us Socrates’s dilemma—the idea of an arbitrary, di-
with a disconcerting dilemma frst spelled out vinely ordained morality—incredible. Tey
in Plato’s Euthyphro. In this dialogue, Socrates therefore reject the divine command theory and
asks a penetrating question that is ofen ex- embrace the other horn, the view that right and
pressed like this: Are actions morally right be- wrong are independent of God’s will. Moral stan-
cause God commands them, or does God dards are external to God, binding on both God
command them because they are morally right? and mortals. If there are divine commands, they
In the frst option, God creates the moral law will conform to these independent moral norms.
(the divine command theory); in the second, the Te religious may then claim that God is good—
moral law is independent of God’s will so that good because he abides perfectly by the moral law
even God is subject to it. Critics of the divine and guides the conduct of believers accordingly.
command theory have argued that the frst If moral standards are not grounded in the
option implies the moral law is entirely arbi- divine will, if they are logically independent of
trary. Te second option denies the theory. religion, then morality is a legitimate concern
Te arbitrariness is thought to arise like this: for the religious and nonreligious alike, and ev-
If actions are morally right just because God eryone has equal access to moral refection and
commands them to be so, then it is possible that the moral life. Te best evidence for the latter is
any actions whatsoever could be morally right. ethics itself. Te fact is that people do ethics.
Te murder and rape of innocents, the oppres- Tey use critical reasoning and experience to
sion of the weak, the abuse of the poor—these determine moral norms, explore ethical issues,
and many other awful deeds would be morally test moral theories, and live a good life. Te re-
permissible if God so willed. Tere would be no sults of these explorations are moral outlooks
independent standard to judge that these acts and standards founded on good reasons and ar-
are wrong, no moral reasons apart from God’s guments and assented to by refective people
will to suggest that such deeds are evil. God everywhere.
would be free to establish arbitrarily any actions In bioethics, the informed opinions of reli-
whatsoever as morally right. gious people are as relevant as those of secular-
Defenders of the divine command theory ists. But all parties must be willing to submit
have replied to the arbitrariness charge by their views to the tests and criteria of critical
saying that God would never command some- reasoning and evidence.
thing evil because God is all-good. But critics But even if ethics does not have this indepen-
point out that if the theory is true, the assertion dent status, there are still good reasons for reli-
that God is all-good would be meaningless, and gious believers to know how to use the critical
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 19

tools that ethics ofers. First, like many secular of arguments. As you may have guessed, here
moral rules, religious moral codes are ofen argument denotes not an altercation but a pat-
vague and difcult to apply to conficts and terned set of assertions: at least one statement
issues, especially in complex felds such as bio- providing support for another statement. We
ethics. Getting around this problem requires have an argument when one or more statements
interpreting the codes, and this task involves give us reasons for believing another one. Te
consideration of broader norms or theories, a supporting statements are premises, and the
typical job for ethics. Second, like everyone else, supported statement is the conclusion. In critical
believers must deal with moral conficts of all reasoning, the term statement also has a techni-
sorts—including clashes between the moral be- cal meaning. A statement (or claim) is an asser-
liefs of religious adherents, religious leaders, tion that something is or is not the case and is
and religious traditions. What is ofen needed is therefore the kind of utterance that is either true
a neutral standard and critical analyses to arrive or false.
at a resolution—tools that ethics can easily pro- You need to understand at the outset that
vide. Tird, public debate on ethical issues in a argument in this sense is not synonymous with
diverse society requires ground rules—chief persuasion. An argument provides us with rea-
among them being that positions must be sons for accepting a claim; it is an attempted
explained and reasons must be given in their “proof ” for an assertion. But persuasion does
support. Unexplained assertions without sup- not necessarily involve giving any reasons at
porting reasons or arguments are likely to be all for accepting a claim. To persuade is to in-
ignored. In this arena, ethics is essential. fuence people’s opinions, which can be accom-
plished by ofering a good argument but also
moral arguments by misleading with logical fallacies, exploiting
emotions and prejudices, dazzling with rhetor-
Critical reasoning is something we employ every ical gimmicks, hiding or distorting the facts,
time we carefully and systematically assess the threatening or coercing people—the list is
truth of a statement or the merits of a logical argu- long. Good arguments prove something
ment. We ask: Are there good reasons for believing whether or not they persuade. Persuasive ploys
this statement? Is this a good argument—does it can change minds but do not necessarily prove
prove its case? Tese sorts of questions are asked anything.
in every academic feld and in every serious So we formulate an argument to try to show
human endeavor. Wherever there is a need to ac- that a particular claim (the conclusion) should be
quire knowledge, to separate truth from falsity, believed, and we analyze an argument to see if it
and to come to a reliable understanding of how really does show what it purports to show. If the
the world works, these questions are asked and argument is good, we are entitled to believe its con-
answers are sought. Ethics is no exception. Criti- clusion. If it is bad, we are not entitled to believe it.
cal reasoning in ethics—called moral reasoning— Consider these two simple arguments:
employs the same general principles of logic and
Argument 1
evidence that guide the search for truth in every
Law enforcement in the city is a complete
other feld. So we need not wonder whether we
failure. Incidents of serious crime have
use critical reasoning in ethics but whether we use
doubled.
it well.
Argument 2
Argument Fundamentals It’s wrong to take the life of an innocent per-
Most critical reasoning is concerned in one way son. Abortion takes the life of an innocent
or another with the construction or evaluation person. So abortion is wrong.
20 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

In Argument 1, the conclusion is “Law en- requirements hold for both of them, even though
forcement in the city is a complete failure,” which the logical connections in each type are distinct.
is supported by the premise “Incidents of serious Deductive arguments are intended to give logically
crime have doubled.” Te conclusion of Argu- conclusive support to their conclusions so that if the
ment 2 is “abortion is wrong,” and it is backed by premises are true, the conclusion absolutely must
two premises: “It’s wrong to take the life of an be true.Argument 2 is a deductive argument and is
innocent person” and “Abortion takes the life of therefore supposed to be constructed so that if the
an innocent person.” Despite the diferences be- two premises are true, its conclusion cannot possi-
tween these two passages (diferences in content, bly be false. Here it is with its structure laid bare:
the number of premises, and the order of their
argument 2
parts), they are both arguments because they ex-
1. It’s wrong to take the life of an innocent
emplify basic argument structure: a conclusion
person.
supported by at least one premise.
2. Abortion takes the life of an innocent
Tough the components of an argument
person.
seem clear enough, people ofen fail to distin-
3. Terefore, abortion is wrong.
guish between arguments and strong statements
that contain no arguments at all. Suppose we Do you see that, given the form or structure
change Argument 1 into this: of this argument, if the premises are true, then
the conclusion has to be true? It would be very
Law enforcement in the city is a complete
strange—illogical, in fact—to agree that the two
failure. Nothing seems to work anymore.
premises are true but that the conclusion is false.
Tis situation is intolerable.
Now look at this one:
Now there is no argument, just an expression
argument 3
of annoyance or anger. Tere are no statements
1. All dogs are mammals.
giving us reasons to believe a conclusion. What
2. Rex is a dog.
we have are some unsupported assertions that
3. Terefore, Rex is a mammal.
may merely appear to make a case. If we ignore
the distinction between genuine arguments and Again, there is no way for the premises to be
nonargumentative material, critical reasoning is true while the conclusion is false. Te deductive
undone. form of the argument guarantees this.
Assuming we can recognize an argument So a deductive argument is intended to have
when we see it, how can we tell if it is a good this sort of airtight structure. If it actually does
one? Fortunately, the general criteria for judging have this structure, it is said to be valid. Argu-
the merits of an argument are simple and clear. ment 2 is deductive because it is intended to
A good argument—one that gives us good rea- provide logically conclusive support to its con-
sons for believing a claim—must have (1) solid clusion. It is valid because, as a matter of fact, it
logic and (2) true premises. Requirement (1) does ofer this kind of support. A deductive ar-
means that the conclusion should follow logi- gument that fails to provide conclusive support
cally from the premises, that there must be a to its conclusion is said to be invalid. In such an
proper logical connection between supporting argument, it is possible for the premises to be
statements and the statement supported. true and the conclusion false. Argument 3 is in-
Requirement (2) says that what the premises tended to have a deductive form, and because it
assert must in fact be the case. An argument actually does have this form, the argument is
that fails in either respect is a bad argument. also valid.
Tere are two basic kinds of arguments— An elementary fact about deductive argu-
deductive and inductive—and our two ments is that their validity (or lack thereof) is a
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 21

separate issue from the truth of the premises. 2. Sonia is a student at this university.
Validity is a structural matter, depending en- 3. Terefore, Sonia is probably a Republican.
tirely on how an argument is put together. Truth Tis argument is strong. If its premises are
concerns the nature of the claims made in the true, its conclusion is likely to be true. If 85
premises and conclusion. A deductive argument percent of the university’s students are Republi-
is supposed to be built so that if the premises are cans, and Sonia is a university student, she is
true, the conclusion must be true—but in a par- more likely than not to be a Republican, too.
ticular case, the premises might not be true. A When a valid (deductive) argument has true
valid argument can have true or false premises premises, it is a good argument. A good deduc-
and a true or false conclusion. (By defnition, of tive argument is said to be sound. Argument 2 is
course, it cannot have true premises and a false valid, but we cannot say whether it is sound until
conclusion.) In any case, being invalid or having we determine the truth of the premises. Argu-
false premises dooms a deductive argument. ment 3 is valid, and if its premises are true, it is
Inductive arguments are supposed to give sound. When a strong (inductive) argument has
probable support to their conclusions. Unlike true premises, it is also a good argument. A good
deductive arguments, they are not designed to inductive argument is said to be cogent. Argu-
support their conclusions decisively. Tey can ment 1 is weak, so there is no way it can be
establish only that, if their premises are true, cogent. Argument 4 is strong, and if its premises
their conclusions are probably true (more likely are true, it is cogent.
to be true than not). Argument 1 is an inductive Checking the validity or strength of an argu-
argument meant to demonstrate the probable ment is ofen a plain, commonsense undertaking.
truth that “law enforcement in the city is a com- Using our natural reasoning ability, we can ex-
plete failure.” Like all inductive arguments (and amine how the premises are linked to the conclu-
unlike deductive ones), it can have true premises sion and can see quickly whether the conclusion
and a false conclusion. So the sole premise— follows from the premises. We are most likely to
“incidents of serious crime have doubled”—can make an easy job of it when the arguments are
be true while the conclusion is false. simple. Many times, however, we need some help,
If inductive arguments succeed in lending and help is available in the form of methods and
very probable support to their conclusions, they guidelines for evaluating arguments.
are said to be strong. Strong arguments are such Having a familiarity with common argument
that if their premises are true, their conclusions patterns, or forms, is especially useful when as-
are very probably true. If they fail to provide this sessing the validity of deductive arguments. We
very probable support, they are termed weak. are likely to encounter these forms again and
Argument 1 is a weak argument because its again in bioethics as well as in everyday life.
premise, even if true, does not show that more Here is a prime example:
likely than not law enforcement in the city is a
complete failure. Afer all, even if incidents of argument 5
serious crime have doubled, law enforcement 1. If the surgeon operates, then the patient
may be successful in other ways, or incidents of will be cured.
serious crime may be up for reasons unrelated to 2. Te surgeon is operating.
the efectiveness of law enforcement. 3. Terefore, the patient will be cured.
But consider this inductive argument:
Tis argument form contains a conditional
argument 4 premise—that is, a premise consisting of a
1. Eighty-fve percent of the students at this conditional, or if-then, statement (actually a com-
university are Republicans. pound statement composed of two constituent
22 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

statements). Premise 1 is a conditional statement. affirming the consequent


A conditional statement has two parts: the part argument 7
beginning with if (called the antecedent) and the 1. If the patient is getting better, then drugs
part beginning with then (known as the conse- are unnecessary.
quent). So the antecedent of premise 1 is “If the 2. Drugs are unnecessary.
surgeon operates,” and the consequent is “then 3. Terefore, the patient is getting better.
the patient will be cured.”
Te best way to appreciate the structure of 1. If p, then q.
such an argument (or any deductive argument, 2. q.
for that matter) is to translate it into traditional 3. Terefore, p.
argument symbols in which each statement is
symbolized by a letter. Here is the symboliza- denying the antecedent
tion for Argument 5: argument 8
1. If the rate of infection is increasing, then
1. If p, then q.
the patients will die.
2. p.
2. Te rate of infection is not increasing.
3. Terefore, q.
3. Terefore, the patients will not die.
We can see that p represents “the surgeon op-
erates,” and q represents “the patient will be 1. If p, then q.
cured.” But notice that we can use this same 2. Not p.
symbolized argument form to represent count- 3. Terefore, not q.
less other arguments—arguments with diferent
Te advantage of being able to recognize
statements but having the same basic structure.
these and other common argument forms is that
It just so happens that the underlying argument
you can use that skill to determine readily the
form for Argument 5 is extremely common—
validity of many deductive arguments. You
common enough to have a name, modus ponens
know, for example, that any argument having
(or afrming the antecedent). Te truly useful fact
the same form as modus ponens or modus
about modus ponens is that any argument having
tollens must be valid, and any argument in one
this form is valid. We can plug any statements we
of the common invalid forms must be invalid.
want into the formula and the result will be a valid
argument, a circumstance in which if the prem-
ises are true, the conclusion must be true. Patterns of Moral Arguments
Another common argument form is modus All that you have learned about argument fun-
tollens (or denying the consequent). For example: damentals thus far applies directly to that sub-
species of argument we are most interested in:
argument 6 moral argument. A moral argument is an
1. If the dose is low, then the healing is slow. argument whose conclusion is a moral state-
2. Te healing is not slow. ment, an assertion that an action is right or
3. Terefore, the dose is not low. wrong or that a person or motive is good
or bad. We utter a moral statement when we
1. If p, then q.
say such things as “Physician-assisted suicide
2. Not q.
is wrong,” or “Maria should not have had an
3. Terefore, not p.
abortion,” or “Dr. Jones is a good person.” We
Modus tollens is also a valid form, and any are constantly making moral statements and
argument using this form must also be valid. including them in our moral arguments, which
Tere are also common argument forms that we frequently devise and hold up for inspec-
are invalid. Here are two of them: tion and evaluation.
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 23

Review: Valid and Invalid Argument Forms

Valid Forms
Affrming the Antecedent (Modus Ponens) Denying the Consequent (Modus Tollens)
If p, then q. If p, then q.
p. Not q.
Therefore, q. Therefore, not p.

Example: Example:
If Spot barks, a burglar is in the house. If it’s raining, the park is closed.
Spot is barking. The park is not closed.
Therefore, a burglar is in the house. Therefore, it’s not raining.

Invalid Forms
Affrming the Consequent Denying the Antecedent
If p, then q. If p, then q.
q. Not p.
Therefore, p. Therefore, not q.

Example: Example:
If the cat is on the mat, she is asleep. If the cat is on the mat, she is asleep.
She is asleep. She is not on the mat.
Therefore, she is on the mat. Therefore, she is not asleep.

Recall Argument 2, a simple (and common) action) is wrong, for example, we must provide a
moral argument: reason for this moral judgment. Te natural
(and logical) move is to reach for a general moral
1. It’s wrong to take the life of an innocent
principle that supports the judgment. Why is
person.
performing surgery on Mrs. Johnson without
2. Abortion takes the life of an innocent person.
her consent wrong? Because, we might say,
3. Terefore, abortion is wrong.
treating people without their consent is a viola-
Here, we can see all the standard features of a tion of their autonomy (a moral principle), and
typical moral argument: (1) At least one premise performing surgery on Mrs. Johnson without
(premise 1) is a moral statement asserting a gen- her consent would be an instance of such a vio-
eral moral norm such as a moral principle; (2) at lation (a nonmoral fact).
least one premise (premise 2) is a nonmoral Tis natural way of proceeding refects the
statement describing an action or circumstance; logical realities of moral reasoning. In a moral
and (3) the conclusion is a moral statement ex- argument, we must have at least one moral
pressing a moral judgment about a specifc premise to draw a conclusion about the moral-
action or circumstance. ity of a particular state of afairs. Without a
Notice how natural this pattern seems. If we moral premise, we cannot legitimately arrive at
want to argue that a particular action (or kind of a moral conclusion. Tat is, from a nonmoral
24 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

must stand or fall on its own merits. The personal


I N D E P TH characteristics of the person espousing the view do
not necessarily have a bearing on its truth. Only if
FALLACIES IN MORAL
we can show that someone’s dubious traits some-
REASONING how make the claim dubious are we justifed in re-
jecting the claim because of a person’s personal
characteristics. Such a circumstance is rare.
The world is full of bad arguments. Many of them
occur again and again in different guises and con-
APPEAL TO IGNORANCE
texts, being so common that they have been given
As its name implies, this fallacy tries to prove some-
names and are studied by those who wish to avoid
thing by appealing to what we don’t know. The
such mistakes. These common, defective arguments
appeal to ignorance is arguing either that (1) a claim
are called fallacies. Here are a few that often crop up
is true because it has not been proven false or (2) a
in moral reasoning.
claim is false because it has not been proven true.
STRAW MAN For example:
The straw man fallacy is the misrepresentation of a No one has proven that a fetus is not a person, so it
person’s views so they can be more easily attacked is in fact a person.
or dismissed. Suppose you argue that because an
immunization program will save the lives of thou- It is obviously false that a fetus is a person because
sands of children and will likely cause the death of science has not proven that it is a person.
only 1 child out of every 500,000, we should fund The frst argument tries to prove a claim by
the immunization program. But then your oppo- pointing out that it has not been proven false. The
nent replies that you think the life of a child isn’t second argument tries to prove that a claim is
worth much. Thus, your point has been distorted, false because it has not been proven true. Both
made to look extreme or unsavory—and is now an kinds of arguments are bogus because they
easier target. The straw man fallacy, of course, assume that a lack of evidence proves something.
proves nothing, though many people fall for it But a lack of evidence can prove nothing. Being
every day. ignorant of the facts does not enlighten us. Notice
that if a lack of evidence could prove something,
APPEAL TO THE PERSON then you could prove just about anything you
Closely related to the straw man fallacy is appeal to wanted. You could reason, for instance, that since
the person (also known as the ad hominem fallacy). no one can prove that horses cannot fy, horses
Appeal to the person is the rejecting of a statement must be able to fy.
on the grounds that it comes from a particular
person, not because the statement, or claim, itself is
false or dubious. For example: BEGGING THE QUESTION
The fallacy of begging the question is trying to prove
You can safely discard anything that Susan has to
a conclusion by using that very same conclusion as
say about abortion. She’s a Catholic.
support. It is arguing in a circle. This way of trying to
Johnson argues that our current health care system prove something says, in effect, “X is true because
is defective. But don’t listen to him—he’s a liberal. X is true.” Here is a classic example:

These arguments are defective because they ask The Bible says that God exists.
us to reject a claim because of a person’s character,
The Bible is true because God wrote it.
background, or circumstances—things that are gen-
erally irrelevant to the truth of claims. A statement Therefore, God exists.
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 25

The conclusion here (“God exists”) is supported SLIPPERY SLOPE


by premises that assume that very conclusion. The metaphor behind this fallacy suggests the
Here’s another one: danger of stepping on a dicey incline, losing your
footing, and sliding to disaster. The fallacy of slip-
All citizens have the right to a fair trial because
pery slope, then, is arguing erroneously that a par-
those whom the state is obliged to protect and give
ticular action should not be taken because it will
consideration are automatically due judicial criminal
lead inevitably to other actions resulting in some
proceedings that are equitable by any reasonable
dire outcome. The key word here is erroneously. A
standard.
slippery slope scenario becomes fallacious when
This passage may at frst seem like a good ar- there is no reason to believe that the chain of
gument, but it isn’t. It reduces to this unimpres- events predicted will ever happen. For example:
sive assertion: “All citizens have the right to a fair
If dying patients are permitted to refuse treatment,
trial because all citizens have the right to a fair
then soon doctors will be refusing the treatment on
trial.” The conclusion is “All citizens have the
their behalf. Then physician-assisted suicide will
right to a fair trial,” but that is more or less what
become rampant, and soon killing patients for
the premise says. The premise—“those whom
almost any reason will become the norm.
the state is obliged to protect and give consider-
ation are automatically due judicial criminal pro- This argument is fallacious because there are no
ceedings that are equitable by any reasonable reasons for believing that the frst step will ultimately
standard”—is equivalent to “All citizens have the result in the chain of events described. If good rea-
right to a fair trial.” sons could be given, the argument might be salvaged.

premise alone, a moral conclusion does not premise what we take to be the nonmoral fact
logically follow. For example, from the non- of the matter.
moral fact that abortions are frequently per- Tis discussion underscores a previously
formed, we cannot conclude that abortion is mentioned fact about moral disagreements.
immoral. Nonmoral premises cannot support a When people disagree on a moral issue, they
conclusion expressing a moral judgment. Like- may or may not be disagreeing about moral
wise, we cannot reason from a moral premise principles. Tey may actually share the relevant
alone (one afrming a general moral principle) moral principles but disagree about the non-
to a conclusion about the morality of a particu- moral facts—or vice versa. So when people take
lar action. We need a nonmoral premise af- contradictory stands on the conclusion of a
frming that the particular action in question is moral argument, the source of the confict could
an instance of the general class of actions re- lie with the moral premises or the nonmoral
ferred to in the general moral premise. In Ar- premises or both.
gument 2, the moral premise tells us it’s wrong Unfortunately, in everyday life moral argu-
to take the life of an innocent person, but we ments do not come with their premises clearly
need the nonmoral premise to assert that abor- labeled, so we need to be able to identify the
tion is an instance of taking the life of an inno- premises ourselves. Tis job is made more dif-
cent person. Afer all, that a fetus is a cult by a simple fact of the moral life: Ofen
person—the kind of entity that is deserving of premises (moral and nonmoral) are lef unsaid
full moral rights—is not obviously true and not and are merely implied. Sometimes premises are
assented to by everyone. We must spell out in a unstated because they are obvious assumptions
26 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

that need not be mentioned. But if we are to per- or strong and will be plausible in the context of
form a thorough evaluation of an argument, we the argument. Te most straightforward ap-
must drag the implicit premises into the open so proach, however, is to treat the argument as
they can be fully assessed. Such careful scrutiny deductive and look for a premise that will
is especially important in moral arguments be- make the argument valid, as we did in Argu-
cause the implicit premises are ofen question- ment 9.
able assumptions—the secret, weak links in the
chain of reasoning. For example: Evaluating Premises
As we have seen, good arguments have true
argument 9
premises. But how do we know if the premises
1. In vitro fertilization is an entirely
are true? Fortunately, there are ways to test, or
unnatural process, as far from natural
evaluate, the truth of premises. Te tests difer,
reproduction as one could imagine.
however, depending on whether the premises
2. Terefore, in vitro fertilization should not
are nonmoral or moral.
be used.
Checking the truth of nonmoral premises
As it stands, this is a bad argument; the con- can involve the exploration of either empirical
clusion does not follow from the premise. But or conceptual matters. An empirical belief, or
there is an implied (moral) premise lurking claim, is one that can be confrmed by sense
here, and if we make it explicit, the argument experience—that is, by observation or scientifc
will be valid: investigation. Most nonmoral premises are em-
pirical claims that we can check by examining
1. In vitro fertilization is an entirely
our own experience or that of others or by con-
unnatural process, as far from natural
sulting the relevant scientifc fndings. By these
reproduction as one could imagine.
methods we can test (and support) a wide vari-
2. Any process that is unnatural should not
ety of empirical assertions, such as many of the
be used.
nonmoral premises examined earlier: “Inci-
3. Terefore, in vitro fertilization should not
dents of serious crime have doubled”; “Eighty-
be used.
fve percent of the students at this university are
Now the argument is complete, and we can Republicans”; “If the patient is getting better,
see both the nonmoral premise (premise 1) and then drugs are unnecessary.”
the moral premise (premise 2), which is a moral In bioethics, among the most controversial
principle. But now that we have brought the nonmoral premises are those afrming that a
moral premise into the light of day, we can see medical treatment or program will or will not
that it is false or at least debatable. We use many have a particular efect on people. Te issue is
processes and products that are unnatural (for whether it will help or harm and to what degree.
example, modern pharmaceuticals, intravenous Sometimes reliable data are available to resolve
feeding, surgery, CAT scans, artifcial limbs, the issue. Sometimes no clear evidence exists,
and contact lenses), but we generally do not leaving people to make educated guesses that
regard them as morally impermissible. are ofen in dispute.
Very ofen we can tell that an argument has In any case, critical reasoning in bioethics
an unstated premise because there is a logical demands that we always seek the most reliable
leap between the stated premises and the con- evidence available and try to assess its worth ob-
clusion. Te inference from stated premises to jectively. It requires that our empirical claims be
conclusion does not work unless the missing supported by good empirical evidence and that
premise is supplied. A good candidate for the we expect the same from others who make em-
implicit premise will make the argument valid pirical assertions.
Chapter 1: Moral Reasoning in Bioethics 27

A conceptual matter has to do with the accepted by all parties so that further support
meaning of terms, something we need to pay at- for the principle is not necessary. At other times,
tention to because disputes in bioethics some- the higher principle itself may be controversial
times hinge on the meaning of a concept. For and in need of support.
example, in disagreements about the moral per- Moral premises can also be supported by a
missibility of abortion, the crux of the matter is moral theory, a general explanation of what
ofen how the disputants defne person (as in Ar- makes an action right or a person or motive
gument 2), or human life, or human being. Simi- good. (In Chapter 2 we discuss moral theories in
larly, whether someone supports or opposes depth.) For example, traditional utilitarianism
euthanasia ofen hangs on how it is defned. is a moral theory afrming that right actions are
Some, for example, defne it in the narrow sense those that produce the greatest happiness for all
of taking direct action to kill someone for his concerned. Appealing to utilitarianism, then,
sake (mercy killing), while others insist on a someone might insist that a baby born with
wider sense that encompasses both mercifully severe brain damage who will die within a few
killing and allowing to die. Whether we are de- days should not be allowed to wither slowly
vising our own arguments or evaluating those away in pain but should be given a lethal injec-
of others, being clear on the meaning of terms is tion. Te justifcation for this policy is that it
essential, and any proposed defnition must be would produce the least amount of unhappiness
backed by good reasons. (including pain and sufering) for all concerned,
Moral premises are like nonmoral ones in including baby, parents, and caregivers. Tose
that they, too, should be supported by good rea- who reject this policy would have to argue that
sons and be subjected to serious scrutiny. But there was something wrong with utilitarianism
just how are moral premises supported and or that other considerations (including alterna-
scrutinized? tive theories) outweigh utilitarian concerns.
Support for a moral premise (a moral princi- Another possible source of support for moral
ple or standard) can come from at least three premises is what philosophers call our consid-
sources: other moral principles, moral theories, ered moral judgments. Tese are moral judg-
or our most reliable moral judgments. Probably ments we deem plausible or credible afer careful
the most common way to support a moral prin- refection that is as unbiased as possible. Tey
ciple is to appeal to a higher-level principle may apply to both particular cases and more
(which ofen turns out to be one of the four general moral statements. For example, afer de-
major moral principles discussed earlier). Sup- liberation we might conclude that “inficting
pose the moral premise in question is “Te pa- undeserved and unnecessary pain on someone
tient’s wishes about whether surgery is is wrong,” or that “emergency care for accident
performed on him should not be ignored.” Some victims should be provided regardless of their
would argue that this principle is derived from, race or religion,” or that “amputating a patient’s
or is based on, the higher principle that autono- leg for no good reason is never morally permis-
mous persons should be allowed to exercise sible.” Like moral principles and theories, such
their capacity for self-determination. Or let’s say judgments can vary in how much weight they
the premise is “Individuals in a persistent vege- carry in moral arguments and can be given
tative state should never have their feeding tubes more or less credibility (or undermined com-
removed so they can ‘die with dignity.’” Many pletely) by relevant reasons. (We examine more
would base this assertion on the principle that closely the relationships among theories, princi-
human life is sacred and should be preserved at ples, and considered judgments in Chapter 2.)
all costs. Frequently, the higher principle ap- Moral premises can be called into question
pealed to is plausible, seemingly universal, or by showing that they somehow confict with
28 PA R T 1: P R I N C I P L E S A N D T H E O R I E S

credible principles, theories, or judgments. One descriptions, examples, amplifcations, or irrele-


way to do this is to cite counterexamples, in- vancies. So how do we evaluate such arguments in
stances in which the moral principle in question the rough?
seems not to hold. Recall that a counterexample Following this procedure will help:
helps us see that the moral premise in Argument
9 is dubious. Te premise says “Any process that Step 1. Study the text until you thoroughly un-
is unnatural should not be used,” but we ofen derstand it. You can’t locate the conclusion or
use unnatural products or processes (CAT scans premises until you know what you’re looking for—
and contact lenses, for instance) and do not and that requires having a clear idea of what the
think these actions morally wrong. In the same author is driving at. Don’t attempt to fnd the con-
way, we can use counterexamples to evaluate the clusion or premises until you “get it.” Tis under-
moral premise in Argument 2: standing entails having an overview of a great deal
of text, a bird’s-eye view of the whole work.
1. It’s wrong to take the life of an innocent Step 2. Find the conclusion. When you evaluate
person. arguments surrounded by a lot of other prose,
2. Abortion takes the life of an innocent your frst task is to fnd the conclusion. Tere
person. may be a single conclusion, or several main
3. Terefore, abortion is wrong. conclusions, or one primary conclusion with
Are there no exceptions to premise 1? Is it several subconclusions. Or the conclusion may
always wrong to kill an innocent person? We be nowhere explicitly stated but embodied in
can imagine cases in which this premise seems metaphorical language or implied by large ex-
either doubtful or at least not obviously true. panses of prose. In any case, your job is to come
What about situations in which many lives can up with a single conclusion statement for each
be saved by taking the life of one person? What conclusion—even if you have to paraphrase large
if all 50 people in a lifeboat at sea will drown sections of text to do it. When you identify the
unless one of them is cast overboard? What if conclusion, the hunt for premises gets easier.
the one unlucky person agrees to be cast over- Step 3. Identify the premises. Like the search
board to save all the others? Or suppose a person for a conclusion, unearthing the premises may
is dying of cancer and is sufering unspeakable involve condensing large sections of text into
pain that cannot be relieved by any medical manageable form—namely, single premise state-
means—and she begs for a lethal injection of ments. To do this, you need to disregard extra-
morphine. Some would argue that these scenar- neous material and keep your eye on the “big
ios raise serious questions about premise 1, sug- picture.” Remember that in moral arguments
gesting that at least in its current form, it may you are looking for both moral and nonmoral
not be true. In response to these counterexam- premises.
ples, some who wish to defend the premise Let’s see how this procedure works on the fol-
might modify it to take the scenarios into ac- lowing passage:
count or even try to show that despite its impli-
cations premise 1 is justifed. [1] John and Nancy Jones had a 2-year-old son
who sufered from a serious but very curable
Assessing Whole Arguments bowel obstruction. [2] For religious reasons, the
Moral argument, like any other kind of argu- Joneses decide to treat their son with prayer in-
ments, usually come to us embedded in larger stead of modern medicine. [3] Tey refused med-
tracts of speech or writing. Ofen the premises and ical treatment even though they were told by
conclusion are embellished or obscured by other several doctors that the child would die unless
elements—by explanations, asides, reiterations, medically treated. [4] As it turned out, the boy
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
kasvatetaan samalla tapaa, ja monessa japanilaisessa kodissa
näkee appelsiinipuita, jotka ovat ainoastaan 15 sm korkuisia ja
kantavat kirsikan kokoisia hedelmiä.

Merkillisimpiä ilmiöitä tämän oudon tarhuritaiteen alalla oli —


kertoo edellämainittu matkustajamme — pienoinen, ainoastaan 2 ½
sm läpimitaten ja 7 ½ sm korkea ruukku, jossa kasvoi mänty,
bamburuoko ja luumupuu, viimemainittu täydessä kukassa. Tämän
harvinaisen puutarhan hinta oli 2,500 mk.

Luonnollisesti valitaan näin surkealla tavalla kidutettaviksi vain


sellaiset kasvit, jotka voivat tulla toimeen mitä epäsuotuisimmissa
olosuhteissa. Ne kaikki totutetaan mitä niukimpaan ravintoon, niin
että ne juuri voivat elää. Ja sen ohessa niitä leikellään ja taivutetaan
mitä monimutkaisimmalla tavalla, niin että ne kadottavat tykkänään
luonnollisen muotonsa ja muistuttavat kurjia rujokkaita, valoa, ilmaa
ja ravintoa vailla kasvaneita ihmisparkoja.

On otaksuttu että Japanin ilmanala on erityisen suotuisa tällaiselle


puutarhuritoimelle; ja totta onkin, etteivät Europassa tehdyt kokeet
ole tuottaneet juuri mitään sentapaisia tuloksia. Suunnatonta
kärsivällisyyttä ja taitoa siihen tarvitaan, ja epäilemättä juuri
japanilaisilla ja kiinalaisilla on ennen muita nämä ominaisuudet.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK LUONNON
IHMEITÄ ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the


Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.
Section 3. Information about the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like