You are on page 1of 12

1190 XIV.

Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

Dahl, Östen (1985), Tense and Aspect Systems. Ox- McCoard, Robert W. (1978), The English Perfect:
ford: Blackwell Tense-Choice and Pragmatic Inferences. Amster-
Dahl, Östen (2000, ed.), Tense and Aspect in the dam: North-Holland
Languages of Europe. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter Montague, Richard (1974), Formal Philosophy, ed.
Fleischman, Suzanne (1983), “From Pragmatics to by Richmond H. Thomason. New Haven/CN: Yale
Grammar: Diachronic Reflections on Complex University Press
Pasts and Futures in Romance”. Lingua 60, 183⫺ Morris, Henry Francis & Kirwan, Brian Edmond
214 Renshaw (1972), A Runyankore Grammar. Nairobi:
Hedin, Eva (1987), On the Use of the Perfect and East African Literature Bureau
the Pluperfect in Modern Greek. Stockholm: Alm- Prior, Arthur (1967), Past, Present, and Future. Ox-
qvist & Wiksell (Acta Universitatis Stockhol- ford: Clarendon Press
miensis: Studia Graeca Stockholmiensia VI) Reichenbach, Hans (1947), Elements of Symbolic
Klein, Wolfgang (1994), Time in Language. Lon- Logic. New York: Collier-Macmillan
don, New York: Routledge Tommola, Hannu (2000), “On the Perfect in North
Leinonen, Marja & Vilkuna, Maria (2000), “Past Slavic”. In: Dahl (ed.), 441⫺478
Tenses in Permian Languages”. In: Dahl (ed.),
495⫺514 Östen Dahl, Stockholm (Sweden)

111. Illocution, mood, and modality

1. Introduction two smaller ones: the first concerns the area


2. Illocution of illocution, the second the area of modality.
3. Modality This subdivision is warranted on semantic
4. Mood
grounds: the category of illocution is con-
5. Uncommon abbreviations
6. References cerned with identifying sentences as instances
of specific types of speech act, whereas the
category of modality is concerned with the
1. Introduction modification of the content of speech acts.
But apart from these semantic differences,
The term mood is used in language descrip- there are also formal reasons to distinguish
tions for the morphological category that between the two areas. As will be shown in
covers the grammatical reflections of a large 4.1, in the expression of illocution the mor-
semantic area. Although the term is applied phological category of mood has to compete
surprisingly consistently across language de- with word order and intonation as markers
scriptions, attempts at defining this semantic of particular subdistinctions, whereas modal-
area in positive terms have never been en- ity is expressed by mood markers only.
tirely successful, in the sense that all defini- In 2 and 3 below the semantic categories
tions proposed leave certain distinctions un- of illocution and modality will be discussed
accounted for. While a positive definition separately. In 4 an inventory of the different
thus seems to require a disjunctive formula- ways of expressing illocutionary and modal
tion, in negative terms the morphological cat- distinctions is given, and the distribution of
egory of mood may be said to comprise all these expression formats across the various
grammatical elements operating on a situa- subdistinctions is specified.
tion/proposition that are not directly con-
cerned with situating an event in the actual
world, as conceived by the speaker. In this 2. Illocution
respect mood differs crucially from tense, as-
pect, and negation, which do have this situat- 2.1. Basic illocution
ing function (Art. 110, 109, 113, respectively). The basic illocution of a sentence can be de-
The large semantic area covered by this fined as the conversational use convention-
negative definition can be subdivided into ally associated with the formal properties of
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1191

that sentence (cf. Sadock & Zwicky 1985: (7) Geber-esi!


155), which together constitute a sentence die.like.a.dog-impr.3.sg
type. Apart from word order and intonation, ‘May he die like a dog!’
these formal properties may include specific
(8) Xiăoxı̄n ou!
mood morphemes, which may in these cases
careful adm
be interpreted as the morphological markers
‘Be careful, OK?’
of basic illocutions. By their very nature, ba-
sic illocutions are restricted to independent In languages not making all the distinctions
sentences and quotations. This feature will be listed here various groupings of basic illocu-
of help in distinguishing illocutionary from tions may occur. The prohibitive may simply
modal categories. be a negative imperative; imperative, opta-
The most frequently attested basic illocu- tive, and hortative may be combined on the
tions are declarative, interrogative, and im- basis of their shared impositive nature; opta-
perative. These are illustrated in the following tive, imprecative, and admonitive may be
examples from Tauya (MacDonald 1990: combined on the basis of their expressive na-
209⫺212): ture; etc.
In 1 a distinction was made between illocu-
(1) Ya-ni tei-mene-amu-? a.
tion and modality as two basic categories that
1.sg-erg catch-stat-1.sg.fut-decl
may be expressed through mood markers.
‘I will have it.’
The importance of this distinction can now
(2) Nen-ni sen-yau-i-nae? be illustrated by comparing some basic illo-
3.pl-erg 1.pl-see-3.pl-int cutions with corresponding modalities. First
‘Did they see us?’ note that declarative, as defined above, is not
the same as indicative. The latter is a mood
(3) Ni-a-e!
category with a wide range of applications,
eat-2.sg.fut-imp
whereas the former is an illocutionary cat-
‘Eat!’
egory. This difference is reflected in the re-
The declarative sentence in (1) is convention- striction that declarative forms are used in
ally associated with an assertion, the inter- main clauses and quotations only, whereas
rogative in (2) with a question, and the im- indicative forms may be used in varying sets
perative in (3) with a command. of subordinate clauses (cf. Bybee 1985: 170).
Apart from these most frequently attested Declarative markers may furthermore freely
basic illocutions there are several others that combine with modal markers that would be
occur with some frequency (cf. Sadock & in conflict with an indicative marker, as in
Zwicky 1985). Among these are prohibitive, the following example, again from Tauya
hortative, and optative, conventionally associ- (MacDonald 1990: 209):
ated with prohibitions, exhortations, and
(9) ? ei-ra mene-a-rafo-? a.
wishes. All three may be found in Tauya
there-top stay-3.sg-dub-decl
(MacDonald 1990: 212 f.):
‘Maybe he’s there.’
(4) Yate-?atene!
MacDonald (1990: 209) adduces this example
go-proh.sg
as problematic for her analysis of -? a as an
‘Don’t go!’
indicative marker. It is, however, unproblem-
(5) Saniya te-amu-ne. atic to have a combination of a modal and
work get-1.sg.fut-hort illocutionary marker: the former indicates the
‘I must work.’ propositional attitude of the speaker (in (9)
his less than full commitment to the truth of
(6) ? ei mene-? e-no!
the proposition), the latter his communica-
there stay-3.sg.fut-opt
tive intention (in (9) his intention to provide
‘Let her be there!’
the addressee with a certain piece of informa-
Two other basic illocutions that are worth tion).
mentioning are imprecative and admonitive, Similarly, basic illocutions such as inter-
conventionally associated with curses and rogative, imperative, and optative should be
warnings, respectively. The following exam- distinguished from modalities such as dubita-
ples from Turkish (Lewis 1967: 115) and tive, necessitive, and volitive, respectively. To
Mandarin Chinese (Li & Thompson 1981: give one more illustration, consider the dif-
311) illustrate these two types: ference between interrogative and dubitative.
1192 XIV. Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

The former has been defined above as a basic (12) Wŏ bı̀ng méi zuò-cuò a.
illocution, whereas the latter will be pre- 1.sg on.the.contrary neg do-wrong mit
sented below as a modality. The basic differ- ‘On the contrary, I didn’t do wrong.’
ence between the two is that sentences with
(13) Nı̆ xiăng bu xiăng tā a?
interrogative basic illocution constitute ques-
2.sg think neg think 3.sg mit
tions, whereas sentences which contain a
‘Do you miss her/him?’
dubitative modality report doubt. Thus, a
speaker may execute an assertive speech act (14) Chı̄-fàn a!
using a declarative sentence, within which he eat-food mit
presents his doubts, rather than execute a ‘Eat food, OK?!’
question as such. This difference is illustrated
The particle a (ya in some dialects) may be
by the Tauya examples (2) and (9) given ear-
added to sentences representing assertions
lier. (2) is an interrogative sentence, (9) a de-
(12), questions (13), and orders (14). In each
clarative sentence which contains a dubita-
case it has the same function of reducing the
tive marker.
forcefulness of the utterance. Thus again it
embodies a more general communicative
2.2. Illocutionary modification
strategy than that of basic illocutions, which
Basic illocutions may be further modified by in this case may be called mitigation.
markers of what I here call illocutionary Illocutionary modification is not a cat-
modification. Like basic illocution, illocutio- egory that has acquired an established posi-
nary modification should be interpreted in tion in language descriptions. Reinforcing
terms of the conversational use of sentences. means may often be found under sentence
But unlike basic illocution, markers of illo- emphasis, mitigating means under a variety
cutionary modification do not identify sen- of labels, many of which will contain some
tences as speech acts of certain types, but reference to their polite nature. A frequently
rather mark much more general communica- used term is downtoner.
tive strategies on the part of the speaker: they
reinforce or mitigate the force of the speech
act (cf. Haverkate 1979: 81⫺87; Hengeveld 3. Modality
1989: 140 f.). Strategies of illocutionary modi-
3.1. Classifying parameters
fication typically apply to sentences with dif-
ferent basic illocutions, and it is this property In classifying modal categories two parame-
that makes it necessary to distinguish them ters have to be distinguished. The first con-
from basic illocutions. Consider the fol- cerns the target of evaluation of a modal dis-
lowing examples from Babungo (Schaub tinction. It is on the basis of this parameter
1985: 119): that a distinction can be drawn between e.g.
objective and subjective modality. The sec-
(10) Mè yé Làmbı́ mčc! ond concerns the domain of evaluation of a
1.sg see:pf:ind Lambi emph modal distinction. It is on the basis of this
‘I have seen Lambi!’ parameter that a distinction is drawn be-
tween e.g. epistemic, deontic, and volitive
(11) Jwı́ mčc! modality. Although distinctions pertaining to
come:imp emph both of these parameters are present in most
‘Come now!’ treatments of modality, they are often not
The emphatic particle mc̀c is used in Babungo strictly kept apart.
to turn both assertions (10) and commands 3.1.1. Target of evaluation
(11) into more insistent speech acts. It thus
represents a more general communicative By the target of evaluation of a modal distinc-
strategy than the one embodied by the in- tion is meant the part of the utterance that is
dicative and imperative verb forms. This modalized. Along this parameter the follow-
strategy may be called reinforcement. ing types of modality can be distinguished
(see Jakobson 1957; Lyons 1977; Foley &
The reinforcing strategy illustrated for Ba-
Van Valin 1984; Hengeveld 1988; 1989):
bungo in (10)⫺(11) may be contrasted with
the mitigating strategy illustrated for Manda- (a) Participant-oriented modality. This type
rin Chinese (Li & Thompson 1981: 316, 313, of modality affects the relational part of
315) in (12)⫺(14): the utterance as expressed by a predicate
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1193

and concerns the relation between (prop- 3.1.2. Domain of evaluation


erties of) a participant in an event and By the domain of evaluation of a modal dis-
the potential realization of that event (cf. tinction is meant the perspective from which
Foley & Van Valin 1984: 215). the evaluation is executed. By varying this
(b) Event-oriented modality. This type of mo- perspective the following types of modality
dality affects the event description con- may be distinguished:
tained within the utterance, i.e the de-
scriptive part of an utterance, and con- (a) Facultative modality is concerned with in-
cerns the objective assessment of the ac- trinsic or acquired capacities.
tuality status of the event. (b) Deontic modality is concerned with what
is (legally, socially, morally) permissible.
(c) Proposition-oriented modality. This type
(c) Volitive modality is concerned with what
of modality affects the propositional
is desirable.
content of an utterance, i.e. the part of
(d) Epistemic modality is concerned with
the utterance representing the speaker’s what is known about the actual world.
views and beliefs, and concerns the speci- (e) Evidential modality is concerned with the
fication of the degree of commitment of source of the information contained in a
the speaker towards the proposition he sentence.
is presenting.
Extensive exemplification of all these types
The following example from Turkish (Lewis will be given below. A first illustration is
1967: 151), containing all three types of moda- given in the following English examples:
lity, may serve as a first illustration of the
(16) John is able to swim.
differences between them:
(Ability: Facultative)
(15) Anlı-y-abil-ecek-miş-im. (17) John has to swim.
understand-Ø-abil-irr-infr-1.sg (Obligation: Deontic)
‘I gather that I will be able to under-
stand.’ (18) John would rather not swim.
(Wanting: Volitive)
In this example the ability suffix -abil (pre-
(19) John may be swimming.
ceded by an obligatory intervocalic -y-) ex-
(Possibility: Epistemic)
presses a participant-oriented modality. The
first singular subject is said to have the ca- (20) John will be swimming.
pacity of engaging in the relation expressed (Inference: Evidential)
by the predicate. The irrealis suffix -ecek ex-
presses an event-oriented modality. The event 3.1.3. Synthesis
described by the sentence is characterized as The combination of three targets of evalu-
non-actual, which is in this case, but not nec- ation with five domains of evaluation leads to
essarily, reflected in the translation by means 15 possible combinations of features of moda-
of a future tense. The inferential suffix -miş lity types. Some of these are logically ex-
expresses a proposition-oriented modality. It cluded, however. To give a simple example, it
signals that the speaker does not fully com- is impossible to evaluate propositions in
mit himself to the propositional content of terms of their intrinsic or acquired capacities.
his assertion. The logically permitted combinations are
listed in Table 111.1:
The term “modality” has been restricted in
various ways to cover only part of the cat-
egories of modality recognized here. Thus, Target Participant Event Proposition
Foley & Van Valin (1984: 213⫺220) restrict
the term to participant-oriented modality, re- Domain
serving the labels “status” and “evidentiality” Facultative ⫹ ⫹ ⫺
for event-oriented and proposition-oriented Deontic ⫹ ⫹ ⫺
modality, respectively. Halliday (1970: 336) Volitive ⫹ ⫹ ⫹
takes the opposite position, restricting the Epistemic ⫺ ⫹ ⫹
term “modality” to proposition-oriented mo- Evidential ⫺ ⫺ ⫹
dality and using “modulation” for the re-
maining categories. Tab. 111.1: Cross-classification of modality types
1194 XIV. Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

The following sections describe the ten re- 3.2.2. Deontic


maining subcategories of modality identified Deontic participant-oriented modalities de-
in Table 111.1, using the target of evaluation scribe a participant’s being under the obliga-
as the primary classificatory parameter and tion or having permission to engage in the
the domain of evaluation as the secondary. event type designated by the predicate. Obli-
3.2. Participant-oriented modality gation seems to be encoded by grammatical
means more often than permission. Terms
Participant-oriented modalities are better used in different grammatical traditions for
known from the literature as agent-oriented verb forms expressing obligation are “obliga-
modalities. Although widely used, this term tive” and “necessitative”. The following ex-
is not too felicitous in that it suggests that ample is from Quechua (Cole 1982: 151):
only controlling participants in dynamic
events may be subject to this type of modali- (26) Miku-na ka-rka-ni.
zation. That this is not the case is apparent eat-oblg cop-past-1
from such examples as: ‘I must eat.’ (lit. ‘I am to eat.’)
(21) John wants to be young again. 3.2.3. Volitive
The term participant-oriented modality is Volitive participant-oriented modality de-
neutral as to the event type in which this class scribes a participant’s desire to engage in the
of modal expressions occurs. Three main event-type designated by the predicate. The
subcategories of participant-oriented moda- following example is from Guajajara (Ben-
lity may be distinguished on the basis of the dor-Samuel 1972: 95):
domain of evaluation they are concerned
with. (27) Za-hem rem.
1.pi-leave vol
3.2.1. Facultative ‘We want to leave.’
Facultative participant-oriented modality de-
scribes the ability of a participant to engage 3.3. Event-oriented modality
in the event type designated by the predicate. Event-oriented modalities occupy a position
In some languages a distinction is made be- in between participant-oriented modalities
tween intrinsic (‘be able to’) and acquired and proposition-oriented modalities. They
(‘know how to’) ability, as shown in the fol- are like participant-oriented modalities in
lowing examples from Mapuche, which has that they form part of the descriptive content
separate auxiliaries for these two types of of the sentence. They are like proposition-ori-
ability (Smeets 1989: 219): ented modalities in that the source of modali-
(22) Pepı́ kuu aw-la-n. zation is not a participant in the event de-
intr.abil work-neg-decl.1.sg scribed within the sentence.
‘I am not able to work.’ Event-oriented modalities describe the
existence of possibilities, general obligations,
(23) Kim tuku-fi-n. and the like, without the speaker taking re-
acq.abil put.at-obj-decl.1.sg sponsibility for these judgements. This is best
‘I know how to put it.’ illustrated by means of the following sen-
Spanish makes the same distinction. Intrinsic tence, which contains both a proposition-ori-
ability is expressed by the modal verb poder ented and an event-oriented modal expres-
‘be able to’, acquired ability by the verb saber sion (Lyons 1977: 808):
‘know (how to)’ in its modal use. (28) Certainly he may have forgotten.
Inability may also acquire the status of a
separate category, as in the Turkish Impoten- Through the epistemic proposition-oriented
tial (25), which may be compared with its Po- modal adverb certainly the speaker commits
tential (24), used for ability (Lewis 1967: 151): himself to the truth of the proposition he may
have forgotten, which contains the epistemic
(24) Gel-ebil-di-ø. event-oriented modal verb may that describes
come-abil-past-3 the existence of the possibility of the occur-
‘He was able to come.’ rence of the event he has forgotten. Although
(25) Gel-eme-di-ø. the two epistemic judgements contained in
come-inab-past-3 (28) are non-harmonic (Lyons 1977; Coates
‘He was unable to come.’ 1983; Bybee et al. 1994), no contradiction
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1195

arises, since the two judgements pertain to But the sense of general obligation may be
different levels: the speaker expresses his cer- present in personal constructions as well, as
tainty about the existence of an objective pos- in (33) (cf. Coates 1983: 73):
sibility. For this reason epistemic proposi-
tion-oriented modality has been called “sub- (33) We ought to have a right to intervene.
jective” and event-oriented modality “objec- 3.3.3. Volitive
tive” (Lyons 1977: 797⫺804; cf. also Halliday
1970; Coates 1983). Objective status may, Volitive event-oriented modality character-
apart from epistemic modality, also be as- izes events in terms of what is generally desir-
signed to facultative, deontic, and volitive able or undesirable. This category seems
varieties. hardly ever to be encoded by specialized
markers, but rather to group with deontic
3.3.1. Facultative modality. An exception to this, however, is
the Tauya avolitional, which “[...] implies
Facultative event-oriented modality charac- that the action or state specified by the verb
terizes events in terms of the physical or cir- would be undesirable” (MacDonald 1990:
cumstantial enabling conditions on their oc- 202 f.):
currence (Bybee et al. 1994; Olbertz 1998).
This type of modality is often referred to as (34) Tepau-fe-? ate-e-? a.
root modality (Coates 1983). Examples are break-tr-avol-1-decl
the following: ‘It would be bad if I broke it.’
(29) It can take three hours to get there. 3.3.4. Epistemic
(30) I couldn’t finish reading the book because Epistemic event-oriented modality character-
it got too dark. izes events in terms of the (im)possibility of
their occurrence in view of what is known
In contrast to facultative participant-oriented about the world. Although many different
modality, the possibility of occurrence of the shades of meaning could be defined within
event does not depend on the intrinsic capaci- this domain, grammatical encoding of this
ties of a participant, but follows from the cir- type of modality is generally restricted to a
cumstances in which the event takes place. realis versus irrealis (or potentialis) opposi-
This sense can most easily be detected in im- tion. An example of this type of opposition
personal constructions such as (29). may be found in Mapuche (Smeets 1989:
307):
3.3.2. Deontic
(35) Trür amu-a-y-u
Deontic event-oriented modality character- together go-irr-decl-1.du.sbj
izes events in terms of what is obligatory or üyüw.
permitted within some system of moral or le- over.there
gal conventions (cf. Allwood et al. 1977: 111). ‘Together we will go over there.’
In contrast to deontic participant-oriented
modality, the obligations expressed by means (36) Trür amu-ø-y-u
of deontic event-oriented modality do not together go-rls-decl-1.du.sbj
rest upon a particular participant, but repre- üyüw.
sent general rules of conduct. This sense of over.there
general applicability can most clearly be iden- ‘Together we went over there.’
tified in impersonal expressions such as the In spite of the translation the Mapuche ir-
Turkish modal periphrases illustrated in (31) realis cannot be interpreted as a future tense
and (32) (van Schaaik 1985): morpheme, since it has a whole range of ad-
(31) Bura-da ayakkabıları cø ıkar-mak var. ditional shades of modal meaning, including
dem-loc shoes take.off-inf exist probability.
‘One has to take off his shoes here.’ (lit. The opposition between realis and irrealis
‘There is taking off of shoes here.’) is sometimes further obscured by the fact
that the realis domain is occupied by certain
(32) Avuç aç-mak yok. tenses, as a result of which the modal cat-
hand open-inf exist.neg egory irrealis stands in opposition to the tem-
‘Begging prohibited.’ (lit. ‘There isn’t poral categories past and present. This is, for
begging.’) instance, the case in Ngiyambaa, where there
1196 XIV. Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

is “a three-way tense system, involving two ted as having optative basic illocution (see
contrasts, one of actuality (actualis versus ir- 2.1), i.e. it is not a wish but an assertion con-
realis) and, within the actualis category, one cerning the speaker’s wishes.
of time (past versus present)” (Donaldson
1980: 160). Again, the category of irrealis 3.4.2. Epistemic
cannot be interpreted as a simple future In the introduction to 3.3 the distinction be-
tense, since it is also used for stating (objec- tween objective and subjective epistemic mo-
tive) probabilities, as in: dality was explained and it was shown that
objective epistemic modality is event-ori-
(37) Yurun-gu nidjal-aga.
ented, whereas subjective epistemic modality
rain-erg rain-irr
is proposition-oriented. Ngiyambaa provides
‘It may rain.’ or ‘It will rain.’
a further illustration of this distinction (Don-
In order to avoid such ambiguities some lan- aldson 1980: 256):
guages make a distinction between a “certain
future” and an “uncertain future”, where the (41) Gali:-ninda-gila niyanu baluy-aga.
latter might perhaps better be interpreted as water-priv-dub 1.pl.nom die-irr
an irrealis form. The following examples are ‘We’ll probably die for lack of water.’
from Garo (Burling 1961: 27 f.): Apart from the irrealis marker discussed in
(38) Ana re’-an-gen. 3.3.4, Ngiyambaa has a special marker for
1.sg move-dir-fut dubitative modality. Both may occur in a sin-
‘I will go.’ gle sentence, as illustrated in (41), which may
be paraphrased as ‘I guess (dub) the unreal-
(39) Re’-ba-nabadona. ized (irr) event of our dying for lack of water
move-dir-irr will take place’. Thus, the dubitative gives the
‘He may come.’ speaker’s subjective assessment of a proposi-
Garo furthermore has an intentional future tion containing an objective specification of
and two negative futures. the unrealized status of an event.
Just as objective epistemic modality
3.4. Proposition-oriented modality groups with tense (3.3), so does subjective epi-
As stated and illustrated above, proposition- stemic modality group with evidentials
oriented modalities specify the subjective atti- (3.4.3). This can be explained as a result of
tude of the speaker towards the proposition the fact that both tense and objective moda-
he is presenting. The speaker may character- lity are event-oriented, while subjective moda-
ize the proposition as his personal wish (voli- lity and evidentiality are proposition-ori-
tive modality), express several degrees of ented. Ngiyambaa illustrates this grouping.
commitment with respect to the proposition In this language irrealis modality is expressed
(epistemic modality), or specify the source of by means of a verb-suffix that is mutually ex-
the proposition (evidential modality). clusive with tense suffixes (see 3.3.4). Dubita-
tive modality, on the other hand, is expressed
3.4.1. Volitive by means of a particle that cliticizes to the
Volitive proposition-oriented modality differs first constituent in the sentence, in exactly the
from its participant-oriented counterpart in same way as evidential modalities. In Garo
that the source of the volitional attitude is the (Burling 1961; see also Bybee 1985: 180 f.) the
speaker, and not a participant in the event uncertain future illustrated in 3.3.4 is a verb
described within the sentence. In Pawnee suffix that may immediately follow the verb
(Parks 1976: 162) a special formation, in stem, just like true tense suffixes, whereas the
which the verb inflected passively is provided dubitative occupies the final position of the
with ‘perfect intentive aspect’ suffixes, ex- suffix string, just like evidential suffixes.
presses volitive proposition-oriented moda- The most important subdistinctions to be
lity: made within the category of epistemic propo-
sition-oriented modality are doxastic, dubita-
(40) Ti-ku-itka-is-ta. tive, and hypothetical. Through a doxastic
ind-1.sg.obj-sleep-pf-intv modality the speaker indicates that he be-
‘I want to sleep.’ (lit. ‘It is going to sleep lieves the proposition he is presenting to be
on me.’) true. Since this is the usual assumption un-
Note that the indicative mood morpheme ti- derlying assertions, this modality type is least
shows that this sentence cannot be interpre- frequently expressed by grammatical means.
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1197

The following example is from Hidatsa (Mat- The most basic grammatically encoded
thews 1964), where the sentence final particle distinction within the domain of evidentiality
c indicates that the speaker has reasonable is that between sensory evidence and non-sen-
grounds to believe that the proposition he is sory evidence (see Willett 1988: 57, who uses
presenting is true: the terms “direct” and “indirect evidence”,
respectively). Markers of sensory evidence in-
(42) Wı́o i hı́rawe ki ksa c. dicate that the speaker acquired the informa-
woman 3.sg sleep ingr iter dox tion he is presenting through perception,
‘The woman fell asleep again and those of non-sensory evidence that he ac-
again.’ quired it from any other source. A language
Through the much more frequently marked making just this binary distinction (in the
dubitative modality the speaker indicates past tense only) is Turkish. Compare the fol-
that he has some doubts about the truth of lowing sentences (Lewis 1967: 128):
the proposition he is presenting. The Ngiy- (46) Bir turist vapuru
ambaa example (41) above illustrates this indef tourist ship
case. A second example comes from Ma- gel-di-ø.
puche (Smeets 1989: 431): come-past.sens.ev-3.sg
(43) Amu-y chi. ‘A tourist-ship arrived (I witnessed it).’
go-decl.3 dub (47) Bir turist vapuru
‘Maybe he went away.’ indef tourist ship
Through a hypothetical modality the speaker gel-miş-ø.
indicates absence of commitment (either posi- come-past.non.sens.ev-3.sg
tive or negative) with respect to the proposi- ‘A tourist-ship arrived (I did not wit-
tion he is presenting. In the following English ness it).’
examples this modality type is expressed by A verb with the suffix -miş, as in (47), “con-
means of a particle that at the same time veys that the information it gives is based
functions as a conjunction: either on hearsay or on inference from ob-
(44) if he comes, (I’ll leave) served facts, but not on the speaker having
seen the action take place” (Lewis 1967: 122),
(45) if he came, (I would leave) whereas a verb with the suffix -di, as in (46),
Note, incidentally, that the distinction be- is used “when relating past events positively
tween realis and irrealis conditions, as il- known to the speaker” (Lewis 1967: 128).
lustrated in (44)⫺(45), is not a subdivision Markers of sensory evidence may be fur-
that obtains at the level of proposition-ori- ther subdivided according to the particular
ented modality, but at the level of event- sensory mode through which the information
oriented modality. Thus, in (44)⫺(45) the was acquired (Palmer 1986: 67; Willett
speaker indicates absence of commitment to 1988: 57). A more fundamental subdivision,
the proposition introduced by if, and within however, obtains within the domain of non-
that proposition he characterizes an event as sensory evidence (Willett 1988). Within this
real (44) or unreal (45) within the hypothe- class a distinction should be made between
sized world. reportative modality, through which the
speaker characterizes the information he is
3.4.3. Evidential presenting as obtained through hearsay, and
inferential modality, through which the
Evidential proposition-oriented modality is
speaker indicates that he has inferred the in-
concerned with the way the proposition the
formation he is presenting from other pieces
speaker is presenting came to his knowledge,
of (non-sensory) information. The following
i.e. it specifies the source on which the
examples from Inga (Levinsohn 1975: 15, 24;
speaker relies for the information contained
see also Palmer 1986: 52) show that this lan-
within his utterance. For this reason the term
guage has markers for these two types of mo-
“epistemological modality” (Chung & Tim-
dality next to its marker of sensory evidence:
berlake 1985) has been used for what is more
generally referred to as “evidentiality” (Ja- (48) %ujpataca Pasto-ma-si ri.
kobson 1957; Chafe & Nichols 1986, eds.; long.ago Pasto-dir-rprt go:3.sg
Willett 1988; Aikhenvald & Dixon 2003, ‘Long ago someone went to Pasto (it is
eds.). said).’
1198 XIV. Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

(49) Chipica diablo-char ca. of basic illocution. Intonational strategies


there devil-infr cop:3.sg may furthermore be exploited to express illo-
‘A devil was presumably there.’ cutionary modification. Thus, Halliday
(1970: 331) shows that in English the speaker
(50) Nispaca Santiago-ma-mi rini.
may mitigate his statement through intona-
after.that Santiago-dir-sens.ev go.1.sg
tional means.
‘After that I went to Santiago.’
(c) Particle. Particles are widely used for the
Within the domain of reportative modality expression of a variety of illocutionary and
further distinctions may be made as to the modal distinctions. In most cases these par-
particular source of the report, whereas in the ticles either occupy the sentence-final posi-
case of inferential modality the type of in- tion, or cliticize to the first constituent of the
formation on which the inference is based clause. In some cases they occupy the prever-
may trigger further subdivisions. See Willett bal position. These three types are illustrated
(1988) for an overview. in the following examples from Hidatsa
(Matthews 1964), Ngiyambaa (Donaldson
4. Mood 1980: 276), and Dutch, respectively:
(53) Wı́o a rı́iti rahe.
The illocutionary and modal distinctions
woman 3.sg hungry rprt
listed in sections 2 and 3 may be expressed
‘I have been told that the woman is
by a variety of morphological markers, for
hungry.’
which the term mood is commonly used. Be-
sides mood there are non-morphological (54) %indu-dhan girambiyi.
markers of illocution, such as word order and 2.sg-rprt sick:past
intonation, which will be included here for ‘You are said to have been sick.’
the sake of completeness. (55) Doe de deur even dicht!
The various semantic categories that have do.imp.sg the door mit closed
been distinguished above are often expressed ‘Close the door, will you?’
differently in main and subordinate clauses.
For this reason these two syntactic contexts (d) Inflection. Inflection of main predicates,
are discussed separately below. Note that illo- mostly of verbs, is widely used to mark many
cution is only expressed in main clauses, and of the illocutionary and modal distinctions
therefore irrelevant to the analysis of subor- described above. Terminology is abundant in
dinated clauses. this particular area, and there is little chance
that terms are used in the same way across
4.1. The expression of modality and language descriptions. Some of the more fre-
illocution in main clauses quent names of inflections are “indicative”
The following strategies for the expression of (for verb forms used in clauses with declara-
modality and illocution in main clauses may tive basic illocution), “imperative” (for the
be distinguished: verb forms used in clauses with imperative
basic illocution), “conditional” (for verb
(a) Word order. The basic illocution of a sen- forms expressing epistemic possibility), and
tence may be signalled by word order, as in “counterfactual” (for verb forms expressing
the following Dutch examples of a declara- irrealis modality). Note that very often inflec-
tive and interrogative sentence, respectively: tions express more than one illocutionary
(51) Peter kom-t. and/or modal value, and that the set of
Peter come-pres.3.sg meanings associated with a given form may
‘Peter comes.’ vary from language to language. The value
given between brackets is the meaning which
(52) Kom-t Peter? is generally included in the set of meanings
come-pres.3.sg Peter of the forms mentioned.
‘Does Peter come?’
The Turkish example (56) illustrates (Lewis
Note that apart from word order differences 1967: 126) the inflectional strategy, here used
the intonation patterns of (51) and (52) are to express event-oriented deontic modality:
different as well.
(56) Gel-meli-ymiş-im.
(b) Intonation. As illustrated in (51)⫺(52), come-oblg-non.sens.ev-1.sg
intonation may play a role in the expression ‘It seems I ought to come.’
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1199

marker word into- particle inflection auxiliary periph- deri-


category order nation rasis vation
basic illocution ⫹ ⫹ ⫹ ⫹ ⫺ ⫺ ⫺
illocutionary modification ⫺ ⫹ ⫹ ⫹ ⫺ ⫺ ⫺
proposition oriented modality ⫺ ⫺ ⫹ ⫹ ⫹ ⫺ ⫺
event oriented modality ⫺ ⫺ ⫺ ⫹ ⫹ ⫹ ⫺
participant oriented modality ⫺ ⫺ ⫺ ⫺ ⫹ ⫹ ⫹

Tab. 111.2: Encoding of illocution and modality

(e) Auxiliary. Modal distinctions may be ex- (61) nadhu dhinga: dhal-i-ninda ga-ra.
pressed by means of auxiliaries, as illustrated 1:nom meat:abs eat-purp-vol cop-pres
in the following examples of the auxiliaries ‘I want to eat meat.’ (lit. ‘I am in want
dū in Babungo (Schaub 1985: 228) and must of eating meat.’)
in English:
A preliminary investigation of a sample of 20
(57) %we nyı́i dı́-dū. languages (Hengeveld 1996, ed.) suggests that
3.sg run:pres dur-inab the various markers of modality and illocu-
‘He is unable to run.’ tion presented above are not randomly dis-
tributed. The general tendency emerging
(58) He must be home. from the data is as in Table 111.2.
(f) Periphrastic construction. In periphrastic As Table 111.2 shows, there appears to be
constructions the modal meaning is the result a clearcut correlation between illocutionary
of a particular configuration of elements, and modal categories on the one hand, and
rather than that it can be attributed to a sin- expression type on the other. The particular
gle element of the clause. Many modal peri- ordering of illocutionary and modal catego-
phrastic constructions involve some form ries given in Table 111.2 may be determined
of the verbs have or be, the latter either in by the fact that the lower the category is in
its existential, locative, or copular sense the table, the more directly relevant to the
(Hengeveld 1992: 257⫺290). The following predicate and the less general in meaning it
examples are from Basque (Lafitte 1944: 221) is (Bybee 1985). Alternatively, one might say
and Quechua (Cole 1982: 151): that the higher the position in Table 111.2,
the more personal (Traugott 1982) the cat-
(59) Etche hunta-n ez da egory is.
house dem-loc neg 3.sg.abs-cop.pres
bizitzer-ik. 4.2. The expression of modality in
live.inf-prtv subordinate clauses
‘It is impossible to live in this house.’ In subordinate clauses the non-morphologi-
(lit. ‘There is no living in this house.’) cal markers listed above, word order and into-
(60) Miku-na ka-rka-ni. nation, are not used as expressions of moda-
eat-irr cop-past-1 lity. This coincides with the fact that in sub-
‘I must eat.’ (lit. ‘I was characterized by ordinate clauses basic illocution and illocuti-
unrealized eating.’) onary modification can not be expressed. The
remaining strategies can all be found in sub-
(g) Derivation. Derivational means are used ordinate clauses, but in the case of particles
to a limited extent, and probably for the ex- and inflections there may be forms that are
pression of participant-oriented modalities specific to subordinate clauses. These two
only. The ability and inability suffixes of Tur- strategies are discussed below.
kish, illustrated in 3.2.1 are of a derivational Particles with a modal value may simulta-
nature, and so is the volitional suffix in Ngiy- neously act as conjunctions in subordinate
ambaa (Donaldson 1980: 115, 281). Note that clauses. Thus, the complementizer if in Eng-
the derivational strategy is here combined lish signals absence of commitment on the
with a periphrastic one. part of the speaker, whereas that may signal
1200 XIV. Sachverhalts-, Eigenschafts- und verwandte Begriffe

positive commitment, as in the following ex- in which the speaker does not assert the
amples: proposition contained in the complement
clause.
(62) Peter didn’t know if John was ill. These facts suggest that the same parame-
(63) Peter didn’t know that John was ill. ter that may be used to describe the crosslin-
guistic distribution of mood markers in main
Note that through the complementizers the clauses, may be used to describe the crosslin-
propositional attitude of the speaker, not guistic distribution of subjunctive verb forms.
that of the subject of the matrix clause, is ex- Tables 111.2 and 111.3 thus lend further sup-
pressed, i.e. the modality type involved is epi- port to the classification of modal categories
stemic proposition-oriented modality (see as to their target of evaluation, apart from
3.4.2). On the other hand, the comple- the classification as to their domain of evalu-
mentizer to in English could be interpreted ation.
as an irrealis marker, i.e. the expression of
epistemic event-oriented modality.
In many languages there are inflectional 5. Uncommon abbreviations
means, usually called ‘subordinate moods’,
that are only or mainly used in subordinate abil ability
clauses. These forms generally cover a wider acq.abil acquired ability
range of modal values than inflectional forms avol avolitional
in main clauses. The best known case of a dox doxastic
subordinate mood is the subjunctive or con- impr imprecative
junctive mood, which is generally used in op- inab impotential
position with the indicative mood, the latter intr.abil intrinsic ability
also being used in main clauses. The range of intv intentive
modal values covered by a subjunctive mood mit mitigation
varies from language to language. From the non.sens.ev non-sensory evidence
data in Noonan (1985: 91⫺103) it can be in- sens.ev sensory evidence
ferred that, at least for complement clauses,
this variation can be described systematically. 6. References
The determining factor is the modality type
in terms of its target of evaluation. The distri- Aikhenvald, Alexandra & Dixon, R[obert] M. W.
bution would be as follows: (2003, eds.), Studies in Evidentiality. Amsterdam:
Benjamins (Typological Studies in Language 54)
A B C Allwood, Jens & Andersson, Lars-Gunnar & Dahl,
Östen (1977), Logic in Linguistics. Cambridge:
proposition oriented ⫺ ⫺ SUBJ Cambridge University Press
modality
Bendor-Samuel, David (1972), Hierarchical Struc-
event oriented ⫺ SUBJ SUBJ
ture in Guajajara. Norman: Summer Institute of
modality
Linguistics
participant oriented SUBJ SUBJ SUBJ
modality Burling, Robbins (1961), A Garo Grammar. Poona:
Deccan College Postgraduate and Research Insti-
Tab. 111.3: Uses of subjunctives tute
Bybee, Joan L. (1985), Morphology: A Study of the
In systems of type A the use of the subjunc- Relation between Meaning and Form. Amsterdam:
tive is restricted to complement clauses with Benjamins (Typological Studies in Language 9)
dependent time reference, including the com- Bybee, Joan L. & Perkins, Revere D. & Pagliuca,
plement clauses of verbs lexically expressing William (1994), The Evolution of Grammar: Tense,
participant-oriented modalities, such as the Aspect and Modality in the Languages of the World.
equivalents of want and be able to. In systems Chicago: University of Chicago Press
of type B the subjunctive has the additional
use of expressing irrealis modality, i.e. it oc- Chafe, Wallace & Nichols, Johanna (1986, eds.),
curs in complement clauses which contain the Evidentiality: the Linguistic Coding of Epistemol-
description of an event the factuality of ogy. Norwood: Ablex
which has not been determined. In languages Chung, Sandra & Timberlake, Alan (1985), “Tense,
of type C the subjunctive is used in all cases Aspect, and Mood”. In: Shopen, Timothy (ed.),
111. Illocution, mood, and modality 1201

Language Typology and Syntactic Description, Vol. Li, Charles N. & Thompson, Sandra A. (1981),
III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 202⫺ Mandarin Chinese: A Functional Reference Gram-
258 mar. Berkeley: University of California Press
Coates, Jennifer (1983), The Semantics of the Lyons, John (1977), Semantics, Vol. 1⫺2. Cam-
Modal Auxiliaries. London: Croom Helm bridge: Cambridge University Press
Cole, Peter (1982), Imbabura Quechua. Amster- MacDonald, Lorna (1990), A Grammar of Tauya.
dam: North-Holland (Lingua Descriptive Studies Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter (Mouton Grammar Li-
5) brary 6)
Matthews, G[eorge] H[ubert] (1964), Hidatsa Syn-
Donaldson, Tamsin (1980), Ngiyambaa. Cam-
tax. The Hague: Mouton
bridge: Cambridge University Press
Noonan, M[ichael] (1985), “Complementation”.
Foley, William A. & Van Valin, Robert D. (1984), In: Shopen, Timothy (ed.), Language Typology and
Functional Syntax and Universal Grammar. Cam- Syntactic Description, Vol. II. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press bridge University Press, 42⫺140
Halliday, M[ichael] A. K. (1970), “Functional Di- Olbertz, H[ella] G. (1998), Verbal Periphrases in a
versity in Language, as Seen from a Consideration Functional Grammar of Spanish. Berlin: Mouton de
of Modality and Mood in English”. Foundations of Gruyter (Functional Grammar Series 22)
Language 6, 322⫺361 Palmer, F[rank] R. (1986), Mood and Modality.
Haverkate, Henk (1979), Impositive Sentences in Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Spanish: Theory and Description in Linguistic Prag- Parks, Douglas R. (1976), A Grammar of Pawnee.
matics. Amsterdam: North-Holland New York: Garland
Hengeveld, Kees (1988), “Illocution, Mood and Sadock, Jerrold M. & Zwicky, Arnold M. (1985),
Modality in a Functional Grammar of Spanish”. “Speech Act Distinctions in Syntax”. In: Shopen,
Journal of Semantics 6.3⫺4, 227⫺269 Timothy (ed.), Language Typology and Syntactic
Hengeveld, Kees (1989), “Layers and Operators”. Description, Vol. I. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 155⫺196
Journal of Linguistics 25.1, 127⫺157
Schaaik, Gerjan van (1985), “Verb Based Terms
Hengeveld, Kees (1992), Non-verbal Predication:
and Modality in Turkish”. Unpublished paper,
Theory, Typology, Diachrony. Berlin: Mouton de
University of Amsterdam
Gruyter (Functional Grammar Series 15)
Schaub, Willi (1985), Babungo. London: Croom
Hengeveld, Kees (1996, ed.), Verslag werkgroep Helm
functionale grammatica II. Unpublished paper,
Smeets, Ineke (1989), A Mapuche Grammar. Un-
University of Amsterdam
published Ph.D. dissertation, University of Leiden
Jakobson, Roman (1957), “Shifters, Verbal Cat- Traugott, Elizabeth C. (1982), “From Proposi-
egories, and the Russian Verb”. In: Jakobson, Ro- tional to Textual and Expressive Meanings: Some
man, Selected Writings, Vol. II. The Hague: Mou- Semantic-Pragmatic Aspects of Grammaticaliza-
ton, 130⫺147 tion”. In: Lehmann, W[infred] P. & Malkiel, Y[a-
Lafitte, Pierre (1944), Grammaire Basque: Navarro- kov] (eds.), Perspectives on Historical Linguistics.
labourdin Litteraire. Bayonne: Librairie “Le Livre” Amsterdam: Benjamins, 245⫺271
Levinsohn, Stephen H. (1975), “Functional Sen- Willett, Thomas (1988), “A Crosslinguistic Survey
tence Perspective in Inga”. Journal of Linguistics of the Grammaticization of Evidentiality”. Studies
in Language 12, 51⫺97
11, 13⫺37
Lewis, G[eoffrey] L. (1967), Turkish Grammar. Ox- Kees Hengeveld, Amsterdam
ford: Oxford University Press (The Netherlands)

You might also like