You are on page 1of 42

%$#"!

Dini Tetkikler Dergisi

ULUM Journal of Religious Inquiries


‫ﻣﺠﻠﺔ اﻟﺪراﺳﺎت اﻟﺪﯾﻨﯿﺔ‬

www.dergipark.org.tr/ulum

al-Māturīdī and Atomism *

Mehmet Bulgen (Bulğen) * *

Abstract

This study aims to shed light on the position of Imām al-Māturīdī (d. 333/944) on atomism. It consists of
three sections. The first section will delineate some theories of matter along with the meaning of certain
pertinent terms, which were widely accepted during al-Māturīdī’s time. The following section will discuss
whether Imām al-Māturīdī understood such notions as body (jism), substance (jawhar), and accident (ʿaraḍ)
within the frame of traditional Islamic atomism. Moreover, this section will give some information on how
al-Māturīdī approached the issues pertaining to physics and cosmology. The last section will cover the
development of atomism in the Māturīdiyya kalām school after Imām al-Māturīdī.

Keywords

Kalām, al-Māturīdī, Atomism, Substance, Accident

*
This article is the revised version of the previously published book chapter in Turkish: Mehmet Bulğen, “İmam Mâtüridî ve
Atomculuk”, İmam Mâtürîdî ve Mâtürîdiyye Geleneği: Tarih, Yöntem ve Doktrin, ed. Hülya Alper (İstanbul: İFAV, 2018), 83-122.
I want to thank Zeliha Uluyurt and Ertul Ortabas for their contribution to the translation of the article into English.
**
Associate Professor, Marmara University, Faculty of Theology, Department of Kalam, Istanbul, Turkey
Doç. Dr., Marmara Üniversitesi, İlahiyat Fakültesi, Kelam Anabilim Dalı
mbulgen@hotmail.com ORCID 0000-0002-2372-471X
Article Types: Translated Article
Received: 30 October 2019
Accepted: 31 December 2019
Published: 31 December 2019
Cite as: Mehmet Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”, ULUM 2/2 (December 2019), 223-264,
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.3601654
224 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

İmam Mâtüridî ve Atomculuk


Öz

İmam Mâtürîdî’nin (ö. 333/944) atomculukla ilişkisini ortaya koymayı hedefleyen bu çalışma, üç bölümden
oluşmaktadır. Birinci bölümde İmam Mâtürîdî döneminde yaygın kabul gören madde teorileri ve bunlarla
ilişkili cisim, cüz, cevher ve araz gibi kavramların anlamları açıklanacaktır. İkinci bölümde İmam
Mâtürîdî’nin cisim, cüz, cevher ve araz gibi kavramları atomculuk ekseninde anlayıp anlamadığı
tartışılacaktır. Ayrıca bu bölümde İmam Mâtürîdî’nin fizik ve kozmolojiye dair meselelere nasıl bir yöntemle
yaklaştığı hakkında bilgi verilecektir. Üçüncü bölümde ise İmam Mâtürîdî sonrasında atomculuğun
Mâtürîdiyye kelâmındaki gelişimi ele alınacaktır.
Anahtar Kelimeler

Kelâm, Mâtürîdî, Atomculuk, Cevher, Araz

Introduction

The theory of atomism, i.e. the view that all the objects in the universe are composed of indivisible
parts known as atoms, has an essential place in classical Islamic thought. This theory, which was adopted
for the first time by the Muʿtazilite scholars and introduced into the kalām discipline at the end of the 2nd/8th
century, was also accepted by the Ashʿariyya and Māturīdiyya schools in the classical period (4th/10th -
6th/12th centuries).1 It is surprising that a theory that is defended by materialists of Ancient Greek thought,
such as Democritus (B.C. 460 – B.C. 370) and Epicurus (B.C. 341 – B.C. 270), has been widely accepted by
Muslim mutakallimūn (i.e., the scholars of kalām) in the classical Islamic thought. 2

Though atomism had been embraced by all kalām schools in the classical era, how Imām al-Māturīdī
(d. 333/944), the founder of the Māturīdīyya, one of the important schools of the Ahl al-Sunna kalām, viewed
this theory has still not been thoroughly investigated. The fact that he did not engage in a discussion
regarding atomism in his extant books, and that he interpreted some notions related to the issue such as
body (jism), substance (jawhar), and accident (ʿaraḍ) in a way different than their prevalent meanings in the

1
For detailed information about Kalām atomism, its criticism, and its assessment in connection with modern science, please see
these books of mine: Mehmet Bulğen, Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri = Criticisms of Atomism in Classical Islamic
Thought (İstanbul: İFAV Publication, 2017); Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu ve Modern Kozmoloji = Kalam Atomism and Modern Cosmology
(Ankara: TDV Publication, 2018).
2
Regarding works on kalām atomism, see. Shlomo Pines, Studies in Islamic Atomism, trans. Michael Schwarz, ed. Tzvi Langerman
(Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, 1997); Alnoor Dhanani, The Physical Theory of Kalām: Atoms, Space and Void in Baṣra Muʿtazilî
Cosmology (Leiden: E.J. Brill Publishing, 1994). Munā Ahmad Muhammad Abū Zayd, al-Tasawwur al-Dharrī fī al-Fikr al-Falsafī al-
Islāmī, (Beiut: al-Muassasa al-Jâmiiyya, 1994). Harry Austryn Wolfson, The Philosophy of the Kalam (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1976), 466; D. B. Macdonald, “Continuous Re-Creation and Atomic Time in Muslim Scholastic Theology”, Isis,
9/2 (1927), 341; Josef Van Ess “Muʿtazilite Atomism”, in Flowering Muslim Theology, trans. Jane Marie Toldd (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 2006), 79-115; A. I. Sabra, “Kalâm Atomism as an Alternative Philosophy to Hellenizing Falsafa”, Arabic Theology,
Arabic Philosophy: Essays in Celebration of Richard M. Frank, ed. James E. Montgomery (Leuven: Orientalia Lovaniencia Analecta,
2006), 152-201; Cağfer Karadaş, "The New Approach to The Source of Kalām Atomism", ULUM 1 / 2 (December 2019): 225-244;
Richard M. Frank, “Bodies and Atoms: The Ashcarite Analysis”, in Islamic Theology and Philosophy, ed. Michael E. Marmura (Albany:
State University of New York Press,1984), 39-54.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 225

classical period, and also that he seemed to include such concepts that are seemingly contrary to atomism
as natures (ṭabāʿi) and prime matter (hayūla), have led some scholars think that al-Māturīdī may not have
embraced atomism and even rejected it.3

My objective in this study is to refute the view that Imām al-Māturīdī did not embrace any form of
atomism. Even though al-Māturīdī did not engage in detailed philosophical discussions concerning what
bodies are and of what they are constituted, it is very likely that he accepted this theory, because he seems
to have understood the terms “body”, “substance” and “accident” in accordance with early atomist
mutakallimūn. Indeed, the fact that the Māturīdītes following him did not have doubts about Imām al-
Māturīdī’s acceptance of atomism also supports my thesis. They also defended this theory, which maintains
the idea that the universe is composed of indivisible parts or atoms, without any exception.

1. The Historical and Conceptual Background

As it is known, the science of kalām was established by Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn at the beginning of
the 2 /8th century. The early discussions of mutakallimūn revolved around some inner disputes with
nd

significant theological and political connotations such as the leadership (imāma) of the Islamic community,
the status of the person who committed the grave sin (murtakib al-kabīra), the free will (irāda) and
predestination (qadar).4 However at the end of the 2nd/8th century, they also started to engage in some
philosophical and cosmological issues such as the nature of body, atom, substance, accident, void, motion,
and causation.5 It is still a matter of debate why mutakallimūn became involved in such philosophical and
scientific issues, which were named as “subtle” (daqīq) or “thin/fine” (laṭīf) topics in the classical kalām.6 It
is commonly claimed that this is due to them being theologians in the first place, so they were dealing with
these issues in order to demonstrate and defend the articles of Islam based on reason or to confront non-
Islamic sects by using a universal language.7 However, the level of development and the variety of the
cosmological theories put forward by mutakallimūn indicate that beyond being apologetic theologians,

3
On this issue, see. Yusuf Şevki Yavuz, “İmâm Mâtürîdî’nin Tabiat ve İlliyyete Bakışı”, Büyük Türk Bilgini İmâm Mâtürîdî ve
Mâtürîdîlik: Milletler Arası Tartışmalı İlmi Toplantı (İstanbul, 22-24 Mayıs 2009) (İstanbul: İFAV Publication), 55. Alnoor Dhanani, “al-
Māturīdī and al-Nasafī on Atomism and the Tabā’ī”, Büyük Türk Bilgini İmâm Mâtürîdî ve Mâtürîdîlik: Milletler Arası Tartışmalı İlmi
Toplantı (İstanbul, 22-24 Mayıs 2009) (İstanbul: İFAV Publication), 65 ff. Ulrich Rudolph, Al-Māturīdī and the Development of Sunnī
Theology in Samarqand, trans. Rodrigo Adem (Leiden, Boston: Brill Publication, 2015), 245. Tahir Uluç, İmâm Mâtürîdî’nin Âlemin
Ontolojik Yapısı Hakkında Filozofları Eleştirisi (İstanbul: İnsan Publishing, 2017), 77.
4
Josef van Ess, ‘The Beginnings of Islamic Theology”, in The Cultural Context of Medieval Learning, ed. J. E. Murdoch and E. D. Sylla
(Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1975), 87–111.
5
Dimitri Gutas, Greek Thought Arabic Culture (New York: Routledge, 1999), 70, 74; Majid Fakhry, A History of Islamic Philosophy, Second
Edition (London: Longman, 1983), 42, S. H. Nasr, Islamic Philosophy from its Origin to the Present (New York: State University of New
York Press, 2006) 123; Marwan Rashed, “Natural Philosophy”, in The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, ed. Peter Adamson,
Richard C. Taylor (UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 288; G. C. Anawati, “Kalam”. Encyclopedia of Religion second editioned.
Lindsay Jones (USA: Macmillan 2005), 8/5059.
6
On this issue see. Dhanani, The Physical Theory of Kalam, 3-4; Bulğen, “Klasik Dönem Kelâmında Dakiku’l-Kelâmın Yeri ve Rolü”,
Turkish Journal of Islamic Studies, İslâm Araştırmaları Dergisi, 33 (2015), 39-72.
7
Edward Grant, A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007), 70; Wolfson, The Philosophy of the Kalam, 471.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


226 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

mutakallimūn were also interested in philosophical and scientific issues as seekers of the truth.8 Indeed,
kalām atomism, which is our research topic, also has the characteristics of being a theory that was developed
at a period when there were numerous creative ideas and different points of view about matter and the
universe within kalām circles.9
It will be very useful to look closely at the 3rd/9th century, a time when mutakallimūn were in a spirit
of enormous curiosity and investigation about the universe, in order to see upon what kind of historical and
conceptual background Imām al-Māturīdī’s ideas regarding matter relied. In this context, the book of Abu’l-
Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī (d. 324/935-36), who is the founder of the Ashʿarīyya school, named Maqālāt al-Islāmiyyīn
(The Doctrines of the Muslims) is one of the rare surviving sources that could provide information about the
ideas of mutakallimūn with regard to the physical and cosmological theories of the 3rd/9th and 4th/10th
centuries. Al-Ashʿarī, who is a contemporary of Imām al-Māturīdī, begins the second chapter of his book by
saying “Views of People on Subtle (daqīq) Issues” and in this chapter, he recounts the ideas of Muslim
mutakallimūn about such issues as body, atom, substance, accident, motion in a detailed way.10
al-Ashʿarī reports that at his time mutakallimūn were divided into twelve groups regarding their
understanding of body (jism). As these views relate directly to our topic, it will be important to mention
them here. They can be arranged into the following seven groups:

1) Body is that which carries/accepts the accidents. The first view, which al-Ashʿarī assigns to the
Muʿtazilī mutakallim Abu’l-Ḥusayn al-Ṣāliḥī (3rd/9th century), defines the body as “that which
accepts/carries (yaḥtamilu) accidents (aʿrāḍ)” such as motion and rest. According to him, if an
accident (ʿaraḍ) is carried by something, it cannot be anything other than a body.11
The remarkable aspect of al-Ṣāliḥī in terms of our topic is that, he also calls both “the indivisible
part” (al-juzʾ alladhī lā yatajazzaʾ) and also “the substance” (al-jawhar) as “jism” (body) because it
accepts/carries accidents. According to him, all classes (ajnās) of accidents can be present in the indivisible
part except the accident of aggregation/composition (taʾlīf). Therefore, an atom or indivisible part is a body
because it carries accidents, even though it can exist separately from other indivisible parts.12
2) Body is that which is composite of indivisible parts. This view, which is supported by mutakallimūn
such as ʿĪsā al-Ṣūfī (3rd/9th century) and al-Iskāfī (d. 240/854), who are among the Baghdād school

8
For example, on this issue see. Josef van Ess, Theology and Science: The Case of Abū Isḥaq al-Naẓẓām, Ann Arbor: Center for Near
Eastern and North African Studies, University of Michigan, 1978; Anton M. Heinen, “Mutakallimūn and Mathematicians”, Der
Islam, 55/1 (1978), 57-73. Alnoor Dhanani: “Problems in Eleventh-Century Kalam Physics”, Bulletin of the Royal Institute for Inter-
Faith Studies, 4/1 (Spring/Summer 2002),73-96.
9
Josef van Ess, “Mu’tezilite Atomism” in The Flowering of Muslim Theology translation Jane Marie Todd (England 2006), 79.
10
Along with al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt, one of the books that we are going to frequently consult is Kitāb al-Maqālāt of Abu’l-Qāsim al-
Balkhī al-Kaʿbī (d. 319/931), who is among the leaders of the Baghdād Muʿtazilites and a contemporary of al-Māturīdī. Al-Kaʿbī,
like al-Ashʿarī, in his book opens a chapter, named “thin/fine (laṭīf) subject”, and here he recounts the opinions of kalām scholars
regarding such issues as body, part (atom), substance, accident, motion, time, place, etc. Here the reason why we prioritize al-
Ashʿarī but not al-Kaʿbī, who al-Māturīdī frequently mentions and criticizes, is that al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt is more systematical and
detailed compared to al-Kaʿbī’s Kitāb al-Maqālāt.
11
Abu’l-Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt al-Islāmiyyīn wa ikhtilāf al-muṣallīn, ed. Muḥammad Muḥyī al-Dīn ʻAbd al-Ḥamīd (Cairo: Maktabat
al-Nahḍah al-Miṣriyyah, 2000), 2/4.
12
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/4.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 227

of Muʿtazila, claims that bodies consist of indivisible parts which come together through the
accidents of aggregation (ijtimāʿ) and composition (taʾlīf). Accordingly, when an indivisible part
(al-juzʾ alladhī lā yatajazzaʾ) comes together with another indivisible part, they both become bodies
in a composite manner. However, if they separate from each other, they both lose the
characteristic of being a body. According to al-Iskāfī, body means “composite” (muʾtalif), and when
two parts come together, composition occurs; thus, two parts are sufficient to form the smallest
body.13

We must indicate that this approach of al-Iskāfī, which associates the body with the accident of
composition and finds two atoms sufficient to constitute the smallest body, later on was also widely accepted
by Ashʿarites and Māturīdīs.14
3) Body is that which has three dimensions. Another view that al-Ashʿarī reports is that of defining
the body as length, width, and depth. This view, accepted widely among the Muʿtazilite
mutakallimūn at the time when al-Māturīdī lived, was supported not only by the mutakallimūn but
also by some philosophers (falāsifā).15 Nevertheless, while philosophers argued that the three-
dimensional body is compound per se, the mutakallimūn claimed that it is a composite entity
consisting of indivisible parts that come together by means of the accident of aggregation
(ijtimāʿ/taʾlīf).16 These mutakallimūn pointed out that the indivisible parts are dimensionless.
Moreover, they were not able to reach an agreement on the minimum number of parts that are
necessary to form the smallest body.17 Abu’l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf (d. 235/849-59 [?]) claimed that six
indivisible parts could form a three-dimensional body by coming together, whereas Hishām b.
ʿAmr al-Fuwaṭī (d. 218/833) regarded what Abu’l-Hudhayl deemed to be a part as underlying
element (rukn), and asserted that the smallest body consists of six underlying elements (arkān) in
a manner that each of its underlying elements has six indivisible parts. Muʿammar b. ʿAbbād al-

13
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/4-5.
14
For example, see. Abū l-Maʿālī al-Juwaynī, al-Irshād, ed. Muḥammad Yūsuf Musa – Al Abdulḥāmid (Cairo: Maktaba al-hanci 1950),
17; on this issue see. Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu, 178.
15
al-Kaʿbī says as follows: “Muʿtazilite and most kalām scholars (aktharu ahl al-naẓar) said: Body (jism) is that which is long, wide,
and deep. (However) it is different from length, width, depth and other accidents. And, it (body) is the carrier (al-ḥāmil) of
accidents. It is not permissible for the body to get rid of all the accidents and the accidents can only be found in the body.” al-
Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 445. It is possible to interpret al-Kaʿbī’s expressions in a way that Muʿtazilites and the most kalām scholars
do not count a dimensionless thing as a body.
16
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/4.
17
Muʿtazilite Mutakallim and Zaidī Imām Ibn al-Murtaḍā (d. 840/1437) explains the controversies which took place among
mutakallimūn about the number of the atoms constituting the minimal body as follows: “Substance (al-jawhar) is that which is
possible to occupy space (taḥayyuz) and impossible to separate (yastaḥīlu tajazziaʾ). If another one is added to it from the level of
those who look at it, it becomes a line. If four square (murabbaʿa) comes together, they become surface. If [the surface] conjoins
to its alike, it becomes a body. This is the least of the body. Abu’l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf says: Conversely, the least of the body is
formed by a combination of six [atoms]. al-Kaʿbī says: It is four; one of them is placed above one of the remaining three. Ashʿarīs
say: Instead, the least of it is two; because the body is that which is composite (al-muallaf). Karrāmiyya says, on the other hand,
body is that which stands by itself. We say as follows: In the lexicon, the body means that something in which length, width, and
depth come together (ijtamaʿa), and it only consists of eight substances. Based on this, if there is an increase in terms of these
elements, they say: It becomes more voluminous (ajsama).” in Ibn al-Murtaḍā, “Riyāḍat al-afhām fī laṭīf al-kalām” in Al-Baḥr al-
Zakhkhār al-Jāmiʿ li-Madhāhib ʿUlamāʾ al-Amṣār, ed. Muḥammad Tamir (Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-ʿIlmīyah, 2001), 1/116

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


228 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Sulamī (d. 215/830), whose body formula will be accepted widely later on, argued that eight parts
must come together to form the smallest body.18
4) Body is that which consists of substances. Another noteworthy approach towards the nature of
the body that al-Ashʿarī conveys belongs to al-Naẓẓām, who is among the sixth generation of
Muʿtazilī scholars. According to him, the only accident is motion (ḥaraka), and such qualities as
color, taste, smell, heat, and coldness that are regarded as accidents by the vast majority of
mutakallimūn would indeed be interpenetrated substances within a body.19

Another characteristic of al-Naẓẓām is that he is a strong opponent of the kalām atomism. Even
tough, like above-mentioned mutakallimūn, he defines the body as that which is long, wide and deep; on the
other hand, he maintains that there is no end in dividing a body. Al-Ashʿarī reports that al-Naẓẓām held the
opinion that there is a half for every half, and there is a part for every part.20
5) Body is that which consists of substances and accidents. This opinion, which belongs to ʿAbbād b.
Sulaymān, one of the eminent mutakallimūn of the Basra school within the Muʿtazila, maintains
that a body is made up of substance and accidents from which is not separated. According to him,
the accidents that come apart from its substance are not body. Al-Ashʿarī also reports that ʿAbbād
said that “body is the place (al-makān)”. ʿAbbād provides evidence for his claim that God is not a
body by saying “If He were a body, He would be a place.” and “If He were a body, He would have a
half.”21

18
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/4-5; Shīʿī Mutakallim al-Shaykh al-Mufīd (d. 413/1022) narrates the ideas of kalām scholars on the topic in
the following manner: “I say that bodies are substances which are combined together (al-jawāhir al-muallafa) in terms of length,
width and depth. Bodies are composed of at least eight parts (ajzāʾ). Two of them are in a manner that is above from the other
in terms of length. [The other] two conjoin to these two substances from the right or left side, and consequently, width
originates. The remaining four are at the opposite of the aforementioned four substances, and as a result depth occurs. Some
kalām scholars are in favor of this opinion. While one group claim that bodies are composed of six parts, the other one state that
they are constituted from four parts. Another group, on the other hand, said that bodies are composite things (muallaf) and
compositeness can happen even by two parts.” al-Shaykh al-Mufīd, Awāil al-Maqālāt, ed. Ibrāhim al-Anṣārī (Mashad: el-Muʿtamar
al-ʿĀlam li Alfiyyah al-Shaykh al-Mufīd, 1413/2000), 97-98. The reason why Muʿtazilīte scholars focus on the idea that bodies are
three-dimensional is that they believe that an atom or indivisible part has no dimension per se. Dimensionless of atom enabled
them to defend that division is not only possible in actuality (bi’l-fʿil) but also in mind (wahm). It is also not possible for an
indivisible part or atom to have different directions and ends. For, possessing different parts and dimension such as left-right,
bottom-top, length-width would require the indivisible to be divisible in mind. On this issue see. al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/5-6. Also
see. Ibn Mattawayh, al-Tadhkirah fī aḥkām al-jawāhir wa-al-aʿrāḍ, ed. Daniel Gimaret (Cairo: Institut Français d’Archélogie
Orientale, 2009), 1/9; Bulğen, Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri, 68.
19
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/23; al-Kaʿbī tells that al-Naẓẓām said the followings: “According to us, visible body is nothing but such
elements as color, taste, smell, sound, flexibility and etc. These things, which are bodies (ajsām) in themselves, combine
(ijtamaʿa), interpenetrate (tadākhala), and then form the dense body (al-jism al-kathīf). Length is that which is long. Width is that
which is wide. There no body other than interlocked length and width. This is his view of inanimate objects. As for the soul (al-
rūḥ), it is a thin/transparent body (jism laṭīf) and one thing (shayʾ wāḥid). All living things are one genre (jins wāḥid).” See. al-
Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 444.
20
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/6; That al-Naẓẓām said qualities are substances and regarded them as composed of infinite parts caused
him to be subjected intense criticisms by both kalām scholars themselves and philosophers. al-Naẓẓām attempted to respond to
these criticisms by introducing some theories such as “interpenetration” (tadākhul), “latency” (al-kumūn), “manifestation” (al-
ẓuhūr) and leap (ṭafra). On this issue see. Bulğen, Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri, 77-112.
21
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/6.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 229

6) Body is that which is formed through a collection of accidents. One of the remarkable opinions
that al-Ashʿarī recounts with regard to the nature of bodies belongs to Ḍirār b. ʿAmr (d. 200/815
[?]), who is among the first representatives of the Baṣra Muʿtazilites. He claims that bodies are a
bundle of accidents i.e. that they are constituted by a combination of different types of accidents.
According to him, bodies cannot be abstracted from accidents such as color, taste, measurement,
weightiness, weightlessness, heat, coldness, dryness, wetness, life, and death and from their
opposites. al-Ashʿarī also reports: Ḍirār says that accidents cannot preserve their existence if they
are separated from the body, and that for a body to cease to exist indicates the decomposition of
accidents.22
7) Body is that which exists. Another view about the body, which al-Ashʿarī conveys, is supported
by Hishām b. al-Ḥakam (d. 179/795), who is a Shīʿī mutakallim. He refers to “existent” (mawjūd),
thing (shayʾ) and “that which stands by itself” (al-qāim bi nafsihi) rather than “composition”
(muallaf) by uttering the term “body”.23 These opinions of Hishām, later on, will be subject to much
criticism by many mutakallimūn, including Imām al-Māturīdī, because it will pave the way to call
Allah a body (tajsīm) [corporealism] and thereby a likening (tashbīh) [anthropomorphism]
between Allah and the creation will be brought about.

The most striking part of the above-mentioned accounts given by al-Ashʿarī with regards to the
definition of body is that the Muslim mutakallimūn of al-Māturīdī’s age were in an environment of sharp
disagreements and disputes. Almost all mutakallimūn accepted different theses concerning the nature of
bodies and their qualities. At that time, there were mutakallimūn defending atomism, particularly Abu’l-
Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf, on the other hand, there were some who objected to atomism such as al-Naẓẓām. Again,
these controversies reveal that in that period, such concepts as “part” (juzʾ), “substance” (jawhar), and
“accident” (ʿaraḍ) took center stage on the subject of the elements that compose bodies.

If we take a closer look at these concepts, in that period, it can be realized that mutakallimūn mostly
preferred the word “part” (juzʾ) to indicate the indivisible parts of the body. Imām al-Ashʿarī states that
Muslim mutakallimūn are divided into 14 sects concerning whether it is permissible for things in a body to
become entirely separate from each other as a result of the composition or for a body to turn into an
indivisible part. The accounts that al-Ashʿarī reported can be put into three categories, first eleven of which

22
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/6-7; al-Kaʿbī narrates Ḍirār’s opinions based on Ibn al-Rāwandī (d. 301/913-14 [?]) in the following way:
“Ḍirār said bodies are composed (allafa) and combined (jumiʿa) accidents. Thanks to this, they straighten up and become fixed,
and turn into bodies that accidents inhere on themselves and transform into one state from one state. Bodies must consist of
such accidents as life, death, colors and tastes and the contraries of them. However, such accidents, which neither themselves
nor their contraries can be separated from bodies, as pleasure, anguish, knowledge, illiteracy are not among the parts of bodies,
for a dead person becomes abstracted from all of these accidents. Because, according to him, these accidents cannot turn into
bodies again after they exist once and then perish. It is only possible at the moment of their first creation. Because these
accidents can only be originated collectively. According to him, when they are existent, they can all come together; however,
they cannot be separated altogether. He (Ibn al-Rāwandī) said: When I told him (Ḍirār) that based on this analogy it would not
be permissible for them to be separated (al-iftirāq)”; at one time he said, “their separation means their annihilation (fanāʾ)”, and
at another time he said, “two bodies can be separated, but once they exist, the parts of bodies (abʿāḍ al-ajsām) cannot be
separated”. al-Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 443-444.
23
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/6.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


230 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

belongs to the mutakallimūn accepting atomism, and two of which belongs to those who oppose atomism
and the last of which belongs to those on the fence i.e., agnostic, about the issue.24
a) The Atomists

When al-Ashʿarī’s explanations are taken into consideration, it is seen that a vast majority of the
Muslim mutakallimūn adopted the view that “the indivisible part” or “atom” is existent.25 However, these
mutakallimūn could not reach an agreement on whether the atoms are bodies, substances, or accidents,
whether the atoms are visible; and whether parts have directions/sides (jihāt) and ends (nihāyāt). Also, they
failed to agree on at least how many atoms are needed to form the smallest body, and how many atoms can
come into contact simultaneously with the atoms like themselves, and which accidents the atoms can carry
when they are not aggregated to another atom.26 Similarly, the accounts he conveyed contain the hot
debates among the mutakallimūn about the idea, which represent one of the key elements of the kalām
atomism, that indivisible parts, when separated, do not have dimensions (abʿād) and that they attain such
qualities as length, width, and depth (al-abʿād al-thalātha) after they come together and become a body.27
Another outstanding view among the ones al-Ashʿarī reported belongs to “the proponents of
accidents” (aṣhāb al-aʿrāḍ) such as Ḍirār b. ʿAmr, Ḥafṣ al-Fard, and Ḥusayn al-Najjār, who support a bundle
theory i.e., the thesis that bodies consist of the originated accidents such as color, taste, heat, coldness,
firmness, and softness, have an atomists point of view as well. Just as other atomist mutakallimūn discussed
the least required number of parts needed to form a body, in the opinion of the aforesaid mutakallimūn, i.e.
at least ten parts must come together to form a body. Moreover, they also repudiated the thesis regarding

24
For detailed evaluation of this classification see. Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu, 176-186.
25
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/13-16.
26
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/13-16.
27
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/13-16. Ibn al-Murtaḍā conveys the debates among the mutakallimūn regarding whether a substance has a
directions/sides (jihāt) as follows: “Abū ‘Alī, Qāḍī al-Quḍāt and al-Kaʿbī says: Side of the substance (jihat al-jawhar) depends on
what is outside of itself. On the contrary, Abū Hāshim says: It depends on the substance itself. We, on the other hand, say: We
know this through an indication and do not assume it as seeing. Affirmation of the sides for a substance entails its separation
(tajazziaʾ). Abū Hāshim says: Substance can adhere to six [substances], which is equivalent to itself. Consequently, it happens to
have six sides. I say: Because the second opinion requires the division of substance, the first opinion is more compelling (aqwā).”
Ibn al-Murtaḍā, Riyāḍat al-afhām fī laṭīf al-kalām, 117. Abū Rashīd al-Nīsābūrī (d. 415/1024) quoted the following in terms of the
discussion on whether the aspect of the particle is external to it or belongs to it essentially: “Our Sheikh Abū Hāshim defended
the view that the sides/directions (jihāt) belongs to the part. However, Abu’l-Qāsim (al-Kaʿbī) claimed that it is separate from it.
Abū ‘Alī also supported him in this regard. The view, which is the closest to the truth in this issue, is that the sides belongs to
the substance. For, thanks to its space occupation (taḥayyuz), it meets with six parts like itself. Those who do not accept that the
aspect belongs to the substance do not deny this. See. Abū Rashīd al-Nīsābūrī, Masāʾil fī al-Khilāf bayn al-Basriyyīn wa al-
Baghdādiyyīn, ed. Ma‘n Ziyada and Ridwan al-Sayyid (Beirut: Ma‘had al-Inma’ al-‘Arabi, 1979), 59-60; al-Nīsābūrī here considered
that thanks to the feature to occupy space, the substance is located at a particular direction, it aggregates with six atoms like
itself, it prevents another substance from being in the space it occupies. However, he also defended the view that this would not
require the substance to be divisible in actual or conceptual terms. also see, Ibn Mattawayh, al-Tadhkirah, 86-89. By considering
these discussions, Alnoor Dhanani states that the kalām atomism are formulated within the framework of a discrete geometry
– similar to the Epicurean minimal parts. For, he reckoned that the following expressions, which are widely used by the
mutakallimūn, make sense only in the context of discrete geometry: “the atom does not possess length, width, and breadth”, “the
smallest line (or length) is made out of two atoms”, “the smallest plane (or length and width) is made out of two smallest
contiguous lines”, and “the smallest body (or length, width, and breadth) is made out of two planes which are put on top of each
other”. See Alnoor Dhanani, The Physical Theory of Kalam, 133.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 231

the interpenetration of the bodies (tadāhkul), supported by al-Naẓẓām, just as other atomist mutakallimūn
did, and they maintained the idea that these parts can only come together through being adjacent
(mujāwara) to each other.28 Indeed, al-Kaʿbī, who is a contemporary of al-Māturīdī, reports that some
mutakallimūn such as Ḥusayn al-Najjār, who supports the idea that bodies in the universe are formed through
the unification of the accidents, say the following:
Big bodies (al-ajsām al-ʿiẓām) can be divided up to the last part which is indivisible (juzʾ lā yatajazzaʾ). This part
is a body and it is the smallest of the bodies (asgharu’l-ajsām). It has length, width and depth. However, it cannot
be divided further or become separated (lan yajūzu an yunṣafa aw yatajazzaʾa). For it ceases to exist in this case.29

The attention-grabbing part of this explanation of al-Kaʿbī is that those who claimed that bodies are
formed by composition of the accidents, had atomistic approach by maintaining the divisibility of bodies up
to the last indivisible part. On the other hand, their account implies that this last indivisible part is still a
composite body which includes certain accidents. This indicates that the indivisible part of body can be
divided both mentally and actually. However, according to them, this division results in the annihilation of
the indivisible part rather than causing the formation of ever smaller parts. This is because accidents cannot
preserve their existence if the composite body is entirely separated.30
It will be significantly important for our discussion to note the details that al-Ashʿarī reports, such
as atoms not having sides (jihāt) or ends (nihāyāt), or dimensions (abʿād), a well as that they attained these
qualities after they come together through the accident of composition (taʾlīf), and that this would be the
reason why bodies could be called “composite” (muallaf). We will return to these discussions when we are
dealing with al-Māturīdī’s views on atomism.
b) The Anti-atomists

In the era when Imām al-Ashʿarī and Imām al-Māturīdī lived, there were some mutakallimūn, who
opposed atomism by claiming that bodies could be divided ad infinitum, even though the majority of
mutakallimūn adopted an atomistic approach with regard to the objects in the universe (ʿālam). Imām al-
Ashʿarī makes a distinction between two anti-atomist views just as he put the atomists under different
groups.
The first of two views is attributed to al-Naẓẓām. He is said to have claimed that every part has a
part, every piece has a piece, and every half has a half. Therefore, according to him, bodies can be divided
ad infinitum.31

28
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/15-16.
29
al-Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 451.
30 al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/6-7; al-Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 443-444.
31
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/16. According to the accounts al-Kaʿbī gives, al-Naẓẓām based his opinion on a theological argument as
follows: “Just as it is impossible (muḥāl) for God to create something and then to not be able create something bigger than it, it
is also impossible for him to be unable to create something smaller (asgharu) than it.” See. al-Kaʿbī, Kitāb al-Maqālāt, 451. Kalām
scholars attempted to confront al-Naẓẓām’s criticism by introducing the “non-dimensional atom” idea. According to atomist
mutakallimūn the reason that indivisible substance or part cannot be divided into smaller parts is not that it is too small but it is
“dimensionless”, like “point” in mathematic. Because it is absurd to divide something dimensionless, i.e., that does not have
sides (jihāt) or ends (nihāyāt), or dimensions (abʿād), it would also be absurd to associate God’s power with dividing atoms. For
God’s power is not related to absurd/impossible things (muḥālāt). The fact that atomist kalām scholars substantiated their claim

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


232 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

al-Ashʿarī ascribes another anti-atomist view to some philosophers (mutafalsifa) without giving their
names. They would have argued that bodies are finite in actuality (fī fiʿl), but there would be no end to divide
them in terms of possibility (fi’l-quwwa wa’l-imkān).32 We know that this view, which is based on Aristotle’s
hylomorphic (prime matter-form) theory, is advocated by some peripatetic philosophers such as al-Kindī
(d. 252/866 [?]), al-Fārābī (d. 339/950), and Ibn Sīnā (d. 428/1037).33
The fact that al-Ashʿarī distinguished the two anti-atomist views of al-Naẓẓām and those
philosophers from each other implies that al-Naẓẓām maintains the idea that bodies are formed through the
composition of actual infinite parts. Indeed, that al-Naẓẓām adopts the “leap” (ṭafra) theory to solve the
problem occurring about the movement in the infinitely divisible space and that he accepts the
interpenetration (tadākhul), latency (al-kumūn) and manifestation (al-ẓuhūr) of bodies indicate that he was
in favor of the thesis that bodies are created through the composition of an infinite number of parts or
substances.34 Thus, whereas Islamic philosophers maintained that bodies have the potential to be infinitely
divided, they did not need to produce such theories as leap, interpenetration, latency, manifestation, and
they opposed these types of ideas.35 However, it needs to be mentioned that some Muʿtazilī mutakallimūn
such as al-Kaʿbī and al-Khayyāṭ (300/913 [?]) are of different opinions about al-Naẓẓām.36 For instance, al-
Kaʿbī gives the following account of al-Naẓẓām:
Body (al-jism) can be divided (yatajazzaʾu) ad infinitum (bi-lānihaya). Each part (kulla juzʾ) of the body is again a
body (jism). (Infinite division) does not occur in the body in actuality (bi’l-fiʿl). This is something that is only

that a division would be absurd in all ways depending on the dimensionless nature of atoms led them to attach very much
importance to the idea of atoms being dimensionless and bodies being three dimensional (al-abʿād al-thalātha). Concerning the
arguments the atomist Abu’l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf and anti-atomist al-Naẓẓām put forward against each other, see my book, Klasik
İslam Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri = Critisims of Atomism in Classical Islamic Thought, 79.
32
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/16.
33
On this issue see. Bulğen, Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri, 135.
34
Ibn al-Murtaḍā relates the discussions of the mutakallimūn of the classical period regarding atomism in the following manner:
“People of Basra claims that the individual substance (al-jawhar al-fard) cannot be separated, al-Naẓẓām, on the contrary,
maintains that it can be divided infinitely (lā ilā nihāya). Some of them refrained from giving an opinion, and philosophers (al-
falāsifa) have different views. We say: If it [atom] separated, it would be composite (muallaf), and it would not be impossible for
each body to be infinitely divided. Because it [the division] would not end. Due to this entailment, Al-Naẓẓām had to defend the
leap (ṭafra) theory. See. Ibn al-Murtaḍā, Riyāzat al-afhām fī laṭīf al-kalām, 117.
35
Bulğen, Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri, 84.
36
al-Khayyāṭ, who is one of the Muʿtazilites mutakallimūn, especially exerted himself to make the views attributed to al-Naẓẓām
and heavily criticized such as leap, latency, manifestation, interpenetration, infinite divisibility of bodies, coherent by
moderating them. For instance, he defended the view that al-Naẓẓām did not advocate infinite division, rather he was of the
mind that a thing, which is finite in one respect needs to be finite in other respects as well, which is compatible with the general
views of the mutakallimūn. See, al-Khayyāṭ, Kitāb al-Intiṣār, 33. al-Khayyāṭ also stated that the view which is attributed to al-
Naẓẓām “There is no such thing that is traversed and would not be infinite” is actually a slander brought forward by Ibn al-
Rāwandī (d. 301/913-14 [?]). In al-Khayyāṭ’s account, Materialists (Dahriyya) claimed that bodies are not limited in terms of
quantity and size, and by contrast, al-Naẓẓām demonstrated that bodies are limited in terms of quantity and size on the basis of
the fact that bodies can be traversed. See, Kitāb al-Intiṣār, 35; al-Khayyāṭ also stated that the theory of latency and manifestation
is also a slander mounted by Ibn al-Rāwandī against al-Nazzām. See, al-Khayyāṭ Kitāb al-Intiṣār ed. Albert Nasri Nader (Beirut: al-
Matbaat al-Katulikiyya, 1957), 52.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 233

imaginary (mawhūm) and intelligible (maʿqūl) . Furthermore, bodies do not have a limit in terms of their sides
(jihātihi).37

As is seen, al-Kaʿbī, contrary to what is commonly believed, states that al-Naẓẓām does not defend
the view indicating that bodies are formed by a combination of an infinite number of substances. According
to him, al-Naẓẓām like the philosophers claimed that bodies could be divided infinitely in supposition (bi’l-
quwwa wa’l-imkān).
c) Agnostics

According to al-Ashʿarī, at that time, some people had a skeptical approach towards atomism and
said that they do not know whether the atom is divisible or not.38

At the time when Imām al-Ashʿarī and Imām al-Māturīdī lived, another concept that left its mark on
the discussions regarding the nature of the bodies and atomism was “substance” (jawhar). Imām al-Ashʿarī
lists the different views of people at that time about the concept of substance by dividing them into four
groups:

(1) Christians (al-Naṣārā): Substance is that which stands by itself (al-qāʾim bi nafsihi).
(2) Some philosophers (al-Mutafalsifa): Substance is that which stands by itself and accepts the
contraries.

(3) Abū ʿAlī al-Jubbāʾī (d. 303/915): Substance is that which bears (al-ḥāmil) the accidents when it
exists. According to al-Ashʿarī, al-Jubbāʾī claimed that substances become substances by virtue of
themselves and that they are known as substances even before they come into being.
(4) al-Ṣāliḥī: Substance is that which bears/accepts (iḥtamala) the accidents. According to him, a
substance can exist without accidents being created for it, and it can carry accidents without being a locus
for them.”39
The abovementioned accounts about the definition of the term substance (jawhar) given by al-
Ashʿarī show that in that period, this term substance was not used to signify atoms alone as it was common
in the later periods in kalām, but rather it had multiple meanings. The definitions of substance provided in
that era draw more attention to such essential qualities of substances as being self-subsistent (qāʾim bi
nafsihi) and being a locus/substratum (maḥāl) for accidents.

al-Ashʿarī recounts the views concerning the question of whether all substances are bodies or
whether there are some substances that are not bodies, by classifying them into three groups:

(1) Some atomist mutakallimūn such as Abu’l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf, Muʿammar and al-Jubbāʾī defended
the impossibility of a single substance which is indivisible (al-jawhar al-wāḥid alladhī lā yanqasimu) to be a

37
al-Kaʿbī, Māqalāt, 445.
38
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/16.
39
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/8.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


234 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

body. This is because, according to them, body would be that which is length (al-ṭawīl), width (al-ʿarīḍ), and
depth (al-ʿamīq). Since a single substance does not have any dimension, it cannot be a body.40
(2) The second view, which al-Ashʿarī mentions, is attributed to al-Ṣāliḥī, and as we can see based
on his approach to body, he prefers to refer to substance as “body” (jism) because it accepts accidents, even
though he adopts the theory of atomism.

(3) The last view divides substances into two categories. The first of them considers a substance as
a being a compound (murakkab) whereas the second category regards substance as a being a non-compound.
This shows that using the word “substance” in that period did not mean the adoption of the theory of
atomism.41

Another crucial debate about the substance (jawhar) is whether it is homogeneous (jins wāḥid). al-
Ashʿarī classifies the views concerning this matter into seven groups. Accordingly, while (1) Aristotelians,
who consider the universe to be one single substance, defended that substances might differ from or be
similar to accidents, (2) Muʿtazilī al-Jubbāʾī claims that substances per se are homogeneous. (3) Dualists
argued that substances are two genera being light and darkness. Also, whereas (4) Marqūnīya claimed that
they are three genera (ajnās), (5) naturalists (aṣḥāb al-ṭabāʿī) maintained that substances are four contrary
genera hot and cold, moist and dry. Moreover, (6) some argued that substances are five genera consisting of
four natures and the spirit (rūḥ) by adding spirit into the substance theory of naturalists. Lastly, (7) al-
Naẓẓām regarded the accidents included on the contrary genus (ajnās) as substances and enumerated them
as whiteness, blackness, yellowness, redness, greenness, heat, coldness, sweetness, tartness, smell, taste,
humidness, dryness, shape and spirit. According to him, all living beings have homogeneous spirits.42

What draws attention among al-Ashʿarī’s narrations is the subtle differences between Aristotle’s
concept of substance (jawhar) and that of al-Jubbāʾī who embraced atomism. Aristotle, who did not accept
the existence of void and adopted the idea of the continuity of the universe, claimed that the universe as a
whole is a single substance and that substances share differences and similarities based on the accidents
alone. According to al-Jubbāʾī, however, the universe consists of numerous indivisible substances, and they
are homogeneous by themselves, not because of the accidents they inhere. This claim of al-Jubbāʾī is
significant in that it shows that each and every substance is individual (fard) and one (wāḥid) in itself.
According to the atomist mutakallimūn, since substances carry accidents as secondary qualities, they do not
cause an essential alteration, contrary to what Aristotle states. Even though the accidents are not durable,
substances can have the accident of permanence/continuity (baqāʾ); therefore, they retain their existence.43

40
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/8; This opinion of them, which identifies the substance (jawhar) with atom, will be widely accepted by the
Ashʿarites and Māturīdites with the name “single substance” (al-jawhar al-wāḥid) and “individual substance” (al-jawhar al-fard).
Regarding this see. Bulğen, Kelâm atomculuğu, 186.
41
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/8.
42
Maqālāt, 2/9. Al-Sheikh al-Mufīd expresses his opinion about the issue as follows: “All substances/atoms (al-jawāhir) are from the
same genus (mutajānis). Differentiation only happens through the accidents (al-aʿrāḍ) that are different in themselves. Most of
the Ahl al-Tawḥīd think the same.” Awāil al-Maqālāt, 95.
43
Ibn al-Murtaḍā demonstrates mutakallimūn’s different opinions about the persistence/continuity (al-baqāʾ) of the substance as
follows: “The majority say: [substance] is that which is persistent, that is, whose existence is continuous (mustamir al-wujūd). al-
Naẓẓām says: Instead, the existence of substance is renewed (yatajaddadu) from one state to another along with the agent (bi’l-
fā‘il). We say: We necessarily know that a body we see today is the body we saw yesterday and that condemning an act belonging

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 235

Before proceeding to Imām al-Māturīdī’s ideas on atomism, we must highlight the concept of
“accident” because this concept has a significant place and role in the classical mutakallimūn including al-
Māturīdī.

al-Ashʿarī’s accounts in Maqālāt indicate that, except Abū Bakr al-Aṣamm44 (d. 200/816),
mutakallimūn, in general, have accepted the existence of accidents and that they used this utterance to refer
to the secondary qualities, which are contrary pairs and attained by substances in time, such as motion-rest,
composition-decomposition, heat-coldness, death-life, color, knowledge, will.45 According to the majority
of mutakallimūn, these accidents, each of which indicates a certain meaning in the mind, cannot exist in the
extra-mental realm by themselves without being carried by a material locus/substratum (maḥal). Similarly,
accidents cannot carry accidents; instead, they are carried by substances standing by themselves. On the
other hand, it is not possible for a substance to be devoid of spatial accidents such as motion, rest,
composition, and separation. If substances are incapable of being free from originated accidents, this implies
that substances are also originated.46
Based on al-Ashʿarī’s descriptions, it will be noticed that most mutakallimūn have accepted the
substance-accident dualism; however, as previously mentioned, there were also those like Ḍirār b. ʿAmr who
defended the notion that the universe was formed completely out of accidents or others like al-Naẓẓām who
accepted that only motion was an accident and that therefore other things which other mutakallimūn
identified as accidents were in fact substances. Also, mutakallimūn were in disagreement regarding issues
such as whether atoms carried certain acc idents individually or as composites.
Another noteworthy dispute concerning our topic that al-Ashʿarī recounted about accidents is the
question of whether accidents are continuous. Most mutakallimūn accepted that bodies and substances were

to yesterday is regarded as gratifying. A matter: Abu Hāshim al-Jubbāī claims that the substance is described with permanence
(al-baqāʾ); conversely, Abū ʿAlī al-Jubbāī maintains that only Allah can be attributed with persistence (al-baqaʾ) and eternality
(qidam). We say: Permanence only means the continuity of an existent within two-time units. Eternity, on the other hand,
indicates the presence of existence before anything else. Therefore, the one that is in such a manner is described with these
two.” See. Ibn al-Murtaḍā, Riyāḍat al-afhām fī laṭīf al-kalām, 115; also see. al-Sheikh al-Mufīd, Awāil alMaqālāt, 96-97; Ibn Mattawayh
al-Tadhkirah fī aḥkām al-jawāhir wa-al-aʿrāḍ, 1/37; Sayf al-Dīn al-Ᾱmidī, Abkār al-Afkār fī Uṣūl al-Dīn. ed. A. al-Mahdī (Cairo: Dār al-
Kutub, 2002), 3/36.
44
al-Asamm, who is a member of Baṣra Muʿtazila, maintained that what really matters is bodies having length, width and depth,
and that the existence of accidents, outside bodies, such as action, standing up, sitting, composition, separation, motion, rest,
color, sound, taste and smell cannot be proven in actuality. It is attention-grabbing that this claim of al-Asamm resembles the
antic Greek atomists, who state that all physical and spiritual qualities except from atoms are mere subjective ideas and reduce
them into primary qualities such as shape and volume. On this issue, see. Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu, 73.
45
Maqālāt, 2/44; for detailed information about accidents see. Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu, 199.
46
al-Sheikh al-Mufīd conveys the related discussions in the following manner: “I say that each accident can inhere (ḥulūl) in
substance (al-jawhar). Substance becomes the recipient (muḥtamil) of the accident to exists. For substances cannot be devoid of
accidents or other subsequent accidents. This is the opinion of Abu’l-Qāsim al-Balhkī and Abū ʿAli al-Jubbāī. Most of the
preceding kalām scholars also thought the same way. On this issue, [Abū Hāshim] ʿAbdussalām b. Muhammad al-Jubbāī [d.
321/933] thought differently and regarded it as permissible that substances can be detached from colors, tastes, smells, and
similar accidents.” Awāil al-Maqālāt, 96. However, we must note that this expression of al-Kaʿbī does not mean that Abū Hāshim
maintained that substances could be entirely free from accidents. Because according to him, substances cannot be devoid of
such spatial accidents as motion-rest and composition-separation (al-akwān). Regarding this topic, see. al-Nīsābūrī, Masāʾil fī al-
Khilāf, 62 ff.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


236 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

continuous, and some believed that some accidents were also continuous.47 al-Ashʿarī divides the views held
by the mutakallimūn into six different categories. According to this classification, the first group, including
Abu’l-Qāsim al-Kaʿbī al-Balkhī from the Baghdād school (d. 319/913), a contemporary of al-Māturīdī, argued
that accidents could not exist in two separate time frames, even though they recognized the existence of all
accidents including colors, tastes, smells, life, power, death, voice, and sounds.48 Abu’l-Hudhayl and al-
Jubbāī, from the Baṣra school, defended the idea that while certain accidents were continuous, others were
not. For example, according to Abu’l-Hudhayl, accidents like colors, tastes, smells, life and power were
permanent. However, motion was not permanent, and for this reason all movement in the hereafter, i.e.
heaven and hell, would end one day, leaving its place for the permanent accident of rest. According to
Ḍirār b. ʿAmr and Ḥusayn al-Najjār, who believed that the universe was composed solely of accidents;
accidents were permanent when they were inside of bodies, but those accidents, which are separated from
bodies, could not exist in two different time units. However, as opposed to Ḍirār, Najjār did not consider
human capacity for action to be a body; and therefore, argued that it was not permanent. al-Naẓẓām, who
did not believe that any accidents existed besides motion, argued that motion was not permanent but
continuously renewed. Lastly, Bishr b. al-Muʿtamir (d. 210-225/825-840), the founder of the Baghdād school
of the Muʿtazila school, argued that all accidents were permanent and that an accident would never end
unless it is replaced by its opposite.49 The views of mutakallimūn regarding the issue of the continuity of
accidents had an impact on their understanding of theological issues such as the creation of the universe,
causality, human acts, miracles, and even the afterlife.
In summary, the discussions regarding the concepts of body, atom, substance, and accident, as
derived from the work of Maqālāt by Imām al-Ashʿarī and al-Kaʿbī, show that, in the lifetime of Imām al-
Māturīdī, there were many differing opinions held by the mutakallimūn on the structure and qualities of the

47
On this issue see. Ahmet Şenharputlu, Klasik Kelâm Döneminde Arazların Bekası Sorunu (Unpublished MA Thesis, Marmara
University Institute of Social Sciences, 2017).
48
Maqālāt, 2/44.
49
Maqālāt, 2/44; al-Sheikh al-Mufīd narrates the opinions of mutakallimūn related to the matter as follows: “Substances are among
the things whose persistence (al-baqāʾ) is permissible. Most of the time they exist and then they disappear from the world as
soon as the persistence leaves them. Most of the members of Ahl al-Tawḥīd hold this opinion. Abu’l-Qāsim al-Balkhī also accepted
this view. However, both himself and Abū ‘Ali al-Jubbāī, also his son Abū Hāshim al-Jubbāī, as well as Nawbahtiyyans out of the
Imāmiyyah and their followers opposed this view we described above concerning the reason for the disappearance of
substances. al-Naẓẓām, on the other hand, believed in a completely different way from all of them and claimed that Allah
recreates bodies again and again (yatajaddadu) and brings them into existence (yaḥduthu) each moment. (…) Consequently,
bodies are among persistent things and I have already said this about atom (al-jawhar al-munfarida). In my opinion, neither the
accident of aggregation (al-ta’līf) nor other accidents are continuous. This opinion belongs to Abu’l-Qāsim al-Balkhī and a
preceding group from Baghdād Muʿtazila. Apart from al-Naẓẓām, no one among the Ahl al-Tawḥīd has thought differently in
this issue. al-Naẓẓām, however, asserted that bodies are being recreated (tatajaddadu) each moment.” See. Awāil al-Maqālāt, 96,
98; al-Sheikh al-Mufīd also says: “I say: Accidents are significances that needs locus. Persistence is not possible for any kind of
accident. This is the opinion of most of Baghdād Muʿtazilites. However, Baṣras and other sects thinks differently on this issue.”
Awāil al-Maqālāt, 97. In this regard, Imāmu’l-Ḥaramayn al-Juwaynī (d. 478/1085) stated that al-Naẓẓām identified substances with
the accidents and defended that substances are renewed on each instant by considering accidents substances. In al-Juwaynī’s
account, this view of al-Nazzām leads to a position which is not compatible with the necessary (iḍṭirārī) knowledge. It would lead
to absurd situations, in which two individuals, who discuss with each other, would not be the same persons at the end of the
discussion, since they are renewed in time. See, al-Juwaynī, al-Shāmil fī uṣūl al-dīn, Ed. ʻAlī Sāmī Nashshār, Fayṣal Budayr ʻAwn,
Suhayr Muḥammad Mukhtār (Alexandria: Munshaʾāt al-Maʿārif, 1969), 160.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 237

entities that make up the universe. In that period, the conceptual solidification of 5th/11th century had not
yet emerged. As there were those who said that the universe was formed by substances and accidents, so
they were those who argued that it was formed only by accidents or by substances. Furthermore, different
thinkers used the terms “substance,” “accident,” and “body,” in ways that carried different meanings. A
kalām scholar who argued that the universe was completely made up of accidents or substances alone could
have been a proponent of some type of atomism. At the same time, a scholar who held the opinion that the
universe was only comprised of substances might have subscribed to an anti-atomist viewpoint. In that
period, alongside those who defined indivisible particles that carried accidents as bodies, there were others
who, despite being atomists, gave space in their systems for concepts such as nature and causality.
Therefore, Imām al-Ashʿarī shows us that in the period of Imām al-Māturīdī, the mere use of the concept of
substance by a kalām scholar, or his contention that the universe was formed out of substances and
accidents, do not provide us with sufficient information to assert whether these scholars had accepted or
rejected atomism.
On the other hand, the explanations made by Imām al-Ashʿarī in the midst of this conceptual
confusion gives us certain indicators by which we may analyze which scholars were atomists and which
were not. According to al-Ashʿarī, atomists were generally united in defending the understanding that a
composite object or a body is formed through aggregation/composition of particles that are simple or finite
in terms of division or separation. In other words, atomists believed that observable phenomena did not
contain internal structures that were continuous, and that essentially individual particles formed as
composites through the accident of aggregation/composition (taʾlīf). What separated Islamic atomists from
non-Muslim atomists was that the former defended the idea that indivisibility was impossible not just in
actuality but also impossible in theory based on the premise that an atom was dimensionless like a point.
This understanding leads the Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn to describe atoms as having no sides (al-jihāt), ends
(al-nihāyāt), or dimensions (al-abʿād), and bodies as three-dimensional (al-abʿād al-thalātha) and having
directions and ends.

2. The Concepts of Body, Substance and Accident in the Thought System of al-Māturīdī

As it is known, Imām al-Māturīdī lived in the Transoxiana area within the 3rd/9th and 4th/10th
centuries. Most of his works are not extant today as it is the case with the other mutakallimūn from his times;
however, while maqālāt, firāq and tabaqāt books recount numerous views about Muʿtazilite and Ashʿarite
mutakallimūn, they have fallen unusually silent concerning Imām al-Māturīdī. Sources we can refer to gather
information about his ideas consist of a couple of extant manuscripts of himself and the views which are
ascribed to him by his successors, primarily by Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī (d. 508/1114).50

50
Regarding Imām Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī’s theological opinions, see. Bekir Topaloğlu, “Mâtürîdî”, Türkiye Diyanet Vakfı İslâm
Ansiklopedisi (Ankara: TDV Publications, 2003) 28/151-157.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


238 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Imām al-Māturīdī’s most important surviving work in which we can find detailed information about
his theological views is Kitāb al-Tawḥīd.51 His main aim in this book is not primarily to do research on the
nature of physical objects and their properties in the same way that a physicist or philosopher does; instead,
it is to demonstrate and defend the basic principles of Islamic revelation, particularly the principle of
monotheism, i.e., tawḥīd.52 In this sense, the cosmological matters he alluded in to this book are more of a
part of “natural theology”, which can be described as proving God’s existence by reason. Thus, contrary to
the Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn such as Abu’l-Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf, Muʿammar and al-Naẓẓām, whose opinions
Imām al-Ashʿarī mentioned above under the daqīq al-kalām-heading, and who meticulously discussed
together such concepts as body, substance, accident and furthered their interests in this field up to the level
of a physicist; Imām al-Māturīdī did not engage in physical theories unless they were related to theological
issues.
That Imām al-Māturīdī’s interest in the physical and cosmological matters had a religious purpose
is not just a general conclusion we have reached using his surviving works. Conversely, he himself demands
from mutakallimūn to avoid participating in detailed debates on these kinds of scientific issues beyond the
need. Indeed, he criticizes al-Naẓẓām, who argues with Sumaniyya about the constituent properties of living
beings in detail:
These are all pointless expressions. What can be said about this subject is that those objects have been created
as they are and been given their present natures (ṭabāʿi): Some substances (jawāhir) fly, some float in the water,
and still others walk on the earth. Trying to find a cause for all these issues would mean an attempt to
overpower God of the universe and probing into the matters that are not permitted and lie outside human
conception. These issues are not among the ones that the religion is responsible for their explanation, as is
with the investigating of material objects (taḥqīq al-aʿyān).53

In the text above, it is remarkable that Imām al-Māturīdī indicates that the detailed investigation
(taḥqīq) regarding the material objects or bodies (aʿyān) do not have a direct relation to religion and
maintains that humans cannot ultimately grasp the very essence of such matters. Imām al-Māturīdī also
seems to have a similar approach in his book, Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, on the Qurʾanic exegesis. While he is
interpreting the verse 24/25, “God created every moving (living) being from water,” he draws attention to
the fact that humankind is not capable of knowing the true nature of the things. Thus, according to him, it
will be a more accurate approach to account for the generation and evolvement observed in nature directly
by God’s power, knowledge, wisdom and governance rather than explaining them through natures and
causes.54

51
The references will be made in this study to Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, are based on the Arabic publication made by late Bekir Topaloğlu
and Muhammed Aruçi (Ankara: TDV Publication 2017) and the Turkish translation made by Bekir Topaloğlu (Ankara: TDV
Publication 2015). The first-page number belongs to the Arabic publication, and the second one refers to the Turkish translation.
52
For similar interperation, see Richard M. Frank, “Notes and Remarks on the tabā'i in the Teaching of al-Mâturidi”, in Melanges
D'islamologie. Ed. Pierre Salmon, (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1974), 139.
53
al-Māturīdī, Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 239 (242). From now on, the references made to this book will be referred as Tawhid without using
author’s name. The emphasis is added.
54
Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī, Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, ed. Halil İbrahim Kaçar and Bekir Topaloğlu (Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2007), 10/185

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 239

The Māturīdite scholars who followed Imām al-Māturīdī also had a similar stance. Abu’l-Muʿīn al-
Nasafī, a famous Māturīdite scholar, explains the fact that Imām al-Māturīdī did not participate in
exhaustive debates about the meaning of “body” (jism) as follows:

The reason for this is that he (al-Māturīdī) does not want to engage in describing the true nature of anything
(ḥaqīqa shayʾ) unless it is necessary for the matters concerning his religion (ʿalā ḥājati fī amri dīnihi). (…) As for
al-Ashʿarī, he made an effort to examine it. He was certainly convinced that a [body] could not be a name for
a thing connected via three sides; length, width and depth.55

As it can be seen, al-Nasafī says that Imām al-Māturīdī did not engage in describing the true nature
of body because this was not essential in terms of religion. According to al-Nasafī, mutakallimūn should avoid
dealing with them in great depth. This is because, he criticizes Imām al-Ashʿarī who took part in serious
discussions about the body refusing to define it as three dimensional.

Concerning the issue of accidents, al-Nasafī states that Imām al-Māturīdī avoided expressing a
strong opinion about the true nature of accidents by saying "it is more secure to keep quiet in this matter
because we do not have any information indicating that not knowing this issue means repudiating a
religious obligation."56 Right after this, al-Nasafī generalizes about al-Māturīdī’s approach above to other
notable scholars of the sect and says: "It is one of the renowned views of our companions (aṣḥābinā) that
they did not try to understand the true nature of things (ḥaqāʾiq al-ashyāʾ) that were not essential in order
to be able to confirm the principles of religion (uṣūl al-dīn)."57 According to al-Nasafī, what is essential about
the matter of accidents is nothing more than proving that they originated in time and substances, which
are parts of the universe, cannot be exempt from originated accidents; and thereby furnishing evidence for
the creation of the universe altogether out of nothing. There is no need to know whether the elements that
which exist themselves, among the ones constituting the universe, are related to the accidents, of which
bodies cannot be devoid, or any other things apart from the accidents.58
The stand of Imām al-Māturīdī and Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī that their interest in some concepts related
to the matter such as body and accident had to be related to the religion is supported, by thinkers such as
al-Fārābī (d. 339/950) who claimed that mutakallimūn dealt with physical and cosmological issues as much
as what revelation mainly considers about it, but not just to seek for the truth.59 Imām al-Māturīdī and al-
Nasafī’s approaches contradict some viewpoints that the science of kalām corresponds to the universal
science or metaphysics within the domain of which the existence qua existence is examined.60 However, we
immediately express that the condition of “being required in terms of religion” (ʿalā ḥājati fī amri dīn) is an
ambiguous statement, i.e., to what extent the religion will need this type of issues is vary from person to

55
Abu’l-Mu’īn al-Nasafī, Tabṣira al-adilla fī uṣūl al-dīn ed. Hüseyin Atay (Ankara: Diyanet İşleri Başkanlığı Publication, 2004), 1/66
From now on, in the references, this book will be called as Tabṣira al-adilla without mentioning the author.
56
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/72.
57
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/72.
58
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/72.
59
On this issue see. Abū Naṣr al-Fārābī, Iḥṣāʾ al-ʿulūm, ed. 'Uthman Amin (Cairo: Dār al-fikr al-ʿarabī, 1949), 107; also see. Galip
Türcan, “Klasik Kelâm’ın Apolojetik Değeri”, Turkish Journal of Islamic Studies, 17/4 (2004)/324-336; Peter Adamson, Philosophy in
the Islamic World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), 75.
60
On this issue see. Ömer Türker, “Kelâm İlminin Metafizikleşme Süreci”, Dîvân: Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies, 12/23 (2007/2),
75-92.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


240 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

person. al-Nasafī’s criticism of Imām al-Ashʿarī that “whether a body has dimensions or not is not linked to
religion” can be used by a traditionalist or Ahl al-Ḥadīth against al-Nasafī by saying “engaging in such issues
as substance and accident is unrelated to the religion”. Moreover, a philosopher, who examines the
existence qua existence, may not be skeptical about to what extent what he does is significant and beneficial
for the religion. Indeed, according to al-Kindī (d. 252/866 [?]), the first Islamic philosopher, a prophet and a
philosopher who is a seeker of truth are on the same road.61

Furthermore, the statement “being required in terms of religion” might make up the reason why a
person extremely absorbed in philosophical and cosmological issues. For instance, al-Qāḍī ʿAbd al-Jabbār (d.
415/1025), one of the well-known scholars of the Baṣra Muʿtazilite, phrases the motive for Muʿtazilite
scholars’ immense absorption in “subtle” (daqīq) subjects as follows:
Principles [regarding monotheism (tawḥīd)] can only be completed by subsidiary issues. This is the reason why
members of our sect discuss on subtle (daqīq) matters. For the explanation of the principle is provided solely
to amend the proof, answer questions and clear up doubts. And this contains speaking about establishing
proofs for the existence of God, and the creation of bodies and others. Plenty of issues that are not counted
among the subtle (daqīq) ones also fall under this. For example, if someone deduces the eternity of the universe
from the infinity of numbers, invalidating this reasoning only happens using “atom” (juzʾ). When you need to
establish the existence of the Creator, the situation is the same. Concerning this issue, you should be able to
confront and debate with Zakariyyā al-Rāzī [d. 313/925], who claims that God is incapable of creating the
essence of the matter. Similarly, you should be able to discuss with him about the time and place issues, which
he regards them as eternal.62

As it can be noticed, al-Qāḍī ʿAbd al-Jabbār asserts that mutakallimūn must be as expert as a natural
philosopher like Zakariyyā al-Rāzī in such subjects as space, time and matter to be able to ground and defend
the principle of monotheism.

Therefore, "being required in terms of religion" is an open-ended expression, and does not imply
that Imām al-Māturīdī did not take into consideration such issues as body, substance and accident at all and
did not express an opinion concerning these issues.63 As a matter of fact, the Kitāb al-Tawhīd has the
characteristics of a work that is very well provided with especially cosmological arguments. I think that
there are two significant reasons why Kitāb al-Tawhīd includes cosmological arguments even though Imām
al-Māturīdī maintains that religion does not directly necessitate to deal with issues concerning matter and
its properties.

61
al-Kindī, “Fī al-Falsafah al-Ūlā (İlk Felsefe Üzerine),” in Felsefî Risâleler ed. and transl. Mahmut Kaya (Istanbul: Klasik Publication,
2013). 129.
62
al-Qāḍī ʿAbd al-Jabbār, Kitāb al-Majmūʿ fi al-Muḥīṭ bi al-taklīf, ed. J. J. Houben (Beirut: Dār al-Mashriq, 1986), 26-27.
63
It is also possible to interpret the adaptation of this type of opinion by al-Māturīdī as an attempt to reset the science of kalām,
which has been going through a crisis by turning into a speculative investigation of the nature or the being and has been inclined
to turning into a natural philosophy or metaphysics, into the axis of Islamic revelation. In this context, the expression “required
in terms of religion” distinguishes kalām from philosophy, with which it shares such matters as knowledge, being and the
universe, or from science as the ultimate goal and demands from kalām scholars to utilize their energy in an appropriate way.
Therefore, the expression “required in terms of religion” does not mean that mutakallimūn should not engage in cosmological
and philosophical matters at all. Neither does it prevent mutakallimūn, including al-Māturīdī himself, from involving in
cosmological and philosophical issues when it is necessary for the sake of defending the religion by expanding the limits.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 241

The first one is based on the epistemology that Imām al-Māturīdī adopted. Even though he has a
flexible attitude towards the issues regarding physical theories, he establishes his overall system over
stringent epistemological principles and in this sense includes himself within the general kalām trend about
such subjects as the sources and types of knowledge. Again al-Māturīdī accepts the principles of the
mutakallimūn of that era that “the existence of God is known by acquired (iktisābī) knowledge based on
reasoning and deduction, not given by empirical or self-evident (iḍṭirārī) knowledge ”.64 This situation led
al-Māturīdī to engage in cosmological arguments to prove such theological issues as the existence and the
oneness of God and His attributes by using inference and reasoning (al-ijtihād wa al-istidlāl). According to
Imām al-Māturīdī, all the beings in the universe, with their qualities, point out to the fact that they are
originated in time and are creations of a Mighty Creator. Such that the universe alone would be enough to
prove the existence of a creator even if there had been no prophets providing evidence for the existence of
God.65
Another reason Imām al-Māturīdī did not participate in cosmological debates is the way of the
theological discussions at that time. If we look back on Imām al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt, the Muʿtazilite scholars
were engrossed in philosophical and scientific subjects and examined religious issues by connecting them
with physical and cosmological matters. Moreover, some groups such as Dualists (Sanawiyya), Materialists
(Dahriyya) and Naturalists (Tabīʿiyya), which were immensely active within the Muslim society at that time,
defended their ideas based on some cosmological theories. This situation inevitably compelled Imām al-
Māturīdī, to use common language in order to engage with his opponents in matters regarding body,
substance and accident leading him to have a stance towards these subjects.
After these introductory remarks, if we pay closer attention to how Imām al-Māturīdī explains such
concepts as body, substance and accident, we notice that he does not treat the subjects concerning the
elements of the universe under a separate chapter in his book because he refers to this type of issues in
theological contexts. A researcher, who aims to reveal al-Māturīdī’s opinions on body, substance and
accident, must assemble the pieces of information scattered over different theological subjects in his works.

One of the issues Imām al-Māturīdī’s addressed about the subject matter of “body” (jism) by asking
whether Allah can be referred to as a body. If we recall Imām al-Ashʿarī’s reports in Maqālāt, Hishām b. al-
Ḥakam defined a body as "existent" and accordingly claimed that Allah could also be called "body" because
He is existent. Again, some groups in Islamic thought, for example the Mujassima and Mushabbiha (the
proponents of corporealism/anthropomorphism) considered Allah to be a body.66
Imām Māturīdī, however, in this chapter, states that the word “body” (jism) can be used in two ways.
The first is about the nature of the body in the seen world (al-shāid). According to this, a body “is the name
of a thing that possesses the characteristics of having sides (al-jihāt) or ends (al-nihāyāt), or three dimensions
(al-abʿād al-thalātha)”.67 In the opinion of Imām al-Māturīdī, the word “body” cannot be used with reference

64
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 331, 390 (356, 434).
65
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 251 (257).
66
Regarding the controversies on this issue see. Al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 1/257.
67
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 119 (90).

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


242 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

to Allah, for its meaning implied “parts” (al-ajzaʾ) and “ends or extreme parts (al-ḥudūd)”. These qualities
refer to the signs of being temporal (al-ḥadath).68
Secondly, Imām al-Māturīdī does not approve of defining the body as “existent” (mawjūd). If that
was the case, according to him, everything would have had to be named a body. However, it is widely
accepted that in the universe apart from existing bodies there are also existing attributes (al-ṣifāt) and
accidents (al-aʿrāḍ) such as color, taste and the like that cannot be considered a body.69

These explanations of al-Māturīdī provide us with some clues about the theory of matter he adopted.
He speaks of the body as being three-dimensional. Defining body in this manner differentiates him from the
definition adopted by subsequent Ashʿarite and Māturīdite scholars. By mainly focusing on the aspects of
composition and combination of parts, they claimed that the composition two parts alone are enough to call
something a “body”. This way they opposed definitions that regard bodies as three dimensional, which were
made by philosophers (falāsifa) and the Muʿtazilite scholars.70
What Imām al-Māturīdī draws attention here to such characteristics of the body as "possessing
sides/directions (al-jihāt)”, "ends (al-nihāyāt)" and "dimensions" (al-abʿād) immediately calls to mind the
atomist mutakallimūn who maintained that while an indivisible part alone does not have sides, ends or
dimensions, bodies possess three dimensions (al-abʿād al-thalātha), ends and sides. However, this will not be
sufficient to make the assertion that al-Māturīdī provided an atomist definition of body in the way that the
Muʿtazilite school intended yet. This is because peripatetic philosophers, who adopted a concept of body
within the axis of prime matter-form theory (Hylomorphism), also accepted that a body has dimensions,
ends and sides and that it can be divided continuously. The distinction between them is that the body, in
the mind of mutakallimūn, is a composite made up of dimensionless parts that do not allow for divisions at
all (neither in actuality nor in potentiality); whereas, in the opinion of supporters of the hylomorphic prime
matter theory, a single body is continuous (muttaṣil) in terms of its structure and not formed through
combination of discrete parts. In other words, according to the hylomorphic theory, since the formation of
dimensional bodies out of dimensionless parts is absurd, the body does not cease to have dimensions and
sides after a certain point in the process of division, contrary to what mutakallimūn believe. Three-
dimensional bodies emerge out of each division of dimensional bodies again just like themselves. That the
elements appearing after each division are three-dimensional body as is with the previous one's results in
potentially endless divisions.71 Therefore, al-Māturīdī’s statement that the body has limits and sides and that
it is three-dimensional still does not give a clear idea in favor of or against atomism. For a clear-cut definition
of body, we need a description of the body that states that a ‘body forms when two or more parts are
aggregated’. This description emphasizes the "composite" (muallaf), compound (murakkab) and discrete
(munfaṣil) aspects, and also signifies the components forming these composites as “simple” (basīṭ) or
“indivisible”.

68
According to al-Māturīdī, if Allah called body without the aforesaid senses being meant, in this case the word becomes removed
from its known-status and it becomes impossible to come into an agreement about the issue through intellect and reasoning.
See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 119/90.
69
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 120 (91).
70
On this issue see. Bulğen, Kelâm Atomculuğu, 178.
71
On this issue see. Ibn Sīnā. Kitāb al-shifāʾ: Fizik II, trans. Muhittin Macit, Ferruh Özpilavcı (İstanbul: Litera Yayıncılık 2005), 12-13.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 243

However, soon enough, Imām al-Māturīdī provides us with the very definition we have been
seeking. While giving reasons for why God cannot be called “body”, at the next page, he uses the word
“composite” (muallaf) for the body:
In the sensible realm (al-shāid), the term body is not used for the things that do not possess the quality of being
divided (al-tabaʿūḍ) and separated (al-tajazziʾ) into parts such as accident (ʿaraḍ), action (al-fiʿl), motion (al-
ḥaraka) and rest (al-sukūn). Thus, it is established that "body" is the name of that which has dimensions such
as length (al-tūl) and width (al-‘arḍ) and that which is composite (al-muallaf). Even if compositeness were
assumed about Allah, the apparent meaning of the term composite (al-muallaf), which is supposedly attributed
to Him, still would not make sense to any action in Him. If our judgment were false, then speaking of a being
that has existed by its essence in eternity (mawjūd bi-dhātihi fī al-azal)) would also be untrue [because a
composite cannot be eternal and existent by itself].72

al-Māturīdī’s expressions mentioned above have great importance in terms of our topic. Because
here, he not only indicates that accidents are not bodies but also maintains that anything that does not carry
the characteristic of division (al-tajazziaʾ) cannot be named a body (jism). Saying that indivisible things in
the sensible world cannot be referred to as body brings him closer to the atomist mutakallimūn who assert
that an indivisible part cannot be a body. Moreover, Imām al-Māturīdī’s explicit use of the word “compound”
(al-muallaf) for body distinguishes him from the defenders of the hylomorphic definition of body, which
claims that the body is contiguous (muttaṣil) in itself, i.e., it does not actually carry discrete parts that are
apparently not bodies in themselves. Therefore, al-Māturīdī’s statement that a “body is the name for that
which has parts such as length and width and that which is composite.” were most probably made within
the context of traditional kalām atomism.73
Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī’s ascription of a definition of body including elements of mathematics to some
early Māturīdites and Muʿtazilite scholars is telling us that Imām al-Māturīdī’s description of the body might
have been shaped by kalām atomism:
As for the body, according to mathematicians (al-ḥissāb), it is that which has three dimensions (al-abʿād al-
thalātha). By three dimensions, they mean length, width and depth. They name the singular substance (al-
jawhar al-wāḥid) that cannot be divided in actuality (alladhī lā yatajazzaʾ fiʿlan), a “point (nuqta)”. They say that
if a substance (jawhar) aggregates (tarakkaba) another one similar to it, a length will occur which they call a
“line”. They define the line as that which is adjoined (al-mujtami) in terms of length. Then, if it [accepts a]
compound from the other side it is called surface. They say that the surface is that which has length and width.
Afterwards, if it accepts another compound [surface] from the bottom or top side, it will have a depth and
thickness, and is now called a body. Our early companions (awāilu aṣhābuna) and Muʿtazilites as a whole (bi
ʾasrihim) supported their view on this topic and asserted that the body is that which possesses length, width
and depth.74

It is quite remarkable that here al-Nasafī thinks of the indivisible part in connection with the
concept of a point in the mathematical discourse just as the Muʿtazilite scholars did. He also points out that

72
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 120 (92).
73
Imām al-Māturīdī ’s use of the term “compound objects” (al-a’yān al-murakkaba) for bodies (al-ajsām) and the term “simple” (al-
baṣīṭ) for the qualities and accidents (al-ṣifat wa al-aʿrāḍ), also see. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 177 (161).
74
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/66.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


244 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

the smallest body is formed by the composition of eight atoms.75 Moreover, he also states that “the early
members of our school and the entirety of the Muʿtazilites supported mathematicians regarding this issue”
and described the body as something that has length, width and depth. This opinion of al-Nasafī is totally in
agreement with the definition of a body by some atomist Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn including Muʿammar
reported by al-Ashʿarī in his Maqālāt.76 That being so, does the expression “our early companions (awāilu
aṣhābuna)” include Imām al-Māturīdī?

If the following explanations of al-Nasafī are taken into consideration, it is likely that Imām al-
Māturīdī is subsumed under the expression “our early companions”. According to al-Nasafī, al-Māturīdī
provided this definition in a manner of someone confident in not revealing deficiency and weakness while
confronting his opponent at the moment of debate and discussion, and who addresses his adversary gently
while expressing himself, but not like a hostile person. Subsequently, he said, “If in the sensible world, the
body is the name of which that has sides (al-jihāt), or that is has ends (al-nihāyāt), or that has three-
dimensions (al-abʿād al-thalātha), it is not permissible to use this utterance for Allah.”77
The definition of body that al-Nasafī ascribes to Imām al-Māturīdī corresponds to the definition of
body that we cited from Kitāb al-Tawhīd, and gives us an idea about the context in which Imām al-Māturīdī
made this kind of description for the body. Therefore, in the background of al-Māturīdī’s explanation of the
body in this way is the atomist Muʿtazilite scholars are also seen. This can also be sensed through the
discomposure of al-Nasafī in between the lines about the fact that al-Māturīdī adopted a Muʿtazilite
definition of body. Classical Ahl al-Sunnah mutakallimūn including al-Nasafī himself opposed the definition of
the three-dimensional body having at least for atoms provided by most of the Muʿtazilite instead, they put
the emphasis on the meanings of being compound (murakkab) or composite (muallaf) and claimed that the
combination of only two atoms is enough to call something “body.”78
Later, al-Nasafī tries to reconcile Imām al-Māturīdī 's opinion with the prevalent opinion of the of
Ahl al-Sunna. Following this, in the first place, he draws attention to the fact that Imām al-Māturīdī
mentioned the word “composition” (taʾlīf) while describing the body. On the other hand, al-Nasafī bases the
fact that Imām al-Māturīdī did not define the body as “the name of that which is composite” but as
something three-dimensional on Māturīdī's reluctance to give an opinion about the issues unrelated to the
religion. According to al-Nasafī, Imām al-Māturīdī probably believed that regarding the impossibility of
using the word “body” for Allah, there is no difference between its being a name for an absolute composition
(which is formed by only two parts) and for a specific composition out of which three dimensions emerge
(and which requires more parts for this).79

75
Associating the indivisible part with the concept of point of mathematics is not a characteristic that belongs to Muʿtazilite,
rather it is also common among the Ashʿarīte mutakallimūn. For example, Imāmu’l-Ḥaramayn al-Juwaynī describes the indivisible
part as follows: “There is a consensus among Muslims that bodies can be divided until the last part. No indivisible part has an
end (ḥad), side (ṭaraf) and part (juzʾ) to be separated. Masters of geometry adopted this opinion, defined the part in question as
“point” (al-nuqṭa), and asserted the indivisibility of it.” al-Juwaynī, al-Shāmil fī uṣūl al-dīn, 143.
76
al-Ashʿarī, Maqālāt, 2/4-5;
77
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/66.
78
For example, on this issue see. Ibn Mattawayh, al-Tadhkirah, 1/9-10.
79
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/66.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 245

Even though Imām al-Māturīdī avoided voicing an opinion about the issues that religion does not
require, this does not indicate that he was at an equal distance to all definitions of body. In this regard he
said that the body is three-dimensional, and mentioned its dimensions such as length and width, and
expressed that it has sides and ends. Also, he emphasized the compositeness (murakkab) of the body,
accepted the existence of simple (baṣīṭ) elements that are not able to be separated into pieces and
maintained that these elements could not be called “body”.80 This strongly implies that Imām al-Māturīdī
adopted a concept of body close to the atomist mutakallimūn’ description of body, according to which the
composite bodies in the universe consist of a combination of simple or indivisible parts.

Moreover, that al-Māturīdī objected the definition of body as “existent” (mawjūd) by saying there
are other existent beings in the universe, which do not fall under the scope of the body such as accidents
and qualities, means that he did not approve of the monistic approaches, which claim that the universe
entirely is made up of only bodies (ajsām), accidents (aʿrāḍ) or substances (jawāhir). If we remember, Hishām
b. al-Ḥakam maintained that the universe as a whole consists of bodies, conversely, Ḍirār b. ʿAmr defended
that it comprises of accidents. al-Naẓẓām, on the other hand, believed that everything in the universe is but
substance with motion being the only accident. Therefore, it seems that Imām al-Māturīdī agrees with the
dualist thesis indicating that the universe is made up of substance/body (jawhar/jism or ʿayn) and accidents
(aʿrāḍ), not the monist views maintaining that the universe consists of mere accidents or substances. In
connection with this, he says the following:
The quiddity of the things (māiyya al-ashyāʾ) is two types: Material object (ʿayn) that is body (jism) and
quality/attribute (ṣifat) that is accident (ʿaraḍ). With this expression of us, it becomes necessary to negate the
quiddities of objects (māiyya al-ashyāʾ), which are nothing but bodies and that of qualities, which are nothing
but accidents from the essence of God.81

Imām al-Māturīdī, in his book Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, more clearly demonstrates the distinction between
substance and accidents. He comments on the 164th verse of Sūrah al-Baqarah (2), concerning the
administration of God over winds and clouds as follows:
In this part of the verse, there is an indication that wind (rīḥ) is not accident (ʿaraḍ) but a body (jism).
Because Allah has created the wind as a being that not only makes dizzy what is in its direction but also
a being that touches (māssa) and hinders (māniaʿ). This is, however, a quality of bodies (ṣifatu’l-ajsām),
not accidents (ṣifatu‘l-aʿrāḍ). Nonetheless, wind cannot be seen because of its transparency (latāfatihā).
This also proves that it is a body. There are some bodies that are neither seen nor touched, such as air
(al-hawāʾ). Air is a body that cannot be seen and touched. Also, there are particles (dharraʾ) of sun which
emits in a certain aspect, they can be seen but not touched.82

It is quite remarkable that al-Māturīdī points out that wind is a subtle/transparent body (jism laṭīf)
because accidents do not have the quality of touching and blocking. Also, his view that the existence of the
transparent/invisible bodies is possible brings him close to the views of some mutakallimūn such as Imām al-
Ashʿarī. This is because Imām al-Māturīdī regarded the human being as an apparent/visible body just as

80
See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 203 (195); 120 (92); 177 (161).
81
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 121 (93); Concerning al-Māturīdī ’s reduction of the universe into two categories, namely substance/body
(jawhar/jism/ʿayn) and accidents (aʿrāḍ), also see. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 200 (193); 209 (204); 236 (239); 227 (226).
82
Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī, Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, ed. Ahmed Vanlıoğlu and Bekir Topaloğlu (Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2005), 1/300-301.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


246 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Imām al-Ashʿarī did, and refused the ideas implying that humans substantially have a transparent spirit
beyond his visible body or that there is an immaterial/abstract substance associated with it.83 All these
opinions bring Imām al-Māturīdī close to the classical atomist perspective, which defends that the bodies in
the universe are constituted of indivisible substances and accidents.
When it comes to the subject of “substance” (jawhar), Imām al-Māturīdī uses this concept in an
ambiguous way; therefore, it does not play a decisive role for [having a clear idea about] the type of matter
theory he adopted.84 His use of the term “substance” sometimes as synonymous with the words “material
object” (ʿayn) and “body” (jism) indicates that he disagreed with some Muʿtazilite scholars such as Abu’l-
Hudhayl al-ʿAllāf, Muʿammar, and al-Jubbāʾī, who claimed that a “single substance” (al-jawhar al-wāḥid)
could not be a body. Having said that in some cases, the meaning al-Māturīdī assigned for the term
“substance” could be influenced by the description of the groups whose views he discussed. For example,
while he sometimes names some accidents or natures (ṭabāʿī) such as hot, cold, wet, and dry as “substance,”
he also calls some objects causing benefit or detriment, good or evil and even human itself “substance.”85
Furthermore, that he mentions the term “substance” (jawhar) generally together with the terms
“accident” and “attribute,”86 and reduces the universe as a whole to substances and accidents might be given
as examples of the cases where he brings such denotations of the word substance as “that which stands by

83
al-Māturīdī explains the first verse of the Sūrah al-Mumtaḥinah (60), in his Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān in the following manner: “O
humans, worship your God!” and the other verses in the same sense point out to the human we see (mā nushāhiduhu). It does not
mean that there is another subtle/transparent body (jismun āhara laṭīfun) in the human, as opposed to what al-Naẓẓām said. Here
this verse shows that human is not a simple substance (jawharun baṣīṭun), unlike al-Nāshī believed. Each of them thought that
this verse indicated that meaning. However, as we stated, human is nothing more than the being we perceive. Allah knows the
truest.” Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, 15/102. Ibn Fūrak (d. 406/1015) narrates from Imām al-Ashʿarī: “Know that he [al-Ashʿarī] said: “The
competent authority (marjiʿ) on this topic is that when we ask linguists ‘What is man?’” it is what they describe with the word
“man” and what they point out. When we answer this question, we find them pointing to this apparent/visible body, composite
(murakkab) with a special structure (al-bunya al-makhṣūṣa). This implies that linguists apply this naming (tasmiya) to this entire
composite (jumla).” Ibn Fūrak, Mujarrad Maqālāt al-Shaykh Abī al-Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī, ed. Daniel Gimert (Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq, 1987),
211. Ibn Fūrak, provides us with details about Imām al-Ashʿarī’s views on air/wind (rīḥ) and soul (rūḥ): if we take into account
what is conveyed by him, according to al-Ashʿarī, air is a subtle/transparent body (jism laṭīf) and becomes apparent when it
moves. Wind is the air, in which a special motion subsists. This is named as soul when it subsists in the limbs of human body in
a particular organic way. It is the air, which fills the skin, when blown into it. If air were an accident, it could not fill the skin in
such a way. Air sometimes becomes dense and its length, width and depth becomes apparent. When a stray of sunlight becomes
apparent upon its passage through a small whole, this is the thing that happens. Ibn Fūrak mentions Imām al-Ashʿarī’s statement
that “angels and jinn are subtler bodies than air”. According to al-Ashʿarī those subtle bodies are types of dense ones. The
indivisible particles, which aggregate in an intense manner, are called dense (kasīf). Bodies become dense when the number of
their particles increases, and they become subtle when the number of their particles decreases. See, Mujarrad, 207. Ibn Fûrek
also states as follows: According to [al-Ashʿarī], the soul (rūḥ) is wind/air (rīḥ), a subtle (laṭīf) object, and travels through the
spaces inside the human organs. But man is alive with life, not with spirit. In other words, when man is alive, he becomes the
place of the soul, or he is not alive with the soul. Can’t you see that ḥayy is derived from life (ḥayāt), and spiritual (rūḥānī) is
derived from spirit (rūḥ). al-Ashʿarī brought evidence with the phrase “the spirit came out” to the truth of his view [that the
spirit was air/wind].” Exiting/coming out is one of the attributes of body and substance (jawhar), because going out means
moving from one place to another. (...) [al-Ashʿarī’s] judgment of the soul was like his judgment of the wind/air (rīḥ), and even
the soul (rūḥ) itself (bi-ʿaynihā) meant wind/air.” See, Ibn Fūrak, Mujarrad, 257;
84
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 94 (59); 143 (120).
85
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 84 (47); 190 (180); 245 (249); 251 (255); 253 (259); 227 (226).
86
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 236 (239); 209 (204).

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 247

itself, and bearer of accidents” into focus.87 Most of the time, he bonds substances and accidents together.
According to him, the substances in the universe, regardless of whether they are material objects (ʿayān) or
bodies (ajsām), cannot be devoid of such accidents as motion, rest, composition and separation.88 As can be
seen from the following statements, al-Māturīdī’s attempt to reduce everything in the cosmos including
natures (ṭabāʿī) into substances and accidents brings him closer to the prevalent universe model that is
supported by Ashʿarites and Māturīdīs in the classical sense:
The natures (al-ṭabāʿī) that materialists (Dahriyya) refers to, such as air and fire, cannot be other than
substances (jawāhir) or accidents (aʿrāḍ). If they are substances, they exist together with accidents while being
in the state of composition (al-ijtimāʿ) and separation (al-iftirāq). If it were not for these two states, each one of
their substance would be scattered all over (mutafarriq). Despite the fact that qualities pertaining to matter
come together in substances, that they exist in different states (e.g. being combined with other substances or
separated from them) shows that substances fall under the control of accidents (ʿalā ghalabati l-aʿrāḍi fīha) and
that they are transformed from one state to another by accidents. It must also be added that accidents do not
stand (lā taqūmu) by themselves and affect (lā taqdaḥu) things (al-ashyāʾ). Thus, it becomes apparent that it is
only possible due to a Being who knows the role accidents play on substances and their various functions.
Additionally, it also emerges that only a Being who has the power to create and organize substances in a
manner that they are susceptible to carry accidents (yaṣluḥu li iḥtimali tilke l-aʿrāḍ) can know such a thing. By
all means, such knowledge is impossible except for someone who makes the previously described
arrangement. Such an inference also leads the conclusion that there is only one Being who is omniscient and
omnipotent, to whom nothing remains hidden, and who does not encounter any difficulty in creating
anything He wishes to exist. If natures (al-ṭabāʿī) that constitute objects are nothing more than accidents, it is
impossible for them to attain existence by themselves and maintain it (muḥālun wujūduha li anfusiha wa
qiyāmuha). Therefore, it is inevitable to conclude that there is an Eternal Creator (mūjid qadīm), that everything
in the universe is created by Him, and that the world only comes into existence by His creative act. We must
also say further that there is not an opposing view about the temporal origination of the accidents (ḥadathu l-
aʿrāḍ). Allah is the Almighty and the Omnipotent.89

This fragment we have excerpted from Imām al-Māturīdī is quite remarkable. First of all, even
though al-Māturīdī appears to give a place to natures in his thought system, he interprets these in a different
manner from the proponents of natures (aṣḥāb al-ṭabāʿī). According to al-Māturīdī, if there are natures as
Dahriyya claims, they do not imply the nonexistence of a creator. In the opinion of al-Māturīdī, that natures
come together although they are contrary to each other and that they form extremely complicated and
various bodies even though they are limited in number demonstrate that everything in the universe is
created by a God who has the power to arrange everything as He wishes without depending on causes (min

87
For the expression “there is no universe (al-ʿālam) except the one that consists of accidents and substances” (wa lā ʿālama bi dūni
wujūdi hadhayni al-nawʿayni min al-aʿrāḍ wa al-jawāhir), see. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 171 (155). “Because when it is established that God the
Almighty has different creations having different attributes (ṣifāt) along with their substance[s] (jawhar), it becomes proven that
His act is not by natures (al-ṭabāʿi) but voluntary (al-ikhtiyār).” Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 125 (97). “In this case, divine providence fulfills
such functions as creating other substances (al-jawāhir) and accidents (al-aʿrāḍ), and determine the time and places in which the
actions are going to take place.” Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 412 (464). “Moreover, there is no material object (ʿayn) or attribute (ṣifāt) in the
universe (al-ʿālam) that is not put under command and overpowered.” Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 143 (120).
88 Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 95 (60), 329 (352).
89
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 227 (226).

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


248 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

ghayri asbāb).90 Thus, here, al-Māturīdī does not absolutely assert that the cosmos is made up of natures
ontologically; instead he tries to show that naturalists’ claim that the universe is formed of natures does not
mean denial of a creator but rather can be used as evidence of the temporal creation of the world.91

Another striking aspect of the text we quoted above is al-Māturīdī’s attempt to explain natures by
reducing them into the terms “substance” and “accident”. This points out to the fact that, according to al-
Māturīdī, the terms substance and accident are two fundamental principles depending on which everything
in the cosmos must be explicated. Therefore, natures (al-ṭabāʿī) must be interpreted in accordance with the
rules required by the higher ontological principles, which are substance and accident. Consequently, one
who wants to understand al-Māturīdī’s view on the matter needs to focus on how he perceived the terms
substance and accident, rather than the term nature.

As for the issue of accidents, among the concepts we have examined so far, his ideas on the accidents
undoubtedly played the most prominent role within the thought system of al-Māturīdī. In fact, as we
mentioned above, that which establishes the existence of substance and turn it into a key concept are again
accidents. In our opinion, there are two reasons why he might have attached this much importance to the
concept of accident.
The first is of a theological nature. As is known, accidents constitute the backbone of the classical
kalām cosmological argument regarding the temporal creation (ḥudūth) of the universe. Imām al-Māturīdī
establishes the createdness of the world through accidents as follows:
The universe (al-ʿālam) is not far away from these alternatives: It is either eternal together with the qualities
it has, such as composition-separation, motion-rest, dirty-clean, good-evil, and excessive-deficient. Yet
characteristics described above are temporally originated (ḥawādith) based on the proofs both senses and the
intellect provide. Because contraries cannot come together [at once], so they must occur successively [in a
manner that one of them perishes and then the other one comes into existence], and this is a justification for

90
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 227 (226). In the same page, al-Māturīdī continues to say regarding natures (al-ṭabāʿī) as follows: “As is known,
the natures (that were assumed to constitute the universe) are contrary (mutaḍāddatun) to each other. Being contrary implies
to reject and push each other. In this state, however, separation is an unavoidable consequence, and so are decomposition and
annihilation in the state of separation. In spite of the contradiction which I described earlier, it is improbable for the
origins/roots of the things (ʾaṣūl l-ashyāʾ) to exist (kāina) on their own and stand (qāima) their existence. Accordingly, if prime-
matter attains existence, it does so thanks to a Being who prevents the state of pushing by which decomposition occurs. This
Being combines decomposed parts of matter and subjugates them. The universe has been formed through this combination, so
its temporal origination (ḥudūth) has become established. This corroboration also shows the falsity of the view that the universe
is constituted by natures (fasād al-qawl al-ṭabāʿī). This is because, the origination of something out of nothing (lā ʿan shayʾ), in the
intellects (fī al-uʿqūl), is not more unlikely than the origination of it by its contrary. Since the creation of the cosmos ex nihilo, in
the opinion of the naturalists, is improbable, they embraced an alternative view. Considering that the trouble they avoid
encountering reappears in front of them within the view they offered, their claim becomes nullified, and the situation that is
supposed to justify themselves disappears. Protection from error is only possible with God’s help.” See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 226-227
(226), These statements of al-Māturīdī shows that he does not accept a nature idea that is the source of the motion by itself and
that is the governor of the universe in the same way that the proponents of natures (aṣḥāb al-ṭabāʿī) believe. Also see. al-Māturīdī,
Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, 10/185.
91
al-Māturīdī's approach to the theory of hylomorphism is similar with his approach to natures. Instead of directly rejecting the
theory, he tries to interpret it in accordance with the temporal creation of the universe (ḥadathu’l-ʿālam). In this direction, he
explains the theory by reducing substance and accident concepts and rejects the eternality of prime mater (al-hayūla/al-ṭiyna)
and form (sūra). Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 231-235 (232-237), 143-144 (121-122).

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 249

being temporal (al-ḥadath). All temporal things are under the category of coming-to-be (al-kawn) while they
were once non-existent. The objects that cannot be exempt from these [temporal accidents] and that cannot
precede them are in the same position.92

If we elaborate on the expressions mentioned above of al-Māturīdī, looking at the outside world, it
can be realized that the material object (body or substance) becomes moving when resting and vice versa.
This situation indicates that states such as motion and rest observed in the body are different from the
bodies themselves. This is because something is a body when it is in motion just as it is a body when rests. If
the body was inherently moving or at rest, these essential qualities could not to be exempt from the body
in any way. However, it is evident that bodies start moving when at rest and turn to rest when they move.
This means that when motion occurs in a body, the accident of rest disappears completely, and when the
accident of rest occurs in it, motion goes out of existence. Otherwise, two contrary qualities would come
together in a body, which is impossible. Thus, a body becomes then a substratum for the temporally
originated qualities, i.e. accidents, which occur and disappear on themselves. It is out of the question for
bodies to be devoid of these temporal and contrary qualities. In the universe there cannot be a single object
that is neither in the state of motion or rest nor composition or separation. This demonstrates that not a
single body or substance in the universe can be separated from temporally originated accidents.

Conversely, the accidents of coming-to-be (al-akwān) such as motion, rest, composition and
separation cannot exist in the extramental world unless there is a material object or substance to carry
them. For example, motion or a rest cannot stand by itself (qāʾim bi-nafsihī) alone in the universe without
being carried by a material object. This means that individual substances and accidents need each other to
exist. Here according to Imām al-Māturīdī, this substance-accident relation indicates the createdness of the
world in two ways: first, the fact that bodies cannot be devoid of temporally originated accidents, which
disappear and re-appear, requires that bodies themselves be temporally originated. Second, that the
material objects and the accidents in the universe cannot exist by themselves and need each other to exist
manifests the absurdity of the claim that they could come into existence by themselves.93

al-Māturīdī also produces some original arguments for beginning of the universe based on the
temporal nature of the accidents. He argues that the sensible accidents such as motion and aggregation are
the last of the past ones of that type. If the accidents continued towards the past eternally, a past without a
beginning should not have ended at the moment. Therefore, according to al-Māturīdī, the fact that contrary
accidents such as motion-rest, composition-separation, heat-coldness, consecutively disappear and
reappear shows that there must have a beginning for this reoccurring process in the past. Otherwise, if they
were eternal things, an eternal thing could not have ended in this way. This means that the material objects,
bodies or substances, which cannot be separated from accidents, also must have a beginning.94
The second reason that al-Māturīdī gives importance to the concept of the accident is
epistemological. As mentioned before, he asserts that human’s relation with the visible world must be
grounded on the empirical knowledge and in respect to God it must be based on acquired (muktasab)
knowledge. In other words, he accepts the general principle of the mutakallimūn that the knowledge of the

92
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 95 (60).
93
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 100 (66).
94
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 97 (62).

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


250 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

existence of God cannot be attained direct observations but through reasoning (istidlāl).95 Accordingly,
humans using the necessary knowledge about the universe, which they acquired through their senses, make
analogies from that which is perceptible to that which is imperceptible (qiyās al-ghāib ʿalā al-shāhid), so they
attain the knowledge of the existence of God.96 For knowledge through acquisition (kasb) [reasoning] to be
valid, it must be based on necessary (iḍṭirārī)) knowledge, which is regarded as empirical and a priori
knowledge. According to the mutakallimūn, the intellect can judge what is “necessary” (wājib) or
“impossible” (muḥāl); however, it cannot form a definite opinion about the universe, which is a “possible”
(mumkin/jaʾiz) realm of existence. Here, considering this epistemological framework, Imām al-Māturīdī
establishes an epistemological principle that “The world is known by observation (baṣar), not by [rational]
evidences (dalāʾil)”.97 This principle makes the accidents related to senses such as color, taste, smell, hearing
and touching of primary importance for perceiving the universe.
However, this kind of epistemological approach grounded on sensationalism towards the world
causes some problems concerning whether a category of existence in the sense of “standing by itself” (al-
qāʾim bi al-dhātihī), i.e., the substance, is included in the universe. For most of the time, mutakallimūn attain
the knowledge about the existence of a substance not by their senses but by reasoning based on the principle
that accidents cannot stand by themselves. This, however, contradicts the principle, Imām al-Māturīdī
established, that “the universe is known not by reasoning but via the senses”, and leads him to have a
sympathetic attitude towards the view that the universe consists entirely of accidents. Abu’l-Muʿīn al-
Nasafī also reports that, in his no longer existing work, named Maqālāt, Imām al-Māturīdī was in favor of the
idea, supported by Ḍirār b. ʿAmr and Ḥusayn al-Najjār, that the universe is entirely collection of accidents,
and he gives the reasons for this as follows:
The owners are of this opinion claim that speaking of the existence of something that does not consist of these
accidents described earlier and that stands by itself (qāim bi al-dhāt) is deviating from the results provided by
senses. For without the accidents we expressed before, nothing can be perceived by senses (lā idrāka li shayʾ
bi’l-hawās siwā hādhihi al-aʿrāḍ). He regarded this opinion as more preferable.98

As it is seen, al-Nasafī indicates that, in certain parts of his life, Imām al-Māturīdī sympathized with
the idea about the composition of the bodies in the universe from accidents depending on epistemological
reasons. However, later on, al-Nasafī does not forget to report that al-Māturīdī eventually distanced himself
from this view. He attributes the reason for this to the reluctance of Imām al-Māturīdī about giving an
opinion about an issue unrelated to the religion.99

95
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 331, 390 (356, 434); about the relation between reason and revelation, also see. Hülya Alper, İmam Mâtürîdî’de
Akıl-Vahiy İlişkisi (Istanbul: Iz Publication, 2009).
96
For example, while interpreting the verses of Sūra Yūnus (10) between 90-92, Imām al-Māturīdī explains the reasons why the
faith of Pharaoh, who said he believed in Allah near-drowning, was not counted as valid on the basis that belief in Allah should
be grounded on the method of deducing the invisible through the visible. However, it becomes impossible in the moment of
drowning or when the process of death starts, and a human begins to see the creatures (angels), which he does not see under
normal conditions according to principle of faith (bi al-qhayb). see. Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī, Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, ed. Ertuğrul Boynu
Kalın, Bekir Topaloğlu (Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2006) 5/105.
97
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 94 (59).
98
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/71.
99
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/71.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 251

These descriptions of al-Nasafī enables us to comprehend the meaning of al-Māturīdī’s expressions,


which we sometime come across in Kitāb al-Tawhīd, implying that the bodies in the universe are composed
of accidents.100 In one of these expressions, Imām al-Māturīdī justifies the idea that nothing in the world is
like Him based on the Qurʾānic verse (42/11) “There is nothing similar to Him”, and says the following:
“There is nothing similar to Him”; as a result of this expression the reification/thingness of things (shayʾiyya
al-ʾashyāʾ), that is to say, simple elements (al-arkān al-baṣīṭa) that are accidents (al-aʿrāḍ) and qualities (al-ṣifāt)
and compound objects (al-aʿyān al-murakkaba) that are bodies (al-ʾajsām) become excluded from the essence of
God.101

As it can be understood from his expressions mentioned above, Imām al-Māturīdī groups the things
in the universe into two categories: composite objects/bodies (al-aʿyān al-murakkaba) and simple elements
(al-arkān al-baṣīṭa) that are accidents and qualities. The fact that he makes a classification of this type implies
the belief al-Māturīdī holds that the composite bodies of the world consist of simple accidents, which are
non-divisible in any way.102
Nonetheless, concerning our issue, we have to state right away that even if Imām al-Māturīdī
accepted the idea that bodies are a bundle of accidents, it does not mean that he rejects atomism. This is
because we previously revealed while examining the Maqālāt of al-Ashʿarī that some scholars, “the
proponents of accidents” (aṣhāb al-aʿrāḍ) such as Ḍirār b. ʿAmr, who maintained that the composite bodies
in the universe are composed by accidents, also had an atomistic perspective. Furthermore, the reports of
Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī below support our opinion:
Ḍirār b. ʿAmr al-Basrī, leader of Ḍirāriyya, and Ḥusayn b. Muhammad al-Najjār al-Basrī, the leader of
Najjāriyya, denied the existence of any other thing in the universe, apart from accidents. They claimed that
the world is made up of bodies and accidents. Bodies, on the other hand, are accidents, which are aggregated
(mujtamiʿ) and carrying/accepting (iḥtamala) other accidents. According to them, bodies are formed by the
combination of such accidents as color, taste, smell, life, death, four natures and their contraries, of which
bodies cannot be devoid of. Those that a body can do without, such as knowledge, power, speech and others

100
For example, see. Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/65. While al-Māturīdī usually seems to differentiate between the body and its visible
qualities, he draws attention to the fact that whether these visible qualities are named accidents or qualities is a matter of
linguistics. He even underlines such Qur’anic verses as “You wish for the temporal goods of this world (aʿraḍ al-dunya).” (al-Anfāl
8/67). “If there was a property of the world (…) near-grabbing (aʿraḍ qharīb).” (al-Tawba 9/42), so that he indicates that things
(al-ashyāʾ) themselves in the universe can be called “accident”. See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 99 (65).
101
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 177 (161).
102 al-Māturīdī's statement here implies that he maintains the idea that the composite bodies are composed of simple or indivisible
accidents. But in my view, what he says that accidents are simple does not necessarily mean that he defends the view that
compound objects are composed of accidents. We should keep in mind that atomist mutakallimūn who defended that the bodies
consist of indivisible substances also defended the idea that accidents have simple/atomic structure as well. For instance,
Ashʿarite Mutakallim ʿAbd al-Qāhir al-Baghdādī (d. 1093/1682) addresses this issue as follows: “Individuals (al-mufradāt) in the
universe are of two types. One of them is the individual in its essence (mufrad fi dhātihī), such that it is impossible to divide (al-
inqisām) it any further. The second is the individual with its kind (jins), but not its essence. Individuals in their essence (mufrad
fi dhātihī) are two types: the first is the individual substance (jawhar fard), such that it is impossible to divide it any further; all
bodies in the universe, when they reach the point to which it is impossible to divide any further, cease to do so. The second type,
which is not divisible, is all accidents (aʿrāḍ) in themselves, due to the fact that [an accident] is an individual which necessitates
only one substratum (mahal wāḥid).” ʿAbd al-Qāhir al-Baghdādī, Uṣūl al-dīn, (Istanbul: Maṭbaʿat al-Dawla, 1928), 35. As it is seen,
al-Baghdādī states clearly that accidents are indivisible like substances.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


252 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

are not units of a body (ab’ad al-jism). According to them, the particles that are subject to division within a
body are also bodies on their own. Furthermore, when a particle reaches the inability to be divided further
neither in mind (bi’l-wahm) nor actuality (bi’l-fiʿil), after successive divisions, they claim that this particle is
also a body. This is what we described as the substance (a-jawhar) in accordance with the opinions of the
majority of mutakallimūn who believe in the indivisible part. [On the other hand] they called it body despite
that their indivisible part is not composed of (mutarakkib) self-subsistent parts [substance], but it is composed
of accidents (aʿrāḍ) as aforementioned. In this case, despite how firmly they claim that the indivisible part is
composed of accidents and the impossibility of a body being composed of [infinitely] divisible parts, along
with classifying the part that cannot be divided as a “body,” as, to them, it is composed of accidents they do
not hesitate to endorse and support the concept of the indivisibility. Pondering on the impossibility of the
composition (tarakkub) of accidents, and the inability of accident to carry/accept other accidents, along with
the unfeasibility of continuation (baqāʾ) on their own, it is easy to conclude that their view is fallacious.103

These explanations of al-Nasafī hold a great significance for our topic. Indeed, these statements
corroborate our understanding that someone who defends the idea that the bodies in universe is composed
of accidents can maintain an atomist perspective, as we also saw when examining the views of the
mutakallimūn concerning bodies in Imām al-Ashʿarī and al-Kaʿbī’s Maqālāt.104

On the other hand, Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī opposes the idea that the bodies are comprised of accidents
by stating that “that this view is absurd (istiḥāla) can be seen if it is considered that it is impossible for
accidents to carry or to accept other accidents, as it is also impossible also for accidents to perdure by
themselves.”105 This might give us an idea as to why despite having sympathy for the notion that the entire
universe is made of accidents, Imām al-Māturīdī did not accept this concept in the final analysis. Indeed,
also according to al-Māturīdī accidents cannot exist by themselves, cannot move from one location to
another, and cannot impact objects through contact. Also, according to him an accident does not endure or
last (lā yabqā’) for two units of time.106
This last view, that of accidents are not continuous or persistent, holds a very important role in al-
Māturīdī’s kalām system.107 In addition to basing his defense of the proof-from-creation on the discontinuity
of accidents, the discontinuity of accidents is also the basis for his arguments in defense of God’s creation of
the human acts and of the existence of miracles as well as his rejection of natural causality. This approach
brings al-Māturīdī close to the Ashʿarite scholars in terms of his adoption of an occasionalist doctrine
regarding the creation of the universe. 108

103
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/71-72.
104
Besides, al-Nasafī’s declamations implies a terminological difference between Imām al-Māturīdī and those who argue that the
universe is made completely through the combination of accidents. Indeed, Ḍirār and Najjār defend the notion that a body
composed of accidents remains a body even when it reaches a state where it can no longer be divided, whereas al-Māturīdī
defines accidents as “simple” and does not consider a thing that is composite (murakkab) or combined (muallaf) as a body.
105
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/71.
106
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 227 (226).
107
This claim distinguishes al-Māturīdī also from the kalām scholars who have asserted that the universe consists of accidents. If
we look back to al-Ashʿarī’s Maqālāt, they had claimed that some accidents are persistent. However, al-Māturīdī believes that
no accident is continuous without any exception.
108
Nazif Muhtaroğlu, “Al-Māturīdī ’s View of Causality” in Occasionalism Revisited: New Essays from the Islamic and Western Philosophical
Traditions, ed. Nazif Muhtaroglu. (Abu Dhabi: Kalam Research and Media, 2017), 3-21.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 253

al-Māturīdī explains the discontinuity of accidents on the basis of continuity (baqāʾ) itself an
accident. According to him, if an accident had a quality of permanence, then this would lead to the problem
of an accident carrying another accident. Therefore, as it is impossible for accidents such as motion,
composition, division, heat, coldness, power, etc., to exist or carry by each other, so it is impossible for them
to possess the accident of continuity.109
According to al-Māturīdī, even if accidents do not endure (lā yabqāʾ), bodies in the universe can still
carry the accident of continuity. However, the temporal origination (ḥudūth) of bodies in the universe; in
other words, for them to possess a first creation, means that continuity for them is not an essential quality
but an accidental quality acquired in time. Therefore, just because they were subject to being created at
some point in the past does not mean that they now have a quality of the accident of continuity that is an
essential quality and that they are therefore completely independent of God. Indeed, since the continuity is
also an accident, this situation would require this accident to be impermanent/discontinuous. al-Māturīdī
explains this situation in the following manner: “The creation of continuity (ḥudūth al-baqāʾ) in a body makes
that body persistent, and the continuity of the body (yadūmu baqāʾuhu) proceeds through the successive
occurrence of the [accidents of] continuity (tatābaʿu’l--baqāʾ) in it.”110 In this way the discontinuity of
accidents not only posits the necessity of the creation of the universe, but implies furthermore that the
accidents in the universe are continuously re-created and that in each moment everything are under the
complete power of God.
According to al-Māturīdī, the discontinuity of accidents leads to important conclusions in regard to
the relationship between God and the universe. Indeed, the discontinuity of accidents in two different
frames of time necessitates the disappearance of an accident the moment it is created
(tatajaddadu/taḥduthu).111 The multiplied continuity of similar kind accidents is related to God’s recreating
of them. al-Māturīdī states that he connects the continuous need that creatures have for God beyond the
first act of creation to this principle of the discontinuity of accidents.112 Therefore according to him, if the
arguments of some Muʿtazilites that accidents are perpetual and that the creation of God is limited only to
the first moment of creation were accepted, then what we would have an autonomous universe that
functions by itself according to certain laws of nature and mechanical causality. Besides, according to al-
Māturīdī, if accidents and bodies were able to exist by themselves, then they would also persist by
themselves without any outer factor acting on them. Moreover, this situation would also render the
temporal creation/origination argument (ḥudūth) debatable. This is because, the conclusion that the
universe is created ex nihilo is arrived by accepting of temporal origination of the accidents observable at
the present time. Their discontinuity/temporality consists in the disappearance of one accident and its
replacement by another in succession.113

109
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 96 (61); also see the controversy about whether the accident of power (qudra) precedes the act or vice versa.
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 361 (396).
110
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 97 (62).
111
See the issue of capacity (istiṭāʿa) regarding al-Māturīdī ’s claim that the accident of power (qudra) continuously re-occurs
(tatajaddadu) and comes into existence (taḥduthu). Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 356-359 (389-392).
112
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 383 (425).
113
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 93 (64).

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


254 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Imām al-Māturīdī also uses the argument of the discontinuity of accidents against the Muʿtazilite
scholars who defend the notion that humans create their own actions.114 In contrast to al-Ashʿarī’s thought,
al-Māturīdī argues in favor of granting humans the ability to act to a certain extent,115 but he also defends
the idea that God is the sole creator of the successively recreated accidents including motion, rest,
composition, separation, and power.116 If human acts, which can be considered continuously renewed
accidents, come out of non-existence, then the disappearance and once again recreation of them deemed to
be dependent on the formation of their agents, thus, some sort of “creation” attribute would be ascribed to
humans. 117 According to al-Māturīdī, if it were to be said that any kind of accident could belong to someone
other than God, then the creation and existence of the universe would become the possession of both God
and another agent. However, this view goes against the fundamental Muslim concept of oneness of the
Creator of the universe (tawḥīd). Muslims have not disagreed on the oneness of the Creator of the universe.118
According to al-Māturīdī, the fact that accidents such as power (qudra) and capacity (istiṭāʿa) are not
continuous proves that God is also the creator of human acts. In relation to this al-Māturīdī says the
following:
Given that power (quwwa) is not among the parts of the body, it is, in fact, an accident. Accidents are not
persistent (lā tabqā) because the continuity (baqāʾ) of something that possesses the quality of annihilation is
only possible through permanence outside of itself. An accident, however, cannot accept (yaqbulu) the others
because it cannot stand by itself. A thing cannot be persistent through permanence presents in another thing
(for example, in the body). Therefore, continuity of the power is out of the question.119

al-Māturīdī also accuses al-Kaʿbī, who on the one hand claims the discontinuity of the accidents,
and on the other hand maintains that humans create their action on their own, of being inconsistent.120 al-
Māturīdī criticizes some Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn who on the one hand maintain that the power (al-qudra)
does not last during two units of time (lā tabqā waqtayn), and on the other hand two actions can be performed
with it.121 al-Māturīdī himself Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān explains the topic of capacity (istiṭāʿa) in the following
manner:
Capacity is the capacity of states (istiṭāʿa al-aḥwāl), and as we stated earlier, it precedes (tataqaddamu) the
action. Knower of the ultimate truth is God. As for the capacity to act (istiṭāʿa al-afʿāl), this type of capability
occurs (taḥduthu) simultaneously with the occurrence of the actions (bi ḥudūthi’l-afʿāl) and actions take place
through it. It is the same with time units that do not last in a second-time unit (ka al-awqāti allatī lā tabqā fī
thāni). So, the capacity to act is similar to the time unit that does not continue in the second time unit (ka al-
waqti alladhi lā yabqā fî waqti thāni). Knower of the ultimate truth is God.122

114
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 361 (396).
115
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 322 (344).
116
According to al-Māturīdī, human actions can be reduced into accidents of motion and rest, and Allah governs over all the acts
of motion and rest. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 329 (352).
117
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 329 (352).
118
See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 331 (355).
119
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 361 (396).
120
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 354 (386).
121
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 364 (400).
122
Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, II, 267.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 255

The foregoing declarations of al-Māturīdī are very important. Indeed, al-Māturīdī not only
emphasizes the discontinuity of accidents, but further he defends the idea that time is discontinuous. This
implies that al-Māturīdī maintains that time has atomic structure, like the majority of atomist mutakallimūn
defended.123
Imām al-Māturīdī uses the concept of the indivisible particle most clearly within the Muʿtazilite
context of whether the universe contains any agents other than God. According to him, Muʿtazilites argue
that motion, rest, composition and separation in the universe can be caused by others beside God. They
maintained that certain beings (humans) are the creators of their own actions. In this sense, ships, buildings,
and writing are all formed through the endeavors of humans. According to al-Māturīdī, if it is possible for
these types of things to be created by humans, then, due to the part-whole relationship, it becomes possible
for the entire universe to be formed by God and by creatures. In this case, more than one agent would be
involved in the creation of the universe.124
For al-Māturīdī, the Muʿtazilites’ defense of this criticism that God’s act of creating takes place in
the imperceptible/atomic planes of existence, and that therefore within the perceptible macro plane
humans are also capable of creation is invalid. Indeed, if the possibility of the possession of accidents such
as motion, rest, composition and division is granted to certain creatures, then following from the law of
analogy of the unknown to the known (qiyās al-ghāib ʿalā al-shāhid), the need for these to be attributed to God
in the imperceptible world is also lifted. This is because, although certain accidents including composition
and separation are sometimes observed, the composer that gives them motion is not perceived. This
function may belong to some others besides God, because these kinds of functions, whose agents are
invisible, are similar to functions, whose agents are perceptible. In this case, the above-mentioned view of
the Muʿtazilites is similar to the views defended by naturalists and the Sanawiyya.125 He explains this in the
following manner:
If it is imagined that the “thin/transparent” bodies (al-ajsām al-laṭīfa) are divided into indivisible parts (ajzāʾ
mimmā lā yatajazzaʾ), it becomes impossible for each of these parts to be perceived by sense and to lead us into
the field of reasoning. For the substances (al-jawāhir) can also come together without a divine intervention
over their thinness and density. Accordingly, the theological proofs for understanding that bodies (are created
and governed by Allah) can be formed by the influence of others. It means that Allah has not revealed to
humans the proofs that the creation and governance belong to Himself in a manner that these proofs did not
eliminate the possibility of belonging these qualities to the others and reinforce the relation of them to

123
On this subject, see Mūsā b. Maymūn, Dalālat al-ḥā’irīn, ed. Hüseyin Atay (Ankara: Ankara Üniversitesi Yayınları, 1979), 197-198.
124
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 171 (155). al-Māturīdī argues that if it were accepted, just as Muʿtazilites did, that such accidents of coming-to-
be (al-akwān) as motion, rest, composition, and separation were created by beings other than Allah, the temporal creation
argument (ḥudūth) would also be affected negatively by this. This is because, what provides the kalām scholars with the
createdness of the objects constituting the universe is the fact that these objects have never been free from being in the state of
separation, adhesion, motion, or rest. Allowing that these previously described states have not been created by Allah in a similar
way to the act of human, whose action occurs on his own hands and in the real sense, it would be impossible to find a chance to
prove the existence of any bodies or substances that have been originated by God’s action and that is perceivable as it is. For [in
that case], the actions mentioned above can come about without the intervention of God. Therefore, according to al-Māturīdī,
it should be accepted that all human acts occur in the manner that Allah creates them in the hand of whoever He wishes, also
in the condition and under the scheme that He pleases. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 330, 332 (353, 356).
125
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 171 (155-156).

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


256 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Himself. Indeed, (according to the Muʿtazilites) Allah has not done this in the sensible world, then, how can
this happen in a non-sensible world [that is in the atomic level]?126

These statements are a rare example that are extant today and which show how al-Māturīdī uses
the concept of the indivisible part. Here, he appears not to have a problem with the concept of an indivisible
part except that it cannot be perceived by senses. Despite the fact that al-Māturīdī defends the principle
that “the universe can be known not through reasoning but through the senses,” this does not mean that
he rejects the self-evident rational argument of the mutakallimūn who in support of atomism claim that “that
which is restricted by ends and boundaries cannot contain the infinite.” This is because, in his Kitāb al-
Tawhīd, he develops an argument for the creation of the universe with the statement that “Something that
is formed by the combination of finite parts (ijtimāʿ ajzāʾ mutanāhiya) cannot be infinite (gayru
mutanāhiya)”.127 Also, while interpreting the Sūra al-Aʿrāf (7) in his Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, al-Māturīdī indicates
that “the parts of the universe are finite as a whole (ajzāʾu’l-ʿālami huwa bi kulliyyatihā mutanāhun).128 As it
seen from these examples, al-Māturīdī seems to benefit from the concept of the indivisible part, which
supports the finiteness of the universe in terms of divisibility and separation.

Undoubtedly, indications that al-Māturīdī embraced the concept of the indivisible particle are not
limited to these. This is also clear from his rejection of other theories of matter, all of which had emerged
in his lifetime as rivals to atomism. In this context, further clear indications that al-Māturīdī opposed the
idea of an eternal universe include his rejection of theories including that of bodies interpenetrating one
another (tadākhul), substances occupying the same space and manifesting after being latent inside each
other (al-kumūn wa al-ẓuhūr), both related to al-Naẓẓām’s well-known defense of the view that bodies are
composed of substances which are infinitely divisible,129 and also his criticism of the Aristotelian

126
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 172 (156). al-Māturīdī also provides other pieces of argument on the origination of the human acts by Allah in
reality. For instance, according to him, in the field of kalām, the analogical reasoning (al-qiyās) is either used or is not. If it is not
going to be used, the method, which opponents of the kalām scholars adopted as to know about the Creator (al-Ṣāniʿ), will become
nullified. Because Allah cannot be perceived through senses (al-ḥawās), His existence can only be known using reasoning. Here,
the reasoning is nothing more than making inferences based on the sensible world (al-istidlāl bi l-shāid). There is also this: We
observe that all the meaning in the universe, along with their accidents, are present in acts of creation (afʿālu l-khalq). If the acts
are not deemed as being created [by rational arguments], the concept of “creation” will only be understood through revelation
(al-samʿ). In that case, either the general principle established by the divine revelation, meaning “He is the Creator of everything”
(al- Anʿām 6/102), will be rendered authority –because it is not possible to grasp the existence of creation for everything through
its special name (ism al-ḥāsiyya)-, or as previously described the necessity of the reasoning (al-qiyās) will be accepted. Besides,
humans do not reach the status of the creator just because they own their actions. Then, his act is originated by someone else
beyond himself. It should also be noted that the way to know the agent (al-fāʿil) is in the traces that his action leaves behind.
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 331 (356-357).
127
Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 171 (155-156).
128
See Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān, 5, 381.
129
These expressions al-Māturīdī can be given as an example of this: “Several times of the volume of something, which is in the
process of manifestation (ẓuhūr), cannot be present within the object in which that thing exists. Consequently, the theory,
claiming that human is present within the sperm, and that tree is present within the seed, is regarded as unfounded.” Kitāb al-
Tawḥīd, 95 (60). “Generation (kawn) of something out of another thing only means that the latter becomes manifested (ẓahara)
after being latent (mustajinna) within the former. That, however, is impossible (muḥāl). That is, a human as a whole and a tree as
a whole together with all the fruits it will bear happen to be existent inside the previously described origin/root (al-ʾaṣl)! Or, all
humans, along with the substances (jawāhir) constituting them, happen to be hidden in the sperm, which is inside the father’s
core! Then, uncountable layers happen to be existent in a single object! Certainly, that is one of the cases that a healthy soul

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 257

hylomorphic theory of matter which propounds that bodies have an infinite potentiality in terms of
division.130
In the conclusion of our section on Imām al-Māturīdī’s views on bodies, substance, and accidents,
we should note that Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī indicates that al-Māturīdī embraced atomism and defended the
prevailing kalām view that “the universe is composed of indivisible substances and accidents.” For example,
al-Nasafī describes the constituents of the universe as follows:
As for the parts of the universe (aqsām al-ʿālam), most of the mutakallimūn claimed that it has three parts:
Substances, bodies, and accidents. Sheikh Abū Manṣūr al-Māturīdī, however, did not approve of this
classification because there is a possibility of interpenetration among them. Since bodies are composed
(murakkab) of substances (al-jawāhir), they are also substances at the same time.131

Here, al-Nasafī’s explanations, and in particular his statement that “bodies are composed of
substances,” contains an indication that al-Māturīdī embraced an atomist model that posited that bodies in
the universe consist of indivisible substances known as atoms. In fact, al-Nasafī moves on to say that
“material objects” (aʿyān) are divided into those that are not compound (gayru’l-mutarakkib)– which are
defined by the mutakallimūn as “substances” – and those that are compound (al-mutarakkib) - which are
defined by the mutakallimūn as “bodies.” In this way, it is understood that each body is considered to be a
substance.”132 He also says, in relation to Hishām b. al-Ḥakam, al-Naẓẓām, many early philosophers (awāil)
and mathematicians, “they denied the indivisible part (al-juzʾ alladhī lā yatajazzaʾ), which we have named
‘substance’ (jawhar).”133 Both of these statements by al-Nasafī strongly indicate that in the final analysis, al-
Māturīdī did not embrace the idea that composite bodies were comprised of simple accidents, but they were
formed by substances understood to be indivisible particles or atoms.

3. Atomism in Māturīdiyya Kalām After Imām al-Māturīdī

Even though Imām al-Māturīdī had a loose approach concerning the theories of matter, the
Māturīdites who came after him possessed a clear view of atomism, which they supported with established
concepts regarding body, substance, and accident.

Upon stating that in general “substance” (jawhar) is defined as “that which stands by itself (al-qāʾim
bi al-dhātihī)” al-Nasafī indicates that this meaning, which is ascribed to the term “substance,” has caused
some controversies because of the fact that Allah also stands by Himself. Also, he argues that therefore it is

cannot imagine, and a sound mind cannot adopt.” Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 112-113 (82). They can say that objects with their substances
(jawāhir) are latent (mustajinna) in the origin (fi al-ʾaṣl) and afterward become manifest (taṭhuru) in actuality. (…) There is a point
in this opinion that the mind opposes: Substances that are as voluminous as several times of a thing are impossible to reside in
that thing. For such an assumption implies contradiction (tanāquḍ), deterioration (fasād) [of the internal structure] and disregard
for the observation.” Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 145 (123). The latency (kumūn) is improbable (lā yaḥtamilu), for it is absurd for something
to be a place (makān) for something ten times bigger than itself. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 200 (193).
130
See. Kitāb al-Tawḥīd, 143,144 (122, 123), 231-235 (232-237).
131
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/62-63.
132
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/63.
133
Tabṣira al-adilla 1, 70.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


258 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

more appropriate to give the meaning of “origin/root/foundation” (al-ʾaṣl) to substance. al-Nasafī explains
the reason for this as follows:
Our evidence is that substance only refers to “origin/root/foundation” (al-ʾaṣl) in the dictionary. About the
individuals famous for their goodness and generosity among the honorable and eminent people, it is said that
such and such person is acting in terms of beneficence suited to his noble, substantial, glorious, and
immaculate ancestry. If a dress is sewn beautifully and has a good quality fabric, it is called “substantial dress
(thawbun jawhariyyun)”. Based on this, they [the speakers of the language] named indivisible parts of the body
(mā lā yatajazzau min al-ajzā’ al-jism) “substance (jawhar).” For out of which the combinations (al-mutarakkibāt)
are made, are in the state of the foundations of them (combinations).134

Afterwards, al-Nasafī states that a meaningful name denominates that which contains the meaning
attached to its name for no reason other than that it comprises the meaning of that which it describes. In
this sense, according to the dictionary the meaning of the utterance of substance is that while it does
connote stand by itself, it carries a meaning related to its being “origin/root (ʾaṣl)”. Therefore, according to
him, to accord the notion of origin to substance is better than to give it the meaning of standing by itself.135

In regard to the debates and controversies surrounding atomism in Islamic thought, Abu’l-Muʿīn al-
Nasafī says, “this is an important subject that contains in itself many proofs as well as many suspicions,”136
and thereby indicates that he is clearly in favor of atomism. This is because, he thinks that the rejection of
atomism –since a thing with infinite particles cannot be larger or smaller than another thing that also has
infinite particles- can lead to absurd conclusions such as that a mustard seed is not smaller than a mountain,
or that a mountain is not bigger than a mustard seed. Indeed, to deny that a mountain is bigger than a
mustard seed is to deny what is clear before the eye.137
al-Nasafī then speaks of an argument that is put forward against the above-mentioned claim that
runs as follows: “Even though the objects of knowledge and power of God are infinite, because His Self is the
object of knowledge of Himself but not an object of power, the things included in God’s knowledge are more
than the things included in His power.” In this case, a situation in which an infinite thing is more than
another infinite thing occurs. However, according to al-Nasafī, this opposition is invalid. Because it leads to
an illogical conclusion in the same way with decomposition of atoms, mustard seed, and mountain.
Performing reasoning about an impossible thing is not right.138

On the other hand, in response to those arguments pertaining to Allah’s knowledge and power
brought against him, al-Nasafī provides the following counter-argument: “Who is the creator of the
composition that occurs in the parts of a certain body? They must say “Allah”. Then they are said to as
follows: “Is Allah capable of creating annihilation of composition instead of composition and separation?”

134
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/150.
135
This definition of al-Nasafī was also shared by other Māturīdite mutakallimūn at that time. For instance, Abu’l-Yusr al-Bazdawī
(d. 493/1100) also says that “Substance (al-jawhar) is the name for the indivisible part (al-juzʾ alladhī lā yatajazzaʾ) that is recipient
(al-qābil) of accidents. It is called body because it is the origin/foundation of bodies (ʾaṣlu l-ajsām), for the substance of something
is the origin/foundation (ʾaṣl) of it.” Uṣūl al-dīn, ed. Hans Peter Linss (Cairo: Dār Ihyā al-kutub al-ʿarabiya), 12.
136
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/70.
137
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/70.
138
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/70-71.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 259

According to al-Nasafī, if they respond by saying “No”; they happen to regard Allah as incapable of
destroying something and creating its opposite instead of it. If they answer by saying “Yes”; then when
composition of the part is annihilated, there does not remain a single part that is recipient of division, as
the recipient of division does not become composite by itself. What is not composite, on the other hand,
does not receive division. So that which emerges when all parts become non-recipients of division and turn
into the indivisible parts is the meaning of what are called ‘substances’.”139

On the definition of body (jism), the shift between Imām al-Māturīdī and those Māturīdites who come
after him becomes more evident with Nūr al-Dīn al-Ṣābūnī (d. 580/1184). After treating the concepts of
substance and accident in a manner similar to that of al-Nasafī, and providing arguments like that of the
piece of mustard in relation to atoms, he says the following concerning the definition of body:
According to some mathematicians, the body is that which is three-dimensional consisting of length, width,
and depth. In the opinion of us, however, a combination (tarakkub) of two substances is enough to call it
“body.” For if one more substance (al-jawhar al-wāḥid) is added to any of the three dimensions (al-abʿād al-
thalātha) that belong to one of the two bodies of the same volume, this body can be said to be “more
voluminous than the other”. If an absolute and a smallest composition were not enough to call two substances
“body”, it would not be right to accept that the body described above is more voluminous than the other just
by the addition of one dimension/substance (buʿd wāḥid). Therefore, the true definition of the body must be
as follows: Body is that which consists of (mutarakkib) or is composed of (mujtamiʿ) two or more substances.140

As can be seen, the mathematically-inspired three-dimensional body definition of Imām al-Māturīdī


has here been replaced by Nūr al-Dīn al-Ṣābūnī’s linguistically-based definition of body. This situation shows
that even though Māturīdite scholars differed from Imām al-Māturīdī on the three-dimensional definition
of bodies, there was not a great difference between them regarding the fact that bodies are compounds that
are formed by the composition of simple parts or point-like atoms, which are not called “body.”

Conclusion

In conclusion, Imām al-Māturīdī, the founder of an important kalām school that had a significant
impact on Islamic thought, lived in a period which may be termed as the golden age of the Muʿtazilites of
the 3rd/9th century. In this period, the Muʿtazilite mutakallimūn felt a deep interest in the nature,
functioning, and origination of universe that exceeded apologetic concerns and furthermore developed a
rich understanding of matter and the characteristics of bodies. At the same time, the Muʿtazilites residing
in Baghdād and Basra discussed in detail subjects including atoms, void space, motion, change, causality,
continuity and discontinuity.
On the other hand, the decline of the Muʿtazila school following the mihna period brought criticisms
on the views expressed by Muʿtazilites on concepts such as body and accident, as well as on other fields of
knowledge in which they had previously engaged. These criticisms aimed against the Muʿtazilites led to the
search for more conservative approaches to subjects related to physics and cosmology, which in turn

139
Tabṣira al-adilla, 1/71.
140
Nūr al-Dīn al-Ṣābūnī, al-Bidāyah fī Usúl al-din/Matürîdiyye Akaidi, ed. & trans. Bekir Topaloğlu (Istanbul: IFAV 2014), 20.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


260 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

resulted in Imām al-Māturīdī’s and Imām al-Ashʿarī’s Ahl al-Sunna kalām schools, in Transoxiana and Basra
respectively.
If we approach Imām al-Māturīdī and the subject of atomism within this context, we see that one of
the fundamental aspects of his thought is certainly that his approach to the study of matter is not a topic to
which primacy is granted in terms of the elucidation of religion. Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī, one of his followers,
also notes that as long as there was no necessity in regard to religious matters, al-Māturīdī was not
interested in seeking to describe the true nature of a thing (ḥaqāʾiq al-ashyāʾ) and that therefore, he abstained
from attempting conclusive definitions of concepts like body, substance, and accident.
al-Māturīdī’s religious approach to physics and cosmology presents certain difficulties for our study.
These difficulties are not limited to the fact that al-Māturīdī does not systematically deal with subjects
related to physical theories or that his cosmological views are found in fragments scattered in his works on
theological matters. Imām al-Māturīdī’s adoption of a religiously minded approach to cosmological issues,
as opposed to one that seeks absolute truths, lead in many instances to him not possessing sets of concepts
particular to his own thought. For this reason, he was able to shift between different meanings when using
concepts like substance, accident, and body, so that sometimes the meanings he accorded to these concepts
were shaped by the individuals with whom he was interacting. This factor makes it difficult to ascertain
Imām al-Māturīdī’s actual views regarding matter and atomism.

On the other hand, Imām Māturīdī’s assertion that theories of matter do not directly involve
religious issues allowed him certain advantages in regard to kalām. Firstly, this situation enabled him to
refrain from subscribing to a specific theory of matter, while also giving him the opportunity to Islamicize
the views of his opponents as opposed to outright rejecting those views. According to al-Māturīdī, many
theories of matter comprise truths attained through observation, and if interpreted correctly, these theories
demonstrate the createdness of the universe, and the existence of a Creator. al-Māturīdī’s focus on multiple
theories of matter also allowed him to apply the method of the cumulative case of evidences in his approach
to proving the existence of God. In this sense, he was able to present a variety of different forms of argument
pertaining to the existence of God and the creation of the universe, including the finitude of particles in the
universe, Aristotle’s prime matter and form (hayūla wa sūrah), the substances of light and darkness (nūr wa
ẓulma), the temporal origination of accidents and bodies (ḥudūth al-a‘rāḍ wa al-ajsām), and the theory of
natures (ṭabāʿī). al-Māturīdī’s flexible approach to different theories of matter, and his preference for
reconciling these theories with belief in creation, shows us how atomism, which was an Ancient Greek
materialist theory, was Islamicized.

al-Māturīdī’s flexibility towards theories of matter, and his adoption of them in proving the
createdness of the universe and the existence of God, has allowed for space to form where mistaken
interpretations have been made about him like the idea that he accepted theories such as prime matter-
form, natures, causality, and continuity. However, al-Māturīdī did not embrace these theories of matter in-
themselves. Rather, he appropriated some of their arguments to prove the existence of a sovereign Creator.
In this manner, he was able to refute his opponents’ views regarding the eternity of the universe while at
the same time using their theories for his own theological purposes and thereby adapting them to belief in
creation.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 261

For instance, the fact that al-Māturīdī considers “natures” (ṭabāʿī) as substances or accidents and
includes them into his system of thought does not mean that he accepted these concepts as materialists
(dahriyya) and naturalists (tabīʿiyya) understood them. Because he does not accept the idea of nature
understood as the source of the motion by itself and the causal factor of the phenomena in the universe in
the same way that the proponents of natures (aṣḥāb al-ṭabāʿī) believed. According to him, even though such
natures as hotness, coldness, wetness and dryness are numerically finite and have a one-way/uniform
motion, the objects in the universe that are constituted out of them have incredible diversity. Natures must
be put together in a very delicate way to be able to constitute the objects that are so complicated and diverse.
However, because natures lack intelligence and consciousness, they cannot establish a uniform composition
on their own. Moreover, the fact that natures exist in objects proportionally despite the fact that they
cannot come together due to being contrary to each other, indicates that they are combined by a volition of
an agent radically different from themselves, i.e. a sovereign Creator.
Even though Imām al-Māturīdi’s apologetic approach to issues regarding mater and physical bodies
provided him with some theological advantages in terms of not necessarily devoting himself to a specific
scientific or philosophical doctrine, and making use of different matter theories for the sake of religious
aims, we should point out that this apologetic attitude might have had some adverse effects on his school in
the historical process. While the Māturīdiyya kalām, especially after Abu’l-Muʿīn al-Nasafī, mostly remained
stagnant, the Ashʿariyya school, which pivots on a model that is integrated or mixed (mamzūj) with
philosophy and science, brought forth such renowned names as Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (d. 606/1210), Sayf al-
Dīn al-Āmidī (d. 631/1233), Qāḍī Bayḍāwī (d. 685/1286), Saʿd al-Dīn al-Taftāzānī (d. 792/1390) and Sayyid
Sharīf al-Jurjānī (d. 816/1413). Therefore, it might be a more accurate attitude to base the stagnation of
Māturīdites relative to the Ashʿarites on the former’s principle of not engaging in scientific and
philosophical issues unless it is required theologically and less so on their geographical setting

At the same time, however, all of this does not mean that Imām al-Māturīdī did not base his thoughts
on certain cosmological theories, and that he did not feel himself closer to certain theories of matter. Despite
the fact that al-Nasafī states how al-Māturīdī chose not to describe the true nature of things as long as there
was no religious necessity to do so, we see that his views regarding “accidents” had a major impact on his
general thought. By taking as a basis the view of the “discontinuity of accidents,” al-Māturīdī seeks to
establish many theological principles including proof from origination, the existence of God, the continuity
of God’s act of creation, human acts and miracles. The discontinuity of accidents is also behind his confident
approach to other theories of matter including natures (ṭabāʿī). It is certain that al-Māturīdī placed a subject
like the discontinuity of accidents, which was controversial among the mutakallimūn, at the center of the
relationship between God and the world and thereby he interpreted many different issues of kalām such as
the creation of human acts (khalq afʿāl al-ʿibād) in a manner that exhibits an occasionalist perspective of the
universe like Ashʿarites.

As for atomism, this subject appeared in many different ways in the period in which Imām al-
Māturīdī lived. In this sense, an individual’s assertion that the entire universe is composed by accidents, or
his use of substance in the sense of body, would not mean that this individual, within the scope of that
period’s conceptual frameworks, was either a proponent or opponent of atomism. In the time-period in
which al-Māturīdī lived, there were those who defined an indivisible particle as “body,” as well as those who

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


262 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

argued that the entire universe was composed of substances and rejected atomism, or those who defended
atomism and claimed that the entire universe was composed of accidents. For this reason, any study that
attempts to consider al-Māturīdī’s views regarding atomism must keep in mind both his own particular
approach to these types of subjects as well as the conceptual frameworks of his time-period.
Although al-Māturīdī’s general approach did not involve detailed considerations of atomism, this
does not mean that he rejected atomism. Indeed, if we take into consideration the conceptual and
problematic background of his period, we will find that there are important clues which indicate that al-
Māturīdī’s thought system was based on a view structured on atomism. Examples include his use of
Muʿtazilite scholars’ atomist terminology when speaking of bodies, his reference to things that are not
composites as bodies, and his argument that there exist in the universe things that are “simple”, in other
words not composite (muallaf). Also notable is al-Māturīdī’s acceptance of the principle of “a thing that is
limited by limits and boundaries cannot contain infinite things,” an argument used by the mutakallimūn of
the time close to atomism, and his critical approach to theories of matter that support infinite divisibility
such as interpenetration (tadākhul), latency (al-kumūn), manifestation (al-ẓuhūr), and prime matter-form.
Also, it should not be forgotten that al-Māturīdī uses the argument that “something that is formed by the
combination of finite parts (ijtimāʿu ajzāʾ mutanāhī) cannot be infinite (gayr mutanāhī),” a premise also
commonly used by atomist mutakallimūn. Moreover, accidents, which played an important role in his
thought system, have a simple structure and are therefore atomic in nature. al-Māturīdī not only
emphasized the discontinuity of accidents, but further defended, like the majority of atomist mutakallimūn,
the idea that time has an atomic structure.

Therefore, what should be considered here is not whether Imām al-Māturīdī’s approach to atomism
is agnostic or whether he subscribed to anti-atomism; what should be considered is the type of atomism
which al-Māturīdī accepts. Even though in certain parts of his life, due to various epistemological
justifications, Imām al-Māturīdī felt sympathy towards the notion that bodies in the universe are collection
of accidents, in the final analysis he did not adhere to this view. Upon closer inspection, important
differences arise between al-Māturīdī’s views on accidents and “the proponents of accidents” (aṣhāb al-aʿrāḍ)
such as Ḍirār b. ʿAmr and Husayn al-Najjār. Firstly, according to Ḍirār and al-Najjār, these accidents which
are regarded indivisible parts are themselves bodies whereas Imām al-Māturīdī argues that simple (basīṭ)
things that comprise bodies cannot be called “bodies” because they do not possess the accidents of
aggregation (taʾlīf). Besides, according to Imām al-Māturīdī accidents do not stand by themselves; they do
not involve states like composition, contact, motion and interaction. Furthermore, according to Imām al-
Māturīdī, accidents are not durative/continuous. This situation shows why in the final analysis Imām al-
Māturīdī does not accept the view that bodies in the universe are comprised of accidents.

Finally, we should note that close and distant classical-period followers of al-Māturīdī, like Abu’l-
Muʿīn al-Nasafī, who possessed books of his that have not reached us, did not have any doubt that al-
Māturīdī after all embraced the standard model of kalām atomism, defended atomism to the degree that
they sometimes charged anti-atomists to be heretical. In Classical Islamic thought, anti-atomism is
attributed to al-Naẓẓām and other marginal groups like the falāsifa, and it is not possible to consider Imām
al-Māturīdī within these groups that are commonly regarded as heretical. Therefore, Imām al-Māturīdī’s
reluctance to engage directly with atomism in his extant works should not be interpreted as indicating that

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum
Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism” | 263

he was opposed to atomism; rather, this factor would be better explained if tied to Imām al-Māturīdī’s
general reluctance to engage with scientific/philosophical issues which are not directly related to religion
or commonly held, as indicated by al-Nasafī.

References
’Abd al-Qāhir al-Baghdādī. Uṣūl al-dīn. Istanbul: Maṭbaʿat al-Dawla, 1928.
ʿAbd al-Jabbār, al-Qāḍī. Kitāb al-Majmūʿ fi al-Muḥīṭ bi al-taklīf. ed. J. J. Houben. Beirut: Dār al-Mashriq, 1986.
Abū Zayd, Muna Ahmad. al-Tasawwur al-zarri. Beirut: al-Muassasa al-Jāmiiyya, 1414/1994.
Adamson, Peter. Philosophy in the Islamic World. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Alper, Hülya. İmam Mâtürîdî’de Akıl-Vahiy İlişkisi. İstanbul: İz Publication, 2009.
al-Ᾱmidī, Sayf al-Dīn. Abkār al-Afkār fī Uṣūl al-Dīn. ed. A. al-Mahdī. 3 Vol. Cairo: Dār al-Kutub, 2002.
Anawati, G. C. “Kalam”. Encyclopedia of Religion. Second edition ed. Lindsay Jones. 8: 5059. USA: Macmillan 2005.
al-Ashʿarī, Abu’l-Ḥasan. Maqālāt al-Islāmiyyīn wa ikhtilāf al-muṣallīn. ed. Muḥammad Muḥyī al-Dīn ʻAbd al-Ḥamīd Cairo:
Maktabat al-Nahḍah al-Miṣriyyah, 2000.
al-Bazdawī, Abu’l-Yusr. Uṣūl al-dīn. ed. Hans Peter Linss Cairo: Dār Ihyā al-kutub al-ʿArabiya, 1963.
Bulgen, Mehmet. “Klasik Dönem Kelâmında Dakiku’l-Kelâmın Yeri ve Rolü”. Turkish Journal of Islamic Studies 33 (2015), 39-72.
Bulgen, Mehmet. Kelâm Atomculuğu ve Modern Kozmoloji = Kalām Atomism and Modern Cosmology. Ankara: TDV Publication, 2018.
Bulgen, Mehmet. Klasik İslâm Düşüncesinde Atomculuk Eleştirileri = Criticisms of Atomism in Classical Islamic Thought. İstanbul: İFAV
Publication, 2017.
Dhanani, Alnoor. “al-Māturīdī and al-Nasafī on Atomism and the Tabā’ī”. Büyük Türk Bilgini İmâm Mâtürîdî ve Mâtürîdîlik:
Milletler Arası Tartışmalı İlmi Toplantı (İstanbul, 22-24 Mayıs 2009). İstanbul: İFAV Publication, 2009.
Dhanani, Alnoor. “V/XI. Yüzyıl Kelâm Fiziğinin Problemleri”. trans. Mehmet Bulğen. KADER 13/2 (2015), 862-885.
Dhanani, Alnoor. The Physical Theory of Kalām: Atoms, Space and Void in Baṣra Muʿtazilî Cosmology, Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1994.
Fakhry, Majid. A History of Islamic Philosophy. Second Edition London: Longman, 1983.
al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. Iḥṣāʾ al-ʿulūm. ed. 'Uthman Amin. Cairo: Dār al-Fikr al-ʿArabī, 1949.
Frank, Richard M. “Bodies and Atoms: The Ashʿarite Analysis”. Islamic Theology and Philosophy. ed. Michael E. Marmura. 39-54.
Albany: State University of New York Press,1984.
Frank, Richard M. “Notes and Remarks on the Ṭabāʿi in the Teaching of al-Māturīdī”. Melanges D'islamologie. Ed. Pierre Salmon.
Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1974.
Grant, Edward. A History of Natural Philosophy: From the Ancient World to the Nineteenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007.
Gutas, Dimitri. Greek Thought Arabic Culture. New York: Routledge, 1999.
Heinen, Anton M.. “Mutakallimūn and Mathematicians”. Der Islam 55/1 (1978), 57-73.
Ibn al-Murtaḍā. “Riyāḍat al-afhām fī laṭīf al-kalām”. Al-Baḥr al-Zakhkhār al-Jāmiʿ li-Madhāhib ʿUlamāʾ al-Amṣār. ed. Muḥammad
Tamir. Beirut: Dār al-Kutub al-ʿIlmīyah, 2001.
Ibn Fūrak, Abū Bakr Muḥammad. Mujarrad Maqālāt al-Shaykh Abī al-Ḥasan al-Ashʿarī. ed. Daniel Gimert. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq,
1987.
Ibn Mattawayh. al-Tadhkirah fī aḥkām al-jawāhir wa-al-aʻrāḍ. ed. Daniel Gimaret. Cairo: Institut Français d’Archélogie Orientale,
2009.
Ibn Sīnā. Kitāb al-shifāʾ: Fizik II. Ed. and Trans. Muhittin Macit - Ferruh Özpilavcı. Istanbul: Litera Publication, 2005.
al-Juwaynī, Imāmu’l-Ḥaramayn Abu’l-Maʿālī. al-Shāmil fī uṣūl al-dīn. Ed. ʻAlī Sāmī Nashshār - Fayṣal Budayr ʻAwn - Suhayr
Muḥammad Mukhtār. Alexandria: Munshaʾāt al-Maʿārif, 1969.
al-Juwaynī, Imāmu’l-Ḥaramayn Abu’l-Maʿālī. Kitāb al-Irshād. ed. Muḥammad Yūsuf Musa - Al Abdulḥāmid. Cairo: Maktaba al-
Hanci 1950.
al-Kaʿbī, Abu’l-Qāsim al-Balkhī. Kitāb al-Maqālāt wa ma‘ahu ʿUyūn al-masāʾil wa al-jawābāt. ed. Hüseyin Hansu - Rājih Abdulhamīd
Kurdī. Istanbul, Amman: KURAMER, Dār al-Fath 2018.

ULUM 2/2 (December 2019)


264 | Bulgen, “al-Māturīdī and Atomism”

Karadaş, Cağfer. "The New Approach to The Source of Kalām Atomism". ULUM 1 / 2 (December 2019), 225-244.
al-Khayyāṭ. Kitāb al-Intiṣār. ed. Albert Nasri Nader. Beirut: al-Matbaat al-l-Katulikiyya, 1957.
al-Kindī. “Fī al-Falsafah al-Ūlā (İlk Felsefe Üzerine)”. Felsefî Risâleler ed. and transl. Mahmut Kaya. Istanbul: Klasik Publication,
2013.
Macdonald, D. B.. “Klasik Dönem Kelâmında Atomcu Zaman ve Sürekli Yeniden Yaratma”. Trans. Mehmet Bulğen. KADER 14/1
(2016), 279-297.
al-Mâtürîdî, Abū Manṣūr. Kitāb al-tawḥīd. ed. Bekir Topaloğlu - Muhammed Aruçi. Ankara: TDV Publication, 2017, 2005.
al-Māturīdī, Abū Manṣūr. Kitāb al-tawḥīd. Trans. Bekir Topaloğlu. Ankara: İSAM Publication, 2015.
al-Māturīdī, Abū Manṣūr. Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān. ed. Ahmed Vanlıoğlu - Bekir Topaloğlu. 1 Vol. Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2005.
al-Māturīdī, Abū Manṣūr. Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān. ed. Ertuğrul Boynukalın - Bekir Topaloğlu, 5 Vol. Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2006.
al-Māturīdī, Abū Manṣūr. Taʾwīlāt al-Qurʾān. ed. Halil İbrahim Kaçar - Bekir Topaloğlu. 10 Vol. Istanbul: Dār al-Mīzān, 2007.
Muhtaroğlu, Nazif. “Al-Māturīdī’s View of Causality”. Occasionalism Revisited: New Essays from the Islamic and Western
Philosophical Traditions. ed. Nazif Muhtaroglu. Abu Dhabi: Kalam Research and Media, 2017: 3-21.
Mūsā b. Maymūn. Dalālat al-ḥā’irīn. ed. Hüseyin Atay Ankara: Ankara University Publication, 1979.
al-Nasafī, Abu’l-Mu’īn. Tabṣira al-adilla fī uṣūl al-dīn. ed. Hüseyin Atay. Ankara: Diyanet İşleri Başkanlığı Publication, 2004.
Nasr, S. H. Islamic Philosophy from its Origin to the Present. New York: State University of New York Press, 2006.
al-Nīsābūrī, Abū Rashīd. Masā’il fī al-Khilāf bayn al-Basriyyīn wa al-Baghdādiyyīn. ed. Ma‘n Ziyada - Ridwan al-Sayyid. Beirut:
Ma‘had al-Inma’ al-‘Arabi, 1979.
Pines, Shlomo. İslâm Atomculuğu. trans. Osman Demir. İstanbul: Klasik Publication, 2018.
Rashed, Marwan. “Natural Philosophy”. The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy ed. Peter Adamson, Richard C. Taylor,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
Rudolph, Ulrich. Al-Māturīdī and the Development of Sunnī Theology in Samarqand. Trans. Rodrigo Adem. Leiden, Boston: Brill.
2015.
Sabra, A. I.. “Kalâm Atomism as an Alternative Philosophy to Hellenizing Falsafa”. Arabic Theology, Arabic Philosophy: Essays in
Celebration of Richard M. Frank. Ed. James E. Montgomery. 152. Leuven: Orientalia Lovaniencia Analecta, 2006.
Şenharputlu, Ahmet. “Klasik Kelâm Döneminde Arazların Bekası Sorunu”. MA Thesis, Marmara University, 2017.
al-Shaykh al-Mufīd. Awāil al-Maqālāt. ed. Ibrāhim al-Anṣārī Mashad: al-Muʿtamar al-ʿālam li Alfiyyah Al-Shaykh al-Mufīd,
1413/2000
Türcan, Galip. “Klasik Kelâm’ın Apolojetik Değeri”. Turkish Journal of Islamic Studies 17/4 (2004).
Türker, Ömer. “Kelâm İlminin Metafizikleşme Süreci”. Dîvân: Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 12/23 (2007/2), 75-92.
Uluç, Tahir. İmâm Mâtürîdî’nin Âlemin Ontolojik Yapısı Hakkında Filozofları Eleştirisi. İstanbul: İnsan Publication, 2017.
Van Ess, Josef. “Muʿtazilite Atomism”. Flowering Muslim Theology. trans. Jane Marie Toldd. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 2006, 79-115.
Van Ess, Josef. “The Beginnings of Islamic Theology”. The Cultural Context of Medieval Learning. ed. J. E. Murdoch and E. D. Sylla.
87–111. Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1975.
Van Ess, Josef. Theology and Science: The Case of Abū Isḥaq al-Naẓẓām. Ann Arbor: Center for Near Eastern and North African
Studies, University of Michigan, 1978.
Wolfson, Harry Austryn. The Philosophy of the Kalam. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976.
Yavuz, Yusuf Şevki. “İmâm Mâtürîdî’nin Tabiat ve İlliyyete Bakışı”. Büyük Türk Bilgini İmâm Mâtürîdî ve Mâtürîdîlik: Milletler
Arası Tartışmalı İlmi Toplantı. (İstanbul, 22-24 Mayıs 2009). İstanbul: İFAV Publication, 2009.

www.dergipark.org.tr/en/pub/ulum

You might also like