You are on page 1of 54

Crisis and Constitutionalism: Roman

Political Thought from the Fall of the


Republic to the Age of Revolution 1st
Edition Benjamin Straumann
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/crisis-and-constitutionalism-roman-political-thought-fr
om-the-fall-of-the-republic-to-the-age-of-revolution-1st-edition-benjamin-straumann/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

1931: Debt, Crisis, And The Rise Of Hitler Tobias


Straumann

https://textbookfull.com/product/1931-debt-crisis-and-the-rise-
of-hitler-tobias-straumann/

The Roman Republic and the Hellenistic Mediterranean


From Alexander to Caesar Joel W. Allen

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-roman-republic-and-the-
hellenistic-mediterranean-from-alexander-to-caesar-joel-w-allen/

Utilitarianism in the Age of Enlightenment: The Moral


and Political Thought of William Paley Niall O’Flaherty

https://textbookfull.com/product/utilitarianism-in-the-age-of-
enlightenment-the-moral-and-political-thought-of-william-paley-
niall-oflaherty/

Roman Political Thought Jed W. Atkins

https://textbookfull.com/product/roman-political-thought-jed-w-
atkins/
The Intellectual Origins of the Belgian Revolution:
Political Thought and Disunity in the Kingdom of the
Netherlands, 1815-1830 Stefaan Marteel

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-intellectual-origins-of-the-
belgian-revolution-political-thought-and-disunity-in-the-kingdom-
of-the-netherlands-1815-1830-stefaan-marteel/

Diodorus Siculus and the world of the late Roman


republic 1st Edition Diodorus Siculus

https://textbookfull.com/product/diodorus-siculus-and-the-world-
of-the-late-roman-republic-1st-edition-diodorus-siculus/

The dawning of American labor : the New Republic to the


Industrial Age Greenberg

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-dawning-of-american-labor-
the-new-republic-to-the-industrial-age-greenberg/

The Modern Cultural Myth of the Decline and Fall of the


Roman Empire 1st Edition Jonathan Theodore (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-modern-cultural-myth-of-the-
decline-and-fall-of-the-roman-empire-1st-edition-jonathan-
theodore-auth/

Hugo Grotius and the century of revolution, 1613-1718 :


transnational reception in english political thought
1st Edition Barducci

https://textbookfull.com/product/hugo-grotius-and-the-century-of-
revolution-1613-1718-transnational-reception-in-english-
political-thought-1st-edition-barducci/
Crisis and Constitutionalism
Crisis and
Constitutionalism
Roman Political Thought
from the Fall of the Republic
to the Age of Revolution
z
BENJAMIN STR AUMANN

1
1
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide.Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.

Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press


198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.

© Oxford University Press 2016

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in


a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction
rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above.

You must not circulate this work in any other form


and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data


Names: Straumann, Benjamin, author.
Title: Crisis and constitutionalism : Roman political thought from the fall
of the republic to the age of revolution / Benjamin Straumann.
Description: New York, NY : Oxford University Press, 2016. | Includes
bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2015028298 |
ISBN 978–0–19–995092–8 (hardback) | ISBN 978–0–19–995093–5 (e-book)
Subjects: LCSH: Constitutional history—Philosophy. | Roman law—Influence. |
Constitutional history—Rome. | Rome—Politics and government—265–30 b.c.
Republicanism—History. | Political science—Philosophy. |
BISAC: HISTORY / Ancient / Rome.
Classification: LCC K3161 .S767 2016 | DDC 342.37—dc23 LC record available at
http://lccn.loc.gov/2015028298

1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed by Sheridan, USA
In memory of my parents,
Ruth Reichstein (1933–​1989) and Bruno Straumann (1924–​2000)
Contents

Preface and Acknowledgments ix

Introduction: The Fall of the Roman Republic and the Rise


of Constitutional Thought 1

PA RT I: Inchoate Constitutionalism in the Late Roman Republic 23

1. “Not Some Piece of Legislation”: The Roman Concept of Constitution 27


2. Infinite Power? Emergencies and Extraordinary Powers
in Constitutional Argument 63
3. “The Sole Bulwark of Liberty”: Constitutional Rights at Rome 118

PA RT II: A Hierarchy of Laws: Roman Constitutional Theory  147

4. Cicero and the Legitimacy of Political Authority 149


5. Greek vs. Roman Constitutional Thought 191

PA RT III: The Limits of Virtue: The Roman Contribution to


Political Thought 239

6. The Roman Republic as a Constitutional Order from the Principate


to the Renaissance 241
viii Contents

7. Neo-​Roman Interlude: Machiavelli and the Anti-​Constitutional


Tradition 260
8. Jean Bodin and the Fall of the Roman Republic 278
Epilogue: Constitutional Republicanism, the “Cant-​Word” Virtue
and the American Founding 303

Bibliography 343
General Index 373
Index Locorum 403
Preface and Acknowledgments

Those living in political orders that are also constitutional orders tend
to take the ideas developed by Roman constitutional thought for granted.
Constitutionalism, like vaccination, perennially runs the danger of falling vic-
tim to its own success. But, as Roman writers and thinkers of the last century of
the Republic knew all too well, political orders can and do collapse. The crises
and eventual collapse of the Roman Republic were one of the pivotal moments in
European political and intellectual history. How and why did this vast, success-
ful republican political order fail? From Cicero and his contemporaries onward,
this question has attracted the interest of some of the best and most interesting
political thinkers. One influential answer, already put forward by some of the
ancients, was that luxury, corruption, and the loss of virtue were to blame. A very
different answer was lurking in Roman historiography, Polybius, and, more
explicitly, in some of Cicero’s philosophical works: the crises of the late Republic
had been of a constitutional nature and could be solved by constitutional means
alone. The idea of a constitutional order, that is to say, a political order based on
rules and institutions that are themselves not subject to the political process; are
more firmly entrenched than mere legislation; and rest on a normative justifica-
tion that is substantive, not merely procedural—​this idea found resonance in the
history of political thought as a result of, and as an answer to, the crisis of the
Roman Republic.
Roman constitutional thought could build on an inchoate constitutionalism
already implicit in the Roman republican political order and its highly legalized
political negotiations. It was further developed and made explicit in Cicero’s
works, and found a very perceptive audience in all those political thinkers from
the fourteenth century onward who preferred the Roman republican order to the
Empire. The fall of the Roman Republic remained the central point of interest
for thinkers who sought constitutional remedies to problems of political order.
Jean Bodin, usually misunderstood as simply an absolutist thinker, was really a
key exponent of the tradition of Roman political thought emanating from the
x Preface and Acknowledgments

crisis of the Republic, and it was Bodin who established the very Roman terms
through which Montesquieu and the thinkers of the Enlightenment started to
investigate solutions to problems of stability and justice in large modern, i.e.,
commercial, republics. Even thinkers who are not usually thought to argue with
historical examples, such as Hobbes or Locke, can be shown to exhibit features
of the Roman tradition under consideration in the present book. The tension
between those interested primarily in virtue (whether for instrumental-​political
reasons or for its own, eudaemonistic sake), on the one hand, and those focusing
on constitutional ideas, on the other, never went away. Whatever the scholarly
arguments over Rousseau’s legacy eventually yield, there is an obvious overlap in
the Genevan’s attraction to virtue and the commitment, on the part of some of the
French revolutionaries, especially the Mountain, to a doctrine of virtue that had
only contempt for formal institutions and constitutional safeguards. But a sur-
prisingly large number of thinkers who are conventionally thought to be cham-
pions of republican virtue, such as Marchamont Nedham, James Harrington,
Walter Moyle, Trenchard and Gordon, or John Adams turn out to be the heirs
to the influential strand of thought described in this book. For them, Roman
political thought, properly understood, was constitutional thought. A fortiori
this was the case for those, like Bodin, Montesquieu, and the Federalist fram-
ers of the U.S. Constitution, who had never shown too much enthusiasm for,
let alone trust in, virtue.
The title of this book carries some overtones that will be particularly obvi-
ous to those who have been exposed to German-​language scholarship in ancient
and European intellectual history. It responds to, and argues against, however
obliquely, some of the concerns and arguments that have been put forward in
influential monographs by Christian Meier and Reinhart Koselleck. But this is
by no means the main thrust of this book. Rather, I seek here to address a key
topic in ancient history from a fresh angle and to connect it with the reception of
classical antiquity. The reception provides the overarching framework and orien-
tation, notwithstanding the fact that it takes up only one third of the book. This
means that the book is at the same time an attempt to describe a key period in
ancient history and the ideas it engendered as well as an attempt at writing a long-​
term intellectual history of constitutional thought that seeks to close some gaps
and establish bridgeheads between classical antiquity, the Renaissance, and the
Enlightenment. I hope that, rather than falling between several chairs, it will find
audiences in ancient history, ancient philosophy, the history of political thought,
legal history, and among early modernists and even early Americanists. A brief
remark seems in order to explain the relationship between the ideas put forward
in the present study and those explored in a previous book of mine, Roman Law
in the State of Nature, that dealt with Hugo Grotius’ use of Roman law. It was
Preface and Acknowledgments xi

the claim of that earlier book that Grotius, along with other natural lawyers and
some exponents of the Scottish Enlightenment, had drawn very extensively on
Roman law and ethics in his attempt to construct and justify a secular, universal
normative order. Grotius’ was never meant to be a political theory in the narrow
sense, i.e., a theory that dealt with the state, political institutions, and their justi-
fication, although it had, of course, very important ramifications that would bear
directly on political theory more narrowly conceived. Rather, it was supposed to
provide a theory of justice for the state of nature, that is to say, the pre-​or extra-​
political realm. In contrast, the ideas explored in the present book are political
in a narrower sense and stem directly from the crisis and fall of one of the most
historically prominent political orders, the Roman Republic.
This study represents a revised version of my Habilitationsschrift, submitted
to the Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at the University of Zurich in the fall
of 2015. I have incurred a great many debts to many people and institutions while
writing this book. Reading the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia at the University
of Zurich in 1999 under the guidance of Christian Marek in a very small group
that included Victor Walser left a lasting impression and reinforced my interest
in constitutional issues. I owe a huge debt to Peter Garnsey and David Lupher,
who provided very valuable comments on the whole draft. Andrew Lintott and
Jürgen von Ungern-​Sternberg have read and commented upon many chapter
drafts and have been extremely helpful and encouraging. Benedict Kingsbury
has offered unwavering support for my work, and New York University School of
Law has been an intellectually stimulating institution to do research at. The Swiss
National Science Foundation supported this project with a generous Fellowship
for Advanced Researchers, and early on I profited from comments and corre-
spondence with Elizabeth Meyer. Wilfried Nippel’s invitation to a conference
in Helsinki helped to articulate my ideas, and Pasquale Pasquino was an excel-
lent person to talk to about dictatorship and emergency powers. I owe thanks to
Christopher Brooke, Leslie Green, Andrew Lintott, and Fergus Millar for facili-
tating my stay in Oxford in 2009, and I was fortunate that Beat Näf, consistently
supportive of my project, invited me back to Zurich to teach a seminar and give a
series of lectures in 2012, which allowed me further to elaborate my views. Several
chapters were written in the rich libraries of the École française and the American
Academy in Rome in 2013. A meeting of the Association of Ancient Historians in
Erie, Pennsylvania, as well as talks at the Universities of Basel and Bern provided
interested and critical audiences for parts of this book. I would like to thank espe-
cially Ryan Balot, Stefan Rebenich, Alfred Schmid, Sebastian Schmidt-​Hofner,
Thomas Späth, and Lukas Thommen for discussions, criticism, and invitations
to speak. Joy Connolly, Michèle Lowrie, Andrew Monson, Michael Peachin, and
Kaius Tuori shared many of my interests and helped clarify my thoughts at our
xii Preface and Acknowledgments

informal gatherings on Roman political thought and legal history at New York
University’s Department of Classics. Kinch Hoekstra, Martti Koskenniemi, Eric
Nelson, Chris Warren, and Arthur Weststeijn answered questions, gave advice
and offered feedback, and Frederik Vervaet and Tobias Schaffner have been
encouraging and sharp colleagues to correspond with. Daniel Lee very generously
shared the manuscript of his forthcoming book, Popular Sovereignty in Early
Modern Constitutional Thought, with me; my interpretation of Bodin is obvi-
ously indebted to his insights. I should also mention the inspiration provided by
David Dyzenhaus’ work, above and beyond his scholarship on Hobbes cited in
this study. David’s scholarship on the constitutional thought of Weimar has been
an important indirect influence, as was Karl Dietrich Bracher’s work. Needless to
say, none of the scholars named endorses all of my arguments; all remaining errors
are my own. I owe further thanks to my editor, Stefan Vranka, who never ceased
supporting the project. Further thanks are due to the anonymous readers and to
my copy-​editor, Andrew Dyck, whose erudition made this a much better book
than it would otherwise have been. I am grateful for permission to reuse material
previously published as “Constitutional Thought in the Late Roman Republic,”
History of Political Thought 32, 2 (2011): 280–​292.
Anna-​Maria von Lösch and Enzo Franco provided wine, meals, conversa-
tions and companionship in Rome, as did Jascha Preuss, Naomi Wolfensohn,
Ariella and Tani in New York; Thömse, Jane, and Rowan Wolff in Basel; and the
Diems in Aarau. Andreas Gyr’s friendship has been a crucial and longstanding
source of ideas, conversation, support, and exchange. My father Bruno gave me
Leszek Kolakowski’s Main Currents of Marxism for my sixteenth birthday, and
Kolakowski’s engrossing book persuaded me that the history of ideas, properly
done, is where the action is. My dad intuited correctly that intellectual history
was more congenial a field of activity for me than music, where his own inter-
ests and vast talent lay. His taste, unconventional magnanimity, warmth, and
wit cannot be overstated. My mother Ruth was interested in and very supportive
of everything to do with literature and ideas, and my brothers, Till and Patrick,
helped sharpen my argumentative abilities early on. They, together with Adriana,
Élie, Yael, and Abril have constantly provided friendship and sustenance not-
withstanding the geographical distances involved. Eva and the new Bruno are
simply the non plus ultra and the best company conceivable.
New York City, September 28, 2015 Benjamin Straumann
Crisis and Constitutionalism
Introduction
The Fall of the Roman Republic and the Rise
of Constitutional Thought

“Can anyone be so indifferent or lazy that he could fail to want


to know how and thanks to what kind of constitution (τίνι
γένει πολιτείαϛ) almost the entire known world was mastered
and brought under the single rule of the Romans, in less than
fifty-​three years—​an unprecedented event?” (Polybius 1.1.5)
“[T]‌he successes of the Thebans were due not to the composi-
tion of their constitution (ἡ τη̑ϛ πολιτείαϛ σύστασιϛ), but to
the virtue of their leading men (ἡ των̑ προεστώτων ἀνδρων̑
ἀρετή). … We must hold very much the same opinion about
the Athenian state.” (Polybius 6.43.5–​6 .44.1)

The extr aordinary influence of the ancient Republic of Rome has


not been limited to classical antiquity, or to the vast geographical area reached
by its forces. Rome, not Athens, has had the deeper impact on Western political
history both in the province of the history of events and institutions and in the
realm of political and legal ideas. Rome, not Athens, was considered the epitome
of an extraordinarily successful, enduring, stable and free republic. And it was
Rome, not Athens, which gave rise to sustained constitutional thought about the
proper limits of legislative authority and the power of magistrates. In short, in the
subsequent history of Western political thought the Roman Republic, not any of
the Greek poleis, with the exception of Sparta, was considered the proper object of
study for thinking about constitutional government. This extraordinary promi-
nence of Rome in political and legal thought remained until at least the rehabili-
tation of democracy, including Athenian democracy, in the nineteenth century.1

1. For Sparta, see Rawson, Spartan Tradition. For the afterlife of Athens, see Roberts, Athens on
Trial. For a broad survey, see Nippel, Antike oder moderne Freiheit; cf. Straumann, “Review Nippel.”
2 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

Beginning with Polybius, much of the attention paid to the Roman


Republic in the history of political thought has been concerned with the
Republic’s constitutional design. Most importantly from the point of view
of the present study, it was the constitution of the Roman Republic that
became the focal point of a growing body of writing that centered, from the
first century BC onward, on the crisis and downfall of the Republic, describ-
ing the end of the republican order in constitutional terms, the crisis as a
constitutional crisis, and prescribing constitutional remedies. Cicero’s theo-
retical writings as well as his forensic and deliberative oratory breathe this
constitutional spirit and contain much that can only be described as consti-
tutional argument; and Livy’s and other historians’ historiography can be
interpreted as projecting back into the early Republic constitutional debates
about the proper limits of the various powers and authorities contained in
the republican constitution and about the proper application of emergency
powers. It was the crisis of the Republic which sparked constitutional reflec-
tion concerning the precise boundaries between constitutional and extra-​
constitutional violence and authority. What had to be explained, from the
point of view of contemporaries, was the failure of the republican constitu-
tion, and the subsequent constitutional change from Republic to Principate;
and the explanation, for the Romans as well as for much of later Western
political thought, had to be sought in the proper delineation of constitu-
tional powers. Since the debates about the scope of such powers became espe-
cially relevant and heated in the face of real and alleged emergencies, the
constitutional debates centering on emergency powers and extraordinary
competencies will have a central claim on our attention. We will not be con-
cerned, then, with a “republican” interest in the uncorrupted virtue of the
early Republic, but rather with the keen interest in the constitutional crises
and eventual failure of the late Republic.
The distinctive contributions of Roman republican institutions and, most
importantly, Roman republican political and constitutional thought, have
been increasingly obscured by a lumping together of the various contributions
of Greeks and Romans to political thought under the label of “classical repub-
licanism.” Since at least the interwar years there has been a comparable neglect
of specifically Roman political ideas in the scholarly literature on the history of
political thought.2 What has been termed “classical republicanism” by historians

2. See Hammer, Roman Political Thought, ch. 1; Kapust, Republicanism, ch. 1; Hammer,
Roman Political Thought from Cicero, for a very different approach from the one pursued here;
cf. Straumann, “Review Hammer.”
Introduction 3

of political thought, and identified variously and promiscuously with a Platonic


impulse for redistribution, Polybian doctrines of the allegedly mixed constitu-
tion, a Sallustian worry about corruption, and above all with an Aristotelian
concern with virtue, has not been sensitive to Roman specificities and has thus
blunted our conceptual instruments and muddied the waters considerably. With
the important exception of a series of seminal works on republicanism and “neo-​
Roman” theories of the state by Quentin Skinner, Philip Pettit, Maurizio Viroli,
Eric Nelson, and others, “classical republicanism” has often been used as an
overly expansive term under which are subsumed not simply the institutional
realities of the Greek city-​states of Athens, Sparta, and lesser Greek poleis as well
as of Rome, but also the political thought engendered by those commonwealths.
The origins of this lumping together may be found deep in the nineteenth
century, in Benjamin Constant’s famous speech, given 1819 at the Athénée Royal
in Paris, on the “Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns,”
which itself was merely the most prominent and influential outgrowth of a tradi-
tion, starting with Adam Ferguson and the Marquis de Condorcet,3 that would
contrast the liberty of the ancients with the liberty of the moderns, drawing a
sharp distinction between a perceived lack of individual rights in classical antiq-
uity, on the one hand, and the modern conception of rights-​based liberty, on the
other. Constant, who was educated in Edinburgh, was drawing on the distinc-
tion, already embraced by his Scottish predecessors, between the martial polities
of classical antiquity and modern commercial societies. For Constant, this cor-
responded to a distinction between ancient liberty, which really meant political
participation, and modern liberty, which consisted in institutional safeguards
for “individual enjoyments,” i.e., individual rights limiting the reach of govern-
ment. This distinction was to have great impact on historical writing and on
liberal political thought in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, and its influ-
ence can be traced in the works of Fustel de Coulanges, Jacob Burckhardt, Lord
Acton and Max Weber.4 Constant differentiated the picture of classical antiquity
somewhat by noting that Athens, by virtue of its openness to trade, allowed “its
citizens an infinitely greater individual liberty than Sparta or Rome.” However,
this differentiation did not owe anything to Athens’ constitutional features;

3. See Ferguson, Essay, p. 156; Condorcet, Sur l’ instruction publique, p. 47. On Ferguson’s use
of classical antiquity, see McDaniel, Ferguson.
4. See Nippel, Antike oder moderne Freiheit, pp. 201–​221; id., “Antike und moderne Freiheit,”
pp. 49–​68. For the effects of this tradition, see Podoksik, “One Concept.” Constant’s view cor-
responds on some level with the history of ethics put forward by Alasdair MacIntyre: where
Constant saw progress, MacIntyre sees decline and the loss of a pre-​modern virtue ethics. See
MacIntyre, After Virtue.
4 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

constitutionally speaking, the ancient polities were all lumped together, sharing
according to Constant a lack of respect for the independence of individuals, sub-
jecting instead virtually every conceivable action of the individual “to the empire
of the legislator.”5 Constant thus presented a view of the basic unity of the clas-
sical constitutional world and equated the “liberty of the ancients” with “active
and constant participation in collective power,” thereby taxing the ancients as a
whole with having mistaken “the authority of the social body for liberty” and
with subjecting the citizens entirely “in order for the nation to be sovereign.”6
Amongst Constant’s coevals, by contrast, “individuals have rights which society
must respect.”7 This provides a constraint on the “empire of the legislator”—​laws,
although preferable to the arbitrary power of men, must have their limits too.8
Constant was by no means the first to present this monolithic view of clas-
sical antiquity, of course. One could cite Hobbes, to whom all the Greek and
Roman polities were “popular states,” and for whom the liberty described by the
classical authors was not the liberty of “particular men,” but the “Libertie of the
Common-​wealth.”9 Out of this tradition liberal constitutionalism grew, aiming
to safeguard individual rights, chief among them the right to private property.
These safeguards were to be instituted against Constant’s “empire of the legisla-
tor,” whether that legislator be democratic, aristocratic, or monarchic.
In something akin to a new querelle des anciens et des modernes the term “clas-
sical republicanism” has thus been attached to many ancient things and ideas,
usually with a slight bent towards the poleis of ancient Greece. Paul Rahe, an
ancient historian by education, in his magisterial Republics Ancient and Modern
(1992), an extensive essay in comparative politics, arrives at a very Constantian
emphasis on the “depths of the chasm that separates the republics of Greek antiq-
uity from those of recent modernity.”10 Rahe arguably arrives at his Constantian
conclusion by considerably loading the dice, however—​that is, by leaving out
the one ancient republic that might have bridged that chasm: Rome. Although
acknowledging two years later in the introduction to the first volume of the
paperback edition of Republics Ancient and Modern that one cannot “make full
sense of the history of the struggle for self-​government in early modern Europe

5. Constant, “Liberty,” p. 319.


6. Ibid., p. 318.
7. Ibid., p. 321.
8. Ibid., p. 320.
9. Hobbes, Leviathan, vol. 2, ch. 21, p. 332.
10. Rahe, Republics, p. 19.
Introduction 5

without referring to the influence of Roman institutions and law,” and conceding
that a “case can no doubt be made for according priority” to ancient Rome, Rahe
concludes by stating that to “the extent that modern political reflection draws
on and responds to the political thought of the ancient Greeks, Hellas must be
accorded primacy.”11 But this is surely to beg the question, as this “extent” is pre-
cisely what is at issue: to what extent did modern political thought draw on and
respond to the political thought of the ancient Greeks, and to what extent did
it draw on and respond to that of the ancient Romans? Furthermore, might the
deeply antidemocratic character of virtually all of Greek political thought have
had a hand in directing Western political theory towards the example and ideas
of the Roman Republic? And if so, should not Rome be accorded primacy?
While Rahe, avoiding the Roman Republic, presents us with a view of
“republics ancient and modern” so much akin to Constant’s that it represents,
in the words of one critic, a voluminous “reprint”12 of Constant’s slim text, the
prominent ancient historian Fergus Millar has given us what promised to be a
much needed study of the history of the Roman Republic in Western political
thought. In The Roman Republic in Political Thought (2002), Millar attempts a
selective survey of the legacy of the Roman republican constitution from con-
temporary writers up to some very recent works of political theory, discuss-
ing what Aristotle might have said about the Republic, Polybius, later Greek
writers, Machiavelli, Marchamont Nedham, James Harrington, John Milton,
Montesquieu, Rousseau, and the American Founders along the way. Since Millar
is above all concerned with finding traces of his own views on the democratic
character of the Roman Republic, however, and since very few of the writers
he discusses subscribe to such views, his book has a very idiosyncratic flavor to
it—​indeed, Millar’s attempt at explaining why so few thinkers thought of the
Republic as a democracy amounts, as one reviewer has sardonically remarked,
to “Sherlock Holmes’s curious incident of the dog in the night on a very large
scale.”13
The present study might thus be helpfully conceived of as supplementing
Fergus Millar’s as well as Paul Rahe’s important work. As opposed to Millar
I will not be concerned with trying to find resonances of the Republic’s suppos-
edly democratic institutions. Rather, my aim is to give an account of what I take
to be the chief Roman contributions to political thought: constitutionalism,
a concern with both pre-​political and civil rights, and a corresponding idea of

11. Id., The Ancien Régime, p. xxiii.


12. Nippel, Antike oder moderne Freiheit, p. 335 (“Neuauflage”).
13. Zetzel, “Review Millar.”
6 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

political justice that is conspicuously distinct from Greek thinking on the sub-
ject. In the same vein the present work might be thought of as adding Roman
political thought to the Greek examples discussed in Paul Rahe’s Republics
Ancient and Modern. Contrary to Rahe’s “reprint” of Constant, however, I will
try to show how the constitutional crises that attended the fall of the Roman
Republic engendered constitutional thought that exhibited a deep proto-​liberal
concern with Constantian themes such as the limits of legislation and popular
sovereignty. Indeed, one of the most interesting, and most distinguishing, fea-
tures of Roman constitutional thought in the late Republic is its concern with
sovereignty—​its sources, its limits, its institutional locus, and the consequences
of its breakdown. Millar’s emphasis on the democratic element in the late repub-
lican constitution is attractive insofar it gives due attention to Polybius’ inter-
pretation of the constitution—​but Polybius’ own conclusion was of course very
pessimistic,14 and normatively perfectly at odds with Millar’s; Polybius antici-
pated that “when Rome was most democratic, it was also most corrupt.”15
This aspect of Roman constitutional argument becomes particularly salient
in discussions that concern emergency powers: whenever the constitutionality of
states of emergency is at stake, whenever the lawfulness of extraordinary com-
mands, of dictatorships, or of the violation of civil rights is contested, consti-
tutional argument and the underlying constitutional theory try to determine
where sovereignty lies. This will require us to discuss the institution of dictator-
ship, irregular commands (imperia), and attempts to legitimize the violation of
the right of appeal (provocatio).
Constant had associated the revival of classical constitutional ideals with the
period of the Terror after the French Revolution and with the Jacobins’ revival
of Greek and Roman models. With his speech on the “Liberty of the Ancients
Compared with that of the Moderns” he had aimed to curb whatever enthusiasm
was left in post-​Napoleonic times for imitating the republics of antiquity or at
least certain “republican usages” such as Athenian ostracism or the Roman cen-
sorship. The thrust of Constant’s argument thus exhibits very clearly what has
become by now an all too often repeated cliché, namely the dichotomy between
ancient republicanism and liberalism, a dichotomy that was to feature promi-
nently in the historiography of political thought in general and that can also be
profitably demonstrated in the historiography of the American revolutionary
and early republican periods.

14. Polyb. 6.57.9.


15. Zetzel, “Review Millar.”
Introduction 7

The historiography of American political thought has indeed drawn on


the dichotomy between ancient republicanism and liberalism to a considerable
extent, using the two concepts in order to describe the American Founding in
terms of a shift in political thought from classical republicanism to modern liber-
alism. Historians have differed over the question of where to draw the line in the
chronology of late colonial and early American political thought, but the integ-
rity of the concepts has never been called into question. While Bernard Bailyn in
The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (1967) had insisted on a minor
role for classical republicanism in the Founders’ political thought, a role con-
fined to providing an indirect source mediated by the British Whig tradition,16
other historians have followed Gordon Wood in conceding far more weight to
ancient republicanism in the revolutionary period,17 at least up to 1787, when a
“transformation” took place “from a republican to a liberal … culture,”18 where
liberty meant personal or private liberty.19 A few years later, John Pocock fur-
ther extended the importance of the classical republican tradition into the early
national period.20 And as we have seen, in his Republics Ancient and Modern, Paul
Rahe, while acknowledging “a deliberately contrived mixed regime of sorts,”21
between ancient and modern republicanism, in the end remained attached to the
broad dichotomy between “ancient republican” and “modern liberal.”
A similar description can be given of the historiography of republican thought
in general, showing that the dichotomy between classical republicanism and

16. Bailyn, Origins, pp. 22–​54.


17. Wood, Creation, pp. 48–​53.
18. Ibid., p. xii.
19. Ibid., p. 609. Cf. Shalev, Rome Reborn, p. 113, for a distinction between a Southern
“classical” republicanism and a “modernity-​embracing” New England republicanism.
20. Pocock, Machiavellian Moment. For criticism, stressing the importance especially for
Harrington of republican Rome as opposed to “Aristotle’s Greece,” see Fukuda, Sovereignty,
pp. 8, 123–​126; Hexter, “Review Pocock,” pp. 330–​337. Hexter points to the the language of
the liberty and property of Englishmen and situates this kind of “ancient constitutionalism”
in a tradition reaching back to Magna Carta as its “medieval version” (p. 333) and, ultimately,
to a “convergence of Stoic ideals and Roman law practicalities” (p. 332). It is true that this tra-
dition is conceptually close to the Roman one under investigation here, but historically they
are separate; see the differentiation in Appleby, Capitalism, pp. 16–​22, where the American
colonial rebels are said to have first appealed to the rights of Englishmen and then to have
shifted to a more abstract notion of constitutionalism—​one described in this book as inspired
by the fall of the Roman Republic; see Epilogue.
21. Rahe, Republics, p. x. For a salutary corrective of the republican-​liberal distinction, see
Sullivan, Machiavelli. Shalev, Rome Reborn, convincingly shows the debt American revolu-
tionaries owed to the classics, especially in terms of their historical thought.
8 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

modern liberalism is at work here too. Indeed, as Stephen Holmes has noted, “the
history of modern political theory has recently been reconstructed as a running
battle between two supposedly rival traditions: liberalism vs. republicanism.”22
In Quentin Skinner’s work, the battle has been reconfigured as a debate about
whether the constitutional framework of a society has a bearing upon the indi-
vidual liberty of its members, with what Skinner calls the “neo-​Roman theorists”
maintaining that it does, and their critics, such as Thomas Hobbes and later Isaiah
Berlin, that it does not. In Skinner’s account, the republican camp has thus been
broadened and made to include adherents of all sorts of constitutional arrange-
ments short of absolutism, not just republican writers in a strict sense. These
“neo-​Roman theorists”—​among whom Skinner counts Harrington, Machiavelli,
Milton, More, Nedham, Neville, and Sidney—​saw individual liberty as condi-
tioned upon the existence of a “free state,” drawing upon an analogy between
individual freedom as non-​slavery and the freedom of states as not being subject
to tyrannical rule.23
Reinforcing the dichotomy between Hobbes’ and the republican, “neo-​Roman”
conception of liberty Skinner, in Hobbes and Republican Liberty (2008), deepens
his claim that what Hobbes was fundamentally opposing was the view, defended
by certain “Democraticall Gentlemen,” that to live freely is to live in a republic as
opposed to a monarchy—​that to live freely is impossible in a monarchy. Skinner’s
interpretation of Hobbes’ conception of liberty as it appears in Leviathan seems
strained and narrow in giving too much weight to what Hobbes calls “the proper
sense” of liberty, and in neglecting the fact that Hobbes, when talking about the
liberty of subjects, and political liberty, does not seem to adhere to this “proper
sense,” but rather to a view of liberty as consisting in liberty from the “artificial
chains” of laws and covenants—​in liberty from Constant’s “empire of the legisla-
tor,” in short.24
The conception of liberty in Leviathan constrains the sovereign, moreover, in
various ways: subjects are at liberty to disobey the sovereign’s command to abstain
from the use of food, air, medicine, “or any other thing, without which he cannot
live.”25 Subjects are free to refrain from accusing themselves, and are of course free
to exercise self-​defense and defend their own lives against the sovereign absent an

22. Holmes, Passions, p. 28.


23. Skinner, Liberty, passim. See also id., “Negative Liberty,” p. 203.
24. See Gert, “Review Skinner.”
25. Hobbes, Leviathan, vol. 2, chap. 21, p. 336. For a convincing constitutionalist interpreta-
tion of Hobbes, see Dyzenhaus, “Hobbes’ Constitutional Theory”; and see Chapter 7 and the
Epilogue.
Introduction 9

offer of pardon.26 Thus nothing may be interpreted according to Leviathan as the


subject’s consent to giving up these liberties—​indeed, there is a very strong con-
stitutionalist conception of inalienable rights derived from an a priori view of the
state of nature. But while it might be accurate to interpret Hobbes’ conception
of liberty as a rather narrow one, Skinner’s account is much less convincing with
regard to his opposition between the so-​called “neo-​Roman” theorists on the one
hand and liberals “after liberalism,” such as Benjamin Constant, on the other.
It seems that, although deliberately allowing for a wide range of constitutional
make-​ups, the writers he calls “neo-​Roman” are in fact united, not so much by
their fierce resistance to monarchy (as in Hobbes’ caricature of their stance),27
but rather by a commitment to constitutional safeguards limiting the authority
of government. Skinner does mention this aspect briefly, but without paying suf-
ficient attention to it; his “neo-​Roman” theorists, in permitting for “a monarch
to be the ruler of a free state,” surely qualify as proponents of “self-​rule” and lib-
erty only through their commitment to safeguards which deprive the “head of
state … of any power to reduce the body of the commonwealth to a condition
of dependence.”28
But if this is so, what distinctly “neo-​Roman” properties remain? Or, to put
it differently, do not these theorists themselves seem to be subscribing to an
ideal of liberty “after liberalism” after all? In stressing constitutional safeguards
and elevating them to the status of necessary and sufficient conditions of lib-
erty, are these writers not in fact giving up anything distinctly “neo-​Roman” in
favor of the liberal view, shared by Hobbes and Constant, according to which
it is not the “source of the law but its extent”29 that matters? If safeguards are
key, regardless of the precise constitutional structure surrounding them, it would
seem that the distinction between neo-​Roman and liberal collapses, opening up

26. Leviathan, vol. 2, ch. 21, pp. 336–​337.


27. Ibid., vol. 2, chap. 29, pp. 506–​507.
28. Skinner, Liberty, pp. 54–​55. For criticism of Skinner and Pettit’s views, stressing the com-
patibility of Roman republican liberty with a certain amount of paternalism, see Kapust,
“Skinner, Pettit and Livy.” It is noteworthy that Pettit’s stress on “non-​domination” as
the crucial feature of republicanism does give constitutionalism its due; his republicanism
is, however, consequentialist in orientation, unlike the Roman tradition discussed here
(Republicanism, pp. 99–​102). Moreover, Pettit seems to glide from a “Roman,” constitu-
tionalist standard of justice (that verges on collapsing into liberalism) to a Rousseauvian
account where well-​designed democratic processes are sufficient to guarantee freedom as non-​
domination. See Pettit, Republicanism; id., On the People’s Terms. Cf. Dyzenhaus, “Critical
Notice of On the People’s Terms.” Non-​domination resembles at times Hobbesian peace and
security; pace Pettit, it may best be achieved by Hobbesian means.
29. Skinner, Liberty, p. 85. See Hobbes, Leviathan, vol. 2, chap. 21, p. 332.
10 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

once again the gap between liberalism, neo-​Roman or not, and republicanism
of the narrow sort which is concerned with participation, virtue, and self-​rule
rather than constraints on the sovereign authority—​“Athenian republicanism,”
as it were, in keeping with a view of Athens prevalent until at least George Grote
and John Stuart Mill in the nineteenth century. Ironically, the historical and
institutional reality of Athens—​as opposed to the view of Athens propounded
in theoretical and normative texts—​especially from the late fifth century BC
onwards would actually hold much interest for those interested in constitu-
tionalism and its institutions. This has been obscured by the fact that at least
until Grote, interest in Greek history did not extend chronologically beyond
the Arginusae trial, to put it crudely. The Athenian institutions most pertinent
to a history of constitutionalism—​a sort of judicial review (the graphe parano-
mon) and the distinction between higher-​order norms (nomoi) and mere decrees
(psephismata)—​remained thus largely hidden from view for most of the history
of political thought.30 By contrast, Greek political thought (as opposed to con-
stitutional reality) has of course had immense impact over the centuries. The
institutional and historical realities of late republican Rome, on the other hand,
remained much closer to, and indeed provided the impetus for, the specifically
Roman kind of political and constitutional thought that is going to interest us in
the course of this book.
Wherever historians were inclined to draw the distinction, and whatever the
differences between the various scholarly approaches described, a belief in the
basic dichotomy between ancient republicanism and modern liberalism is com-
mon to all of them. The belief seems to rest on two, usually implicit assump-
tions: first, the assumption that there is such a thing as “ancient republicanism,”
i.e., that the various versions of classical republicanism and instances of actual
republics as evidenced by classical literature, philosophy, and historiography can
be said to share a sufficient number of properties to make the unifying concept
meaningful; and second, the assumption that the concept of liberty as based on
individual rights and on constraints on public powers is a distinctly modern idea,
liberty after liberalism as it were, paying less attention to self-​government but
stressing the limits of Constant’s “empire of the legislator.”
Republicanism has been the Roman legacy most emphasized in the histo-
riography of political thought; at times, a certain kind of republicanism has
also influentially been taken to have some normative upshot, as in Quentin
Skinner and Philip Pettit’s work on freedom as non-​domination. This view

30. Except for Hume, who showed interest in these institutions, as we will see in Chapter 5.
Cf. Ostwald, Popular Sovereignty.
Introduction 11

has been criticized, both on normative and on historical grounds.31 My book


seeks to be read as a contribution to that literature, from both an ancient his-
torian’s and an intellectual historian’s point of view, and I hope that it will be
read by historians of political thought as well as by classicists. The legacy of
Roman political thought as stressed in my account is not to be confounded
with that focused on by Skinner and Pettit; rather, it is the Roman contribu-
tion to a specific view of politics that centers on certain rights and norms
achieved and guaranteed by a set of higher-​order constitutional rules, rules
that are understood to have legal character. This I take to be an extremely
influential as well as rather specific outgrowth of the crises of the late Roman
Republic that can profitably be contrasted with Greek political thought. That
the institutional arrangements of the Roman Republic were highly success-
ful and therefore noteworthy is a view that was advanced already in classical
antiquity by the Greek historian Polybius, and it has since had its share of
important adherents, first among them Machiavelli.32 This view, however, is
one that subscribes to a highly pragmatic, if not outright cynical, position on
the criteria for success: Roman imperial expansion was thought to be the chief
achievement of the republican constitutional order. As such it is a rather odd
candidate to serve as a model for the theory of “freedom as non-​domination,”
as Clifford Ando has pointed out. But there has always been another, less
empirically minded interpretation of the constitutional setup of the Roman
Republic, and it is this normative view of the Roman model that will interest
us here.
Due to Benjamin Constant’s ancient-​modern dichotomy, a distinct Roman
constitutional tradition, not to be confused with Skinner’s “neo-Roman” repub-
licanism, has been lost from sight. For us to see it again, it will be necessary to
disassemble the far too broad concept of “ancient republicanism” by paying
close attention to its Roman parts. Much progress has already been made in this
regard in recent years. A certain reorientation, increasingly skeptical of the uni-
fying concept “ancient republicanism” and more sensitive to differentiation, is
already visible in the historiography of political thought. Earlier research that
had assumed “classical republicanism” tout court33 has given way to studies focus-
ing on the substantial differences between Greek and Roman political thought

31. See, e.g., Ando, Law, ch. 5.


32. However, as we will see Polybius, unlike Machiavelli, offers a genuinely normative justifi-
cation for Roman constitutionalism, above and beyond the prudential aspects of his admira-
tion for Rome.
33. See, e.g., Pocock, Machiavellian Moment.
12 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

and institutional legal history.34 Much of the progress was made possible by pay-
ing increased attention to the ancient world itself, to its institutions and its politi-
cal thought, and to the rich literature developed by ancient historians, classicists,
and historians of Greek and Roman philosophy.
Manifestations of this can be found in the work of ancient historians and
classicists who focus on the legacy of classical antiquity in the later history of
political thought, such as that of Peter Garnsey, Fergus Millar, Wilfried Nippel,
Paul Rahe, Elizabeth Rawson, and Jennifer Tolbert Roberts. In tandem with
this development, historians of political thought—​of the so-​called Cambridge
School and beyond—​have been giving increasing attention to the rich and rel-
evant body of scholarship produced by classicists, such as Chaim Wirszubski’s
seminal monograph on Roman libertas, Andrew Lintott’s work on the Roman
republican constitution, Robert Morstein-​Marx’s innovative scholarship on the
contiones of the late Republic, Claude Nicolet’s on Roman citizenship, Wilfried
Nippel’s work on Mischverfassungstheorie or Kurt von Fritz’s book on The Theory
of the Mixed Constitution in Antiquity. Moreover there is a marked tendency, at
least in American academia, for classicists and ancient historians to work not
only on the history of (ancient) political thought, but increasingly on problems in
political theory proper. Examples for this tendency are not hard to find—​Josiah
Ober, Ryan Balot, Kinch Hoekstra, and, most recently, Jed Atkins account for
some of the most interesting and visible scholarship in this regard.
My book seeks to make a contribution to this kind of literature by practic-
ing the history of political thought as the history of the reception of classical
antiquity. I hope that this will be of interest to ancient historians, historians
of political thought, legal historians, early modernists, and political theorists
alike. Furthermore, it is hoped that the ideas, institutions, and historical devel-
opment explored in this study may have something to offer even to those of a
more empirical bent. In the last forty years economists, economic historians, and
political scientists, especially scholars associated with neo-​institutional econom-
ics, have shown a keen interest in the development of institutions and their rele-
vance for the behavior of historical agents.35 Constitutional thought as discussed
in this book is shown to have arisen against the background of late republican

34. See Millar, Roman Republic; Nelson, Greek Tradition; Hammer, Roman Political Thought;
id., Roman Political Thought from Cicero; and Skinner’s and Pettit’s work on republicanism.
35. See North, Institutions; North, Wallis and Weingast, Violence; and North and Weingast,
“Constitutions and Commitment,” for an application of neo-​institutionalism to English
constitutionalism after 1688. Cf. also Acemoglu and Robinson, Nations, pp. 158–​164 for
an account of the institutions of the Roman Republic as “inclusive” and thus providing
economic incentives.
Introduction 13

institutions and politics, but it also testifies to the historically powerful effect of
ideas and to the large body of thought that is presupposed by the constitutional
institutions we inhabit in the West. Constitutionalism as investigated here is,
furthermore, not just one institution among many; rather, it is the basis and fun-
damental framework on which all other institutions rest. Institutions matter, but
they presuppose constitutionalism. Constitutionalism is pivotal, but it presup-
poses a particular political theory. To explain the emergence of Roman consti-
tutional thought against the backdrop of the fall of the late Republic is not to
reduce these constitutional ideas to their historical context. Constitutionalism,
understood as political theory and remedy against republican decline, is not
merely epiphenomenal but can be shown empirically to have acquired causal
force of its own over the long term. Having a normative constitution in the rel-
evant sense is, on the view of the tradition described in this book, a necessary
condition for a political order that is both stable and just.36
As for the set of problems I am setting out to deal with in the present book,
the political ideas on constitutionalism and emergencies arising out of the con-
stitutional crises of the late Roman Republic, and their legacy in the history of
Western political and constitutional thinking, these have not been dealt with
comprehensively or even coherently in the literature.37 On the ancient side of
things, there is no comprehensive scholarly work dealing with the constitutional
history of the late Republic’s various emergency institutions and exceptional
powers.38 One reason for this might be an increased skepticism among schol-
ars towards the effectiveness of legal rules in classical antiquity in general, and
increased interest and sensitivity towards the role of forces other than law in
fostering social cohesion.39 Moreover, ever since Ronald Syme’s path-​breaking
Roman Revolution (1939)40 there has been a strong tendency to describe the devel-
opment from Republic to Principate in terms of the disintegration of the old

36. My thinking about constitutionalism and its importance owes an obvious debt to a body
of scholarship by Jon Elster and Stephen Holmes. See Elster, Ulysses and the Sirens; id., Ulysses
Unbound; Holmes, Passions.
37. For the fall of the Republic, see Bleicken, Geschichte, pp. 242–​246; id., Gedanken;
Bringmann, Krise und Ende, esp. pp. 93–​95; Christ, “Untergang,” esp. pp. 150–​157; id., Krise
und Untergang. See also Beard and Crawford, Rome in the Late Republic; Meier, Res publica
amissa; Deininger, “Zur Kontroverse”; Gruen, Last Generation.
38. But see Nippel, Aufruhr; Lintott, Violence; id., Constitution;Arena, Libertas, pp. 179–​220;
Golden, Crisis Management (cf. Straumann “Review Golden”); Vervaet, High Command, ch. 7.
39. See, e.g., Nippel, Public Order; for a similar view of Athens, see Cohen, Law.
40. Syme famously referred to the republican constitution as “a screen and a sham”: Roman
Revolution, p. 15.
14 Cr isis a n d Const i t u t ion a l ism

nobility and with prosopographical means,41 a tendency that has been comple-
mented, and to a degree superseded, by attempts to describe the institutions of
the Roman Republic—​seemingly inspired by approaches developed in politi-
cal science—​in structural terms by reference to their underlying social forces.42
While few scholars during the last thirty years were prepared to ascribe crucial
causal force to the constitutional makeup of the Roman Republic, and although
some have indeed declared Roman constitutional law a non-​entity,43 an endur-
ing belief in the “centrality of the legal and constitutional machinery at Rome”44
can still be found in relatively recent scholarly work, and Theodor Mommsen’s
Römisches Staatsrecht continues to exert a defining influence on the literature45—​
all the while never having been translated into English.
Indeed, the most provocative and influential recent account of the late
Roman Republic’s constitutional setup that has shaped the debate in the field for
the last twenty years, that of Fergus Millar, has been subjected to severe criticism
precisely due to its alleged adherence to an ideal-​typical, meta-​historical concep-
tual framework in the tradition of nineteenth-​century Begriffsjurisprudenz.46
Karl-​Joachim Hölkeskamp and, with a different emphasis, Martin Jehne have
instead proposed to approach the Roman Republic through a description in
terms of its “political culture,” comprehensively understood, rather than in nar-
rowly legal terms.47 Jochen Bleicken, who in his Lex Publica had discussed and

41. Wiseman, New Men, and Gruen, Last Generation, are best seen in this tradition, which
has emerged out of the early prosopographical works by Drumann and Groebe and the
later contributions especially by Münzer and Gelzer to Paulys Realenzyklopädie; see, e.g.,
Drumann, Geschichte Roms; Münzer, Adelsparteien; id., “Ti. Sempronius Gracchus”; Gelzer,
Pompeius. For important criticism, see Brunt, “Fall”; North, “Politics and Aristocracy.”
42. Meier, Res publica has inspired and influenced research ever since its publication in 1966
and could be described as initiating the program of examining the “political culture,” rather
than the constitution, of the Republic. For the research of the last decades, see Hölkeskamp,
Rekonstruktionen, see for Meier’s impact especially pp. 31–​56.
43. For an ascription of this view to Eduard Fraenkel, see Daube, “Das Selbstverständliche,” p. 10.
44. Lintott, Violence, p. xxvii.
45. On Mommsen’s Staatsrecht and its continuing impact, see the contributions in Nippel and
Seidensticker, Mommsens langer Schatten. Cf. also Grziwotz, Verfassungsbegriff, pp. 25–​284.
46. See especially Millar, Crowd. For criticism of Millar, see Hölkeskamp, Senatus,
pp. 257–​277 (review of Millar, Crowd); id., Reconstructing, pp. 12–​14; Jehne, Demokratie, p. 8.
See also Mouritsen, Plebs. For the role of the contiones, see Morstein-​Marx, Mass Oratory;
see also the important study of elections in late republican Rome by Yakobson, Elections; cf.
Harris, “On Defining.”
47. Hölkeskamp is indebted to Christian Meier’s work. See Hölkeskamp, Rekonstruktionen,
pp. 57–​72; id., “Ein ‘Gegensatz’ ”; Jehne, “Die Volksversammlungen,” pp. 149–​160, with
further references.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
possible to discover the reason, for apparently neither diminution of
temperature nor scarcity of food cause them (the Insects) to suffer.
One is tempted to suppose that the death of the Insects is the result
of a physiological necessity."

Nests of Social Wasps.—In Europe wasps' nests disappear very


soon after they are deserted. As it would appear from de Saussure's
conclusions that in the tropics as well as in the temperate regions the
rule is that the colonies endure only a portion of one year, and that a
new nest is commenced by a single founder once in twelve months,
it is a somewhat remarkable fact that some tropical wasp-nests are
much more durable than the lives of the inhabitants require, so that
solidly constructed nests are often found hanging to the trees long
after they have been deserted, and are sometimes overgrown with
moss. Cuming has recorded the fact that he found in South America
an old wasp-nest that had been taken possession of by swallows.
We do not assign, however, much importance to the views of de
Saussure, because we may anticipate that enquiry will reveal much
variety in the habits of tropical and sub-tropical wasps. It is known
that species exist that store up honey, after the fashion of bees, and
von Ihering has recently shown[41] that in Brazil, species of several
genera form new colonies by swarming, after the manner of bees.
So that it is possible that certain colonies may remain for a long
period in the same nest.

Much more variety exists in wasps' nests than would be supposed


probable; those formed by some of the tropical species of Vespidae
are enveloped in so solid and beautifully constructed an envelope of
papier-maché, that they resist with complete success the torrential
rains of the tropics; while some of those found in our own country are
made of extremely soft and delicate paper, which is probably chiefly
glandular products. Our British Vespidae number only eight species,
all belonging to the one genus Vespa, and yet they exhibit three
different modes of nidification. Vespa vulgaris, V. germanica and V.
rufa form subterranean nests, while V. arborea, V. sylvestris and V.
norvegica suspend their habitations from the branches of trees,
bushes, or strong annual plants. Vespa crabro, the hornet, usually
adopts an intermediate course, forming its nest above ground, but in
a spot where it is protected and concealed. The favourite habitat of
this formidable Insect is the interior of an old tree, but the hornet will
sometimes avail itself of the protection of a thatched roof. Both it and
other arboreal species are said, however, to occasionally make
subterranean nests. It is ascertained that V. austriaca, the eighth
species, is an inquiline.

Fig. 32—Nest of (?) Polybia sp. The envelope partly cut open; o,
entrance. (After de Saussure.)

De Saussure,[42] the monographer of the social wasps, classifies


them according to the architecture of their nests. He establishes
three groups: (1) Stelocyttares, in which the layers of comb are not
connected with the envelope, but are supported by pillars made by
the wasps (Fig. 31); (2) Poecilocyttares, an unsatisfactory group of
which the chief characteristics appear to be that the nest is always
covered by an envelope, and the comb is supported by an object
such as the branch of a tree, round, or on, which the envelope is
placed (Fig. 32); (3) Phragmocyttares, in which the layers of comb
are supported, in part or entirely, by the envelope of the nest,
communication being effected by a hole in each layer of the comb
(Fig. 33). de Saussure's classification is far from satisfactory. There
are many social wasps that construct nests destitute of any proper
envelope; as an example of this, we may mention the species of the
abundant genus Polistes; these Insects make hexagonal cells, of
paper-like material, forming an irregular comb, or mass, attached to
bushes by a stalk near its centre; these nests are placed so that the
mouths of the open cells look downwards. The species of
Ischnogaster (Fig. 34) make layers of comb, connected by a pedicel,
but without any envelope; these Insects form a section of
Stelocyttares called Gymnodomes.

Most of the nests of the Poecilocyttares have only a single layer of


comb. The wasps of the genera Synoeca and Polybia have the habit
of spreading a layer of cells on a leaf, or on the bark of a tree, and of
covering this with an envelope that is pierced by a single orifice only,
but that does not rest on the cells, and so allows circulation of the
Insects between the cells and the envelope. This appears to be the
arrangement in a nest of Synoeca cyanea preserved in the British
Museum; in this construction a large layer of cells is moulded on the
branch of a tree, whose contour, for a length of two or three feet, it
consequently follows; while outside the mass there is placed a
continuous envelope, leaving a considerable distance between it and
the cells.

It would be impossible in the space at our disposal to give a


satisfactory account of all the forms of wasp-nests, and we must
therefore refer the student to de Saussure's work, confining
ourselves to a brief notice of some specially interesting forms. The
habitation of the Brazilian Polybia (Myrapetra) scutellaris is a very
solid, closed structure, covered externally with rough knobs or
angular projections. Although of very large size—it may be upwards
of two feet in length—it is suspended from a branch, and has but one
orifice; the arrangement of the combs in the interior is that of the
Phragmocyttares, they being firmly attached to the outer envelope,
and so placed as to form a curved surface, the convexity of which is
downwards: the number of wasps in a well-developed nest of this
kind must be very great. This species is said to be a honey-gathering
wasp.
One of the best known of the South American wasps' nests is the
construction (Fig. 33) of Chartergus chartarius; these nests are so
regularly shaped, and formed of papier-maché so compact and solid,
as to look like stone: this edifice is attached in a very firm manner to
the branch of a tree, and has a single portal of entry beneath; its
interior arrangement is much like that of Myrapetra scutellaris.

A very remarkable wasp's nest is preserved in the British Museum of


Natural History; it is considered to be the work of Montezumia
dimidiata Sauss. an Eumenid wasp; it is a large mass of cells
encircling the branch of a tree, which therefore projects somewhat
after the manner of an axle through the middle: the cells are very
numerous, and are quite as regular as those of the most perfect of
the combs of bees: the mass is covered with a very thick layer of
paper, the nest having somewhat the external appearance of half a
cocoa-nut of twice the usual size.

Fig. 33—Section of nest of Chartergus chartarius. South America, o,


Entrance. (After de Saussure.)

Apoica pallida, a South American Insect, forms a nest in a somewhat


similar manner to Polistes, but it is covered on its outer aspect by a
beautiful paper skin, so that the nest looks somewhat like a toadstool
of large size attached to the branch of a tree.

The nests of the Insects of the genus Polybia—which we have


already mentioned as located by de Saussure in his unsatisfactory
group Poecilocyttares—usually have somewhat the form and size of
pears or apples suspended to twigs of trees or bushes; these little
habitations consist of masses of cells, wrapped in wasp-paper, in
which there are one or more orifices for ingress and egress. Smith
says that the combs in the nest of P. pygmaea are of the most
exquisite construction, and that it is by no means an uncommon
circumstance to find the outer envelope of the nest ornamented with
patches of delicate hexagonal tracery. This nest is about the size of
an orange.

We have already noticed the variety of nests formed by our British


species of the genus Vespa; in other parts of the world the edifices
formed by species of Vespa attain a very large size. V.
crabroniformis in China, and V. velutina in India, make nests several
feet or even yards in length, inhabited by an enormous number of
individuals; they are apparently constructed of a material like brittle
paper, and are arranged much like the nests of our British hornet, V.
crabro. Vespa orientalis mixes a considerable quantity of earth with
the paper it uses for its constructive efforts. In the British Museum
collection there is a nest said to be that of the Japanese hornet, V.
japonica. This is completely covered by a paper envelope, and has
apparently only a single small orifice for ingress and egress. In the
same collection there is a nest from Bahia (believed to be that of a
social wasp, though of what species is unknown), the outer wall of
which is apparently formed entirely of earth, and is a quarter or half
an inch thick: the comb inside appears also to be formed of clay, the
whole forming an elaborate construction in pottery. One is tempted to
believe it may prove to be the production of a social Eumenid.

Habits of Social Wasps.—We have already briefly noticed the way


in which a colony of wasps is founded, but some further particulars
as to the mode in which the society is increased and developed may
be mentioned. The queen-wasp makes at first only a very small
group of three or four incomplete cells; each cell is at first circular, or
nearly so, and moreover is of smaller diameter than it will afterwards
be. In each of the first three or four incomplete cells an egg is laid,
and more cells are commenced; but as the eggs soon hatch and
produce larvae that grow rapidly, the labours of the queen-wasp are
chiefly directed to feeding the young. At first she supplies them with
saccharine matter, which she procures from flowers or fruits, but
soon gives them a stronger diet of insect meat. This is procured by
chasing living Insects of various kinds. Some species of wasps
prefer particular kinds of Insects, and the hornet is said to be very
fond of the honey-bee, but as a rule Diptera are the prey selected.
When an Insect has been secured, the hard and innutritious parts
are bitten off, and the succulent parts, more especially the thorax
which contains chiefly muscular tissue, are reduced to a pulp by
means of the mandibles; this is offered to the larvae, which are said
to stretch out their heads to the mother to receive the food, after the
manner of nestling birds. When a larva is full grown it spins a cocoon
in the cell and changes to a pupa. It is said by some entomologists
that the queen-wasp closes the cell for the purpose of the larval
metamorphosis; but this is contradicted by others, and is probably
erroneous. In about a month, or a little less, from the time of
deposition of the egg, the perfect Insect is ready for issue, and
almost immediately after leaving its cell it assists in the work that is
going on for the development of the society. The Insects produced at
this early period of the colony are exclusively workers, i.e. imperfect
females. They relieve the queen of the task of supplying the larvae
with food, and she henceforth remains within the nest, being, it is
said, herself fed by her workers; the society now rapidly increases in
numbers, and fresh combs are formed, the upper layer being always
the oldest. About the month of August, cells of larger size than those
that have previously been constructed are formed, and in these
males and perfect females are produced; in a few weeks after this
the colony languishes and becomes extinct. When it is no longer
possible for the enfeebled wasps to carry out their tasks of feeding
the brood, they drag the larvae out of the cells and destroy them. An
uncertain number of queen-wasps seek protected nooks in which to
pass the winter, and each of these queens may be the founder of a
nest in the ensuing spring. It should be remarked that de Saussure
states that all the intermediate grades between perfect and imperfect
females exist, and Marchal's recent observations confirm this. There
is in fact no line of demarcation between worker and queen in the
wasps as there is in the honey-bee. Von Siebold long since drew
attention to the existence of parthenogenesis in certain species of
wasps, and it appears probable that it is of common occurrence.

Our knowledge of the social life of European wasps has recently


been much increased by the observations of two French naturalists,
P. Marchal and C. Janet. The latter has given an elaborate history of
a nest of the hornet, showing the rate and variations of increase in
numbers. His observations on this and other species indicate that
warmth is of the utmost importance to wasps; the Insects themselves
create a considerable amount of heat, so that the temperature of
their abodes is much greater than that of the air. He considers that in
Europe an elevated temperature is essential for the development of
the individual,[43] and that the chief object of the various wrappers of
paper with which the Insects surround their nests is to keep up this
high temperature. These envelopes give a great deal of trouble to
the Insects, for they have to be repeatedly destroyed and reformed,
as the combs they contain increase in size. Marchal's
observations[44] relate chiefly to the production of the sexes and
worker-forms, in the subterranean species, Vespa germanica and V.
vulgaris. The layers of comb include cells of two sizes. The upper
layers, which are the first formed, consist of small cells only: the
lower combs are constructed (at Paris) early in August, and consist
of larger cells from which males and large females are reared. The
males are, however, reared also in large numbers in the small cells.
If the queen be removed, the workers become fertile, and produce
parthenogenetically many eggs, but all of the male sex. He
entertains no doubt that even when the queen is in full vigour the
workers produce males if there is an abundant food supply.

The social wasps at present known number 500 or 600 species.


Polistes is a very extensive genus, and it has also a very wide
geographical distribution; some of the species—and those found in
widely-distant parts of the world—are remarkable on account of their
excessive variation in colour, and it is worthy of note that the extreme
forms have been more than once taken from the same nest.
Next to Polistes, Vespa is the most numerous in species, about 150
being known, and it is to this genus that all our British social wasps
belong. No Insects are better known in our islands than these wasps,
owing to the great numbers of individuals that occur in certain
seasons, as well as to their frequently entering our habitations and
partaking of our food, and to the terror that is occasioned by their
supposed ferocity and desire to sting. This last feature is a complete
mistake; wasps never sting unless they are roused to do so by
attacks, or by considerable interference with their work. The only real
danger arises from the fact that a wasp may be occasionally taken
into the mouth with fruit, or may be handled unawares. When they
are flying about they are perfectly harmless unless attacked or
irritated, and even if they settle on the person no danger of their
stinging exists unless movement is made. Sichel correctly states that
a person may station himself close to a wasp's nest and remain
there without any risk at all, provided that he makes no movement;
indeed, it is more than probable that if no movement, or if only gentle
movement, be made, the wasps are unaware of the presence of an
intruder. It is, however, well ascertained that if they are molested at
their work, more especially when they are actually engaged in the
duties of the nest, they are then extremely vindictive, and follow for a
considerable distance those who have irritated them. The East
Indian V. velutina is specially fierce when aroused, and is said by
Horne to have followed a party through dense jungle for miles, and
on some occasions to have stung animals, and even human beings,
to death.

Fig. 34—Ischnogaster mellyi. Java. A, Female imago (the line at the


side shows its length); B, nest, C, maxilla; D, labium; E, mandible
(tip downwards). The nest is probably upside down, although
shown here as by de Saussure.

This vindictiveness is, however, only an exceptional mood due to


some interference with the colony. Even the hornet, notwithstanding
its threatening appearance, is harmless unless unduly provoked; its
nests and their inhabitants can be kept in domesticity, exhibited to
strangers, even moved from place to place, yet the hornets will not
take offence if due gentleness be observed. It is said that wasps will
rear the progeny of a neighbour in circumstances where this
assistance is necessary. Hess has related a case in which a queen-
hornet had commenced a nest, and was killed by an accident,
leaving young brood in the comb unprovided for: as a result many of
the helpless grubs died, and others were in a state of starvation,
when a strange queen-hornet appeared, associated itself with the
comb, and, adopting the orphan brood, nourished them and brought
them to their full size.

We have already alluded to the fact that, so far as external structure


is concerned, there is no great difference between the social and the
solitary wasps. Both, too, run through analogous series of forms and
colours, and the genus Ischnogaster (Fig. 34) seems to connect the
two groups by both its structure and mode of life. The social habits
are in many species only inferred, and with greater knowledge will
probably prove fallacious as a guide to classification; indeed we
have already said that in the genus Vespa—perhaps the most
perfectly social of all the wasps—there is one species that has no
worker, and that lives, it is supposed, as a parasite, in the nests of its
congeners. For this species, V. austriaca, it has been proposed to
create a separate genus, Pseudovespa, on account of this
peculiarity of habit, although no structural character has been
detected that could distinguish it. De Saussure has stated his
conviction that workers do not exist in some of the exotic genera, so
that it appears highly probable that with the progress of knowledge
the present division between social and solitary wasps will prove
untenable.
Remains of Insects referred to the genera Polistes and Vespa have
been found in tertiary strata in various parts of Europe and in North
America.

Fig. 35—Masaris vespiformis. A, male; B, female. Egypt. (After


Schaum.)

Fam. 3. Masaridae.

Anterior wing with two complete sub-marginal cells. Antennae


usually incrassate or clubbed at the extremity. Claws distinctly or
obsoletely dentate.

This is a group of fifty or sixty species with but few genera, and most
of its components appear to be Insects of the greatest rarity. In their
appearance the Insects of this Family differ considerably from the
other Diploptera, and as the wings are only imperfectly, or not at all,
plicate, it must be admitted that the systematic affinities of the group
require reconsideration. The pronotal structure is, however,
completely that of Diploptera. The typical form of the Family, Masaris
vespiformis, though described a hundred years since, is a species of
such extreme rarity, and its sexes are so different, that entomologists
have only recently been able to agree about it. It has been found in
Egypt and Algeria. The genera Ceramius, Jugurthia, Quartenia and
Coelonites are also members of the Mediterranean fauna, while
Paragia is Australian, and Trimeria South American. Several species
of the genus Masaris inhabit North America, and Cresson has
recently described another Masarid genus from the same country,
under the name of Euparagia.

The little that is known of their natural history is almost limited to an


account given by Giraud of the habits of Ceramius lusitanicus, of
which species he found a colony near Briançon. The Insect makes
nests in the earth; they are entered by means of a chimney-like
passage analogous to what is formed by certain Odynerus; the
gallery when completed is about six centimetres long, and at its
extremity is an earthen cell in which the larva lives; this is fed by the
mother, who brings to it from time to time a supply of a paste,
described as being somewhat like dried honey. The growth of the
larva is believed to be rapid.

Fig. 36—Cells constructed by Coelonites abbreviatus. (After André.)

Some fragmentary observations made by Lichtenstein on Coelonites


abbreviatus have also been recorded. This species, near Montpellier,
constructs earthen cells; they are not, however, subterranean, but
are placed side by side on the dry stems of plants (Fig. 36); these
cells are stored with a material similar to that supplied by Ceramius
lusitanicus to its young.
CHAPTER III

HYMENOPTERA ACULEATA CONTINUED—DIVISION III. FOSSORES OR


FOSSORIAL SOLITARY WASPS—FAMILY SCOLIIDAE OR SUBTERRANEAN
FOSSORS—FAMILY POMPILIDAE OR RUNNERS—FAMILY SPHEGIDAE OR
PERFECT-STINGERS

Division III. Fossores.

Aculeate Hymenoptera, in which the abdomen, though very


diverse in form, does not bear prominences on the upper aspect
of the basal segments; front wing without longitudinal fold along
the middle; hairs of body not plumose. Only two forms (male and
female) of each species.

Fossorial Hymenoptera are distinguished from other Aculeates at


present only by negative characters, i.e. they are Aculeates, but are
not ants, bees or wasps. According to their habits they fall into four,
by no means sharply distinguished, groups—(1) those that form no
special receptacles for their young, but are either of parasitic or sub-
parasitic habits, or take advantage of the abodes of other Insects,
holes, etc.; (2) constructors of cells of clay formed into pottery by the
saliva of the Insect, and by drying; (3) excavators of burrows in the
ground; (4) makers of tunnels in wood or stems of plants. Several
species make use of both of the last two methods. The habits are
carnivorous; the structures formed are not for the benefit of the
makers, but are constructed and stored with food for the next
generation. Their remarkable habits attracted some attention even
2000 years or more ago, and were to some extent observed by
Aristotle. The great variety in the habits of the species, the extreme
industry, skill, and self-denial they display in carrying out their
voluntary labours, render them one of the most instructive groups of
the animal kingdom. There are no social or gregarious forms, they
are true individualists, and their lives and instincts offer many
subjects for reflection. Unlike the social Insects they can learn
nothing whatever from either example or precept. The skill of each
individual is prompted by no imitation. The life is short, the later
stages of the individual life are totally different from the earlier: the
individuals of one generation only in rare cases see even the
commencement of the life of the next; the progeny, for the benefit of
which they labour with unsurpassable skill and industry, being
unknown to them. Were such a solicitude displayed by ourselves we
should connect it with a high sense of duty, and poets and moralists
would vie in its laudation. But having dubbed ourselves the higher
animals, we ascribe the eagerness of the solitary wasp to impulse or
instinct, and we exterminate their numerous species from the face of
the earth for ever, without even seeking to make a prior
acquaintance with them. Meanwhile our economists and moralists
devote their volumes to admiration of the progress of the civilisation
that effects this destruction and tolerates this negligence.

Fig. 37.—Sceliphron nigripes ♀ (Sub-Fam. Sphegides). Amazons. ×


3⁄2.

It should be noted that in the solitary as in the social Insects the


males take no part whatever in these industrial occupations, and
apparently are even unaware of them. It is remarkable that,
notwithstanding this, the sexual differences are in the majority less
than is usual in Insects. It is true that the various forms of Scoliidae
exhibit sexual distinctions which, in the case of Thynnides and
Mutillides are carried to an extreme degree, but these are precisely
the forms in which skill and ingenuity are comparatively absent, the
habits being rather of the parasitic than of the industrial kind, while
the structure is what is usually called degraded (i.e. wingless). The
great difference between the habits of the sexes, coupled with the
fact that there is little or no difference in their appearance, has given
rise to a curious Chinese tradition with regard to these Insects,
dating back to Confucius at least.[45] The habit of stinging and
storing caterpillars in a cell, from which a fly similar to itself
afterwards proceeds having been noticed, it was supposed to be the
male that performed these operations; and that when burying the
caterpillars he addressed to them a spell, the burden of which is
"mimic me." In obedience the caterpillars produce the wasp, which is
called to this day "Jiga," that is in English "mimic me." The idea was
probably to the effect that the male, not being able to produce eggs,
used charmed caterpillars to continue the species.

Summary of the Prey of Fossores.

Group of Fossores. Food or Occurrence.


Fam. Scoliidae.
Sub-Fam. Mutillides As parasites on Hymenoptera
Aculeata.
" Thynnides (?) Parasites on Lepidopterous
pupae.
" Scoliides Larvae of Coleoptera [(?) spiders in
the case of Elis 4-notata].
" Rhopalosomides Unknown.
" Sapygides The provisions stored by bees.
Caterpillars (teste Smith).
Fam. Pompilidae Spiders. Rarely Orthoptera
(Gryllidae and Blattidae, teste
Bingham) or Coleoptera.
Fam. Sphegidae.
Sub-Fam. Sphegides Orthoptera (especially Locustidae),
larvae of Lepidoptera, Spiders [(?)
same species (Sceliphron
madraspatanum and Sphex
coeruleus), both spiders and
caterpillars].
" Ampulicides Orthoptera (Blattidae only).
" Larrides Orthoptera of various divisions.
Aculeate Hymenoptera, in the
case of Palarus. [Spiders stolen
from nests of Pelopaeus by
Larrada.]
" Trypoxylonides Spiders, caterpillars, Aphidae.
" Astatides Astata boops uses Pentatomid
bugs, cockroaches, and even
Aculeate Hymenoptera (Oxybelus,
teste Smith).
" Bembecides Diptera and Cicada.
" Nyssonides Diptera, Homoptera (Gorytes
mystaceus takes Aphrophora out
of its "cuckoo-spit").
" Philanthides Aculeate Hymenoptera
(Philanthus). Hard beetles, viz.
Curculionidae, Buprestidae,
Chrysomelidae (Cerceris).
" Mimesides Small Homoptera, even Aphidae.
Diptera (Tipulidae) in Hawaii.
" Crabronides Diptera, Aphidae [? the same
species of wasps both of these].
Other small Homoptera. Ants (in
the case of Fertonius). Parasitic
Hymenoptera (in the case of
Lindenius).

Great diversity of opinion exists as to the classification of the


Fossores. This arises chiefly from the incomplete state of the
collections studied, and from the fact that the larger part of the works
published are limited to local faunae. Opinions as to the families
vary; some admitting only three or four, others upwards of twenty.
After consideration of the various views, the writer thinks it best to
admit at present only three families, which speaking broadly,
correspond with habits, viz. (1) Scoliidae, subterranean stingers; (2)
Pompilidae, runners; (3) Sphegidae, stingers above ground.

1. Scoliidae. Pronotum and tegulae in contact. Abdomen with the


plane of the ventral surface interrupted by a chink between the
first and second segments. Numerous wingless forms.

2. Pompilidae. Pronotum and tegulae in contact. Abdomen with


the plane of the ventral surface not interrupted by a chink. Legs
very long. No wingless forms.

3. Sphegidae. Pronotum and tegulae not in contact. No wingless


forms.

We shall treat as sub-families those divisions of Scoliidae and


Sphegidae considered by many as families.

Fam. 1. Scoliidae.

The members of this family, so far as is known, display less perfect


instincts than the Sphegidae and Pompilidae, and do not construct
cells or form burrows. Information as to the habits is almost confined
to European forms. We adopt five sub-families.

Sub-Fam. 1. Mutillides.—The sides of the pronotum reach the


tegulae: the female is destitute of wings and ocelli, frequently
having the parts of the thorax so closely soldered that the
divisions between them are obliterated: the males are winged,
furnished with ocelli, and having the thoracic divisions distinct;
intermediate tibiae with two apical spurs. Front wing with two or
three sub-marginal cells. The larvae live parasitically at the
expense of other Hymenoptera Aculeata.
The Mutillides have some resemblance to ants, though, as they are
usually covered with hair, and there is never any node at the base of
the abdomen, they are readily distinguished from the Formicidae.
The great difference between the sexes is their most striking
character. Their system of coloration is often very remarkable, the
velvet-like pubescence clothing their bodies being variegated with
patches of sharply contrasted vivid colour; in other cases the
contrast of colour is due to bare, ivory-like spaces. They have the
faculty of stridulating, the position and nature of the organ for the
purpose being the same as in ants.

Very little exact information exists as to the habits and life-histories of


the species. Christ and Drewsen, forty or fifty years ago, recorded
that M. europaea lives in the nests of bees of the genus Bombus,
and Hoffer has since made some observations on the natural history
of the same species in South East Europe, where this Mutilla is
found in the nests of ten or eleven species of Bombus, being most
abundant in those of B. agrorum and B. variabilis; occasionally more
individuals of Mutilla than of bees may be found in a nest. He
supposes that the egg of the Mutilla is placed in the young larva of
the Bombus, and hatches in about three days; the larva feeds inside
the bee-larva, and when growth is completed a cocoon is spun in the
interior of the pupa-case of the bee. When the perfect Insects
emerge, the males leave the nest very speedily, but the females
remain for some time feeding on the bees' honey. Females are
usually produced in greater numbers than males. This account
leaves much to be desired. From the observations of Radoszkowsky
it is clear that other species of Mutillides are by no means confined
to the nests of Bombus but live at the expense of Aculeate
Hymenoptera of various groups. This naturalist asserts that the basal
abdominal segment of the parasite resembles in form that of the
species on which it preys.

The apterous condition of the females of Mutillides and Thynnides is


very anomalous in the Fossors; this sex being in the other families
distinguished for activity and intelligence. The difference between the
sexes is also highly remarkable. The males differ from the females
by the possession of wings and by the structural characters we have
mentioned, and also in a most striking manner in both colour and
form; Burmeister, indeed, says that in South America—the
metropolis of Mutillides—there is not a single species in which the
males and females are alike in appearance; this difference becomes
in some cases so extreme that the two sexes of one species have
been described as Insects of different families.

Fig. 38—Mutilla stridula. Europe. A, Male; B, female.

Upwards of one thousand species are assigned to the genus Mutilla,


which is distributed over the larger part of the world; there is so much
difference in these species as to the nervuration of the wings in the
males, that several genera would be formed for them were it not that
no corresponding distinctions can be detected in the females. Three
or four species of Mutilla are described as being apterous in the
male as well as in the female sex; they are very rare, and little is
known about them. Only three species of Mutillides occur in Britain,
and they are but rarely seen, except by those who are acquainted
with their habits. The African and East Indian genus, Apterogyna,
includes some extremely peculiar Hymenoptera; the males have the
wing nervuration very much reduced, and the females are very ant-
like owing to the deep constriction behind the first abdominal ring.

Sub-Fam. 2. Thynnides.—Males and females very different in


form; the male winged, the front wing with three, or only two,
sub-marginal cells; the female wingless and with the thorax
divided into three sub-equal parts.
Fig. 39—Methoca ichneumonides. A, Male; B, female. Britain.

The Thynnides are by some entomologists not separated from the


Mutillides; but the distinction in the structure of the thorax of the
females is very striking. In the Thynnides the nervuration of the wing
appears always to extend to the outer margin, and in the Mutillides
not to do so. This family is represented in Britain by a single very
rare Insect, Methoca ichneumonides: to the unskilled observer the
female would appear to be without doubt an ant. This Insect is by
some considered as the type of a family distinct from the Thynnides
proper. Thynnides are numerous in Australia. Very little is really
known as to their habits, though it has been stated that they are
parasitic on Lepidoptera, Bakewell having obtained specimens from
subterranean cocoons of that Order. Those who are interested in
differences between the sexes of one species should examine the
extraordinary examples of that phenomenon presented by the
Thynnides; the dissimilarity throughout the group—which is now of
considerable extent—being so extreme that no entomologist would
from simple inspection believe the two sexes to have any
connection; but the fact that they are so connected has been
demonstrated beyond doubt. In very few cases, however, have the
sexes been matched, so that at present males are no doubt standing
in the lists of Hymenoptera as one species and their females as
other species.

Sub-Fam. 3. Scoliides.—Pronotum reaching back to the


tegulae; legs stout; intermediate tibiae with one apical spur; both
sexes winged; the nervures not extending to the posterior (i.e.
distal) margin.
This group includes some of the largest and most powerful of the
Aculeate Hymenoptera. Its members are usually hairy Insects with
thick legs, the colour being black, more or less variegated with bands
or spots of red or yellow; the hind body is elongate, has only a very
short pedicel, and in the male is usually terminated by three
projecting spines. The pronotum is of variable dimensions, but its
front angles are always co-adapted with the points of insertion of the
front wings. The nervuration of the front wings is confined to the
basal part, the extensive apical or outer area possessing no
nervures. There is frequently a great difference in the size of the two
sexes of the same species, the female being very much larger than
the other sex. The larvae, so far as is known, devour those of
Lamellicorn Coleoptera.

Fig. 40.—Scolia haemorrhoidalis ♀. Europe.

Fabre has investigated the habits of some of the species of Scoliides


found in France, and has informed us that their means of
subsistence consists of larvae of the larger Lamellicorn beetles,
Cetonia, Oryctes, Anoxia, and Euchlora; these beetles belong to
very different divisions of the Lamellicornia, but they have in
common the fact that their larvae are of subterranean habits, living in
the earth or in accumulations of débris in which there is a large
proportion of vegetable matter or roots. The female Scolia
penetrates into the ground in order to find the Lamellicorn larvae
necessary as food for its progeny. Scolia bifasciata attacks the
larvae of several species of Cetonia, and S. (Colpa) interrupta
chooses the larvae of the chafers Anoxia villosa and A. matutinalis.
The mother Scolia enters the ground in August or September, and
having found a suitable larva stings it and deposits an egg on the
ventral surface of the prey; the paralysed larva is left where it was

You might also like