You are on page 1of 3

τ Laudan, δε ε α ε τ α στ ε τα τ ατ α στ ε στ τ τα ε τ α

σε ε φ στ σ ε φ . Η ε στ τ τα, ατα ε τα στα ε τε α


ασατ α δ σ τ Δ τ σ , δε ετα σ α α ετ α ,α ε
αφετ α σ ε ε ε δε α στ α :

Η ε στ ε α δε α σ .
Η τ τα σ , τ στ , ε ε σ δ τ στ τ α τ
ε ε τα ε α δεδ .
Α τ τ τα δε σ στ σ α α ετ α , α τε ε στ
α α τ σ τ α τ ε ε α εα .

τε ε τα α τ ε ε α ε α α τ ε δ . ατ τ Popper, α α τε α σ ε
σ εα τ ε α σε ε ε δ ασ ε , δ αδ τα τ ετα ε τ δ α α
δα ε α στασ . Η α τ τ Popper α τ ε τ ε στ ε στ φετα
α α εταφ σ α σα , στ α στ ετα τ τ α α τ σ τ α εα
(quest for truth). δ α α τ α τ δ , ετ δ α α εταφ σ δ στασ
τ , δ αφα ετα α σε ε ε δ ε : Feyerabend ε ε τ δ τ ε τε τ
α ε τ α, τ α ε δ ε α ε α αφ ε στ τ ε στ α τ ,
α τ α στ τα τ α στ ε στ σ ε α ε ε ε δ α α α.
Α τ ετα, στ Lakatos, δ α ατ ε τα σα α α ε δ αδ ασ α
σα , ε τε τ ατ τ ε α στα ε ε σσ ε α δ α ε δ τ α ε τε
τ ε α στ ετα α ε α τ τ σ τ εφα τ . , α τ Kuhn,
αφ σ τ ατ φα α τ α δε α α τ σ ε ε α φ εσ τε
δ τ α αδε ατ , ε α τ εσ α τ α ατ στασ σ α δ ε στ ε α δ σ
α τ αδ α φ σ τ τ εδ α σ τ ( τ , 1983).

6.9.
. Popper ε σ α ε τ τ τ δ α ε σ τ τα στ ε στ . ε στ τ σε , α τ
Popper, ε τα σ α δε τ δ ε σ , ε ε ε στ τ τ δ α ε σ τ τα ,
δ αδ ε α ε α ατασ ε ασ ε ε τ τ τ στε α ε α δ ατ α δ α ε στ . ε ,
ε στ ε α α δ αστ τ τα, α ε ετα σε α α α ε α (δ τ ε
ε στ τ σε ε α ε φ σε σ ). Η ε στ , ασφα , α ε τ φ α
δ α α ατ α ατ τ τα, ε τ α ε αφα ε α ασ ε δ ε , ε σε α α ε .Η
α α τε δ α τ ε στ , σ α α α ετ τ α ε , ε ατα ε ετα στ ασ
τ σ σ ε α α φ σ φ α τ ε στ .
ε σα ε στ σ ε α στ Kuhn, δε δ ετα τ δ ατ σ ε τ σ . φ α
ε τ δ , ε στ ε ε ετα σε σ α τ α α τ στ α ε ,
α τε ε , δ αδ , α α δ αστ τ τα, α ε τ σσετα σε α σ ε -
στ ασ , τ σ στ α τ α. Kuhn ε σ α ε τ α τ ε στ
α αδε ατ (scientific paradigm), στ σ , « α δε α» δε ε τ δα α τ
α δδ ε στ α . α ε στ α αδε ατα α α α τ α στα τα , ε ,
δε ε σ σσ ε σ σε α τ σ σ σ τ α ε α. Α τ ε δα ε α τ τ α
τ 19 α α ε τ ε στ δε δε δε ετα α δε τ στ σ
ε στ α.
Lakatos σ ε ε τ α δ σ , τ Popper, α ε σ ε τ α τ «ε στ -
ε ε τ α τ ». Α τ τ , Feyerabend α α τ σσε α α α σ αστ α τ ,
ατ α φ σ τε τ ε τ τ τ τα στ ε στ .Ε α τ α τε
α α δ σ α , α, σ αστ α τ ε στ ε ετ σα ε, δ τ
ε ε δ τα α α τ α τ τ τα . φ α ε τ Feyerabend,
α ε ε ατ α αδ σε . ε α σ σ στ α α φ α αα α τ ,
στ σ α ε ε τα αδ , τε ασφα α . τ σ τ τ τα , ε
ε , ε σ ετα α τ α ασ ασ τ σε , α στ ετα στ α τ τα
τ α ε .

150
Davis, J.B. (2007). Economic methodology since Kuhn. In: W.J. Samuels, J.E. Biddle & J.B. Davis (Eds.), A
companion to the history of economic thought (pp. 573-587). Oxford: Wiley.
De Carvalho, E.M. (2013). Kuhn and the rationality of scientific choice. Principia, 17(3), 439-458.
de Jong, W.R., & Betti, A. (2010). The classical model of science: A millennia-old model of scientific
rationality. Synthese, 174(2), 185-203.
Diéguez-Lucena, A. (2006). Why does Laudan's confutation of convergent realism fail? Journal for General
Philosophy of Science, 37(2), 393-403.
Díez, J. (2007). Falsificationism and the structure of theories: The Popper-Kuhn controversy about the
rationality of normal science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 38(3), 543-554.
Dronen, T.S. (2006). Scientific revolution and religious conversion: A closer look at Thomas Kuhn's theory of
paradigm-shift. Method and Theory in the Study of Religion, 18(3), 232-253.
Farrell, R.P. (2001). Feyerabend's metaphysics: Process-realism, or voluntarist-idealism? Journal for General
Philosophy of Science, 32(2), 351-369.
Fawundu, F. (1991). Blaug on Kuhn versus Lakatos and the marginalist revolution. Atlantic Economic
Journal, 19(1), 29-32.
Friedman, M. (2002). Kant, Kuhn, and the rationality of science. Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 171-190.
Garrison, J.W. (1988). Hintikka, Laudan and Newton: An interrogative model of scientific inquiry. Synthese,
74(2), 145-171.
Gattei, S. (2004). Karl Popper's philosophical breakthrough. Philosophy of Science, 71(4), 448-466.
Gholson, B., & Barker, P. (1985). Kuhn, Lakatos, and Laudan: Applications in the history of physics and
psychology. American Psychologist, 40(7), 755-769.
Gorton, W.A. (2006). Karl Popper and the social sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Grobler, A. (1990). Between rationalism and relativism: On Larry Laudan's model of scientific rationality.
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 41(4), 493-507.
Han, H. (2014). Analysing theoretical frameworks of moral education through Lakatos's philosophy of
science. Journal of Moral Education, 43(1), 32-53.
Hart, J. (2011).Terence Hutchison and the introduction of Popper's falsifiability criterion to economics.
Journal of Economic Methodology, 18(4), 409-426.
Hayes, C. (2008). Popper, Hayek and the open society. London: Routledge.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1995). Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on a draft of the structure of
scientific revolutions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 26(3), 353-387.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2002). Paul Feyerabend und Thomas Kuhn. Journal for General Philosophy of
Science, 33(1), 61-83.
Hudelson, R. (1980). Popper's critique of Marx. Philosophical Studies, 37(3), 259-270.
Hyslop-Margison, E.J. (2010). Scientific paradigms and falsification: Kuhn, Popper, and problems in
education research. Educational Policy, 24(5), 815-831.
Jones, G., & Perry, C. (1982). Popper, induction and falsification. Erkenntnis, 18(1), 97-104.
Kashdan, T.B., & Steger, M.F.(2004). Approaching psychological science with Kuhn's eyes. American
Psychologist, 59(4), 272-273.
Kidd, I.J. (2013a). A pluralist challenge to "integrative medicine": Feyerabend and Popper on the cognitive
value of alternative medicine. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C : Studies in History
and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(3), 392-400.
Kidd, I.J. (2013b). Feyerabend on science and education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 47(3), 407-422.

152
Kindi, V. (2005). Should science teaching involve the history of science? An assessment of Kuhn's view.
Science and Education, 14(7-8), 721-731.
Kindi, V., & Arabatzis, T. (2013). Kuhn's the structure of scientific revolutions revisited. London: Routledge.
Kiss, O. (2006). Heuristic, methodology or logic of discovery? Lakatos on patterns of thinking. Perspectives
on Science, 14(3), 302-317.
Knowles, J. (2002). What's really wrong with Laudan's normative naturalism. International Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, 16(2), 171-186.
Larvor, B. (2003). Why did Kuhn's structure of scientific revolutions cause a fuss? Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science Part A, 34(2), 369-390.
Lecocq, X., Demil, B., & Ventura, J. (2010). Business models as a research program in strategic management:
An appraisal based on Lakatos. Management, 13(4), 214-225.
Maia Neto, J. (1993). Feyerabend on the authority of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,
24(4), 687-694.
Maia Neto, J.R. (1991). Feyerabend's scepticism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 22(4), 543-
555.
Malone, M.E. (1993). Kuhn reconstructed: Incommensurability without relativism. Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science, 24(1), 69-93.
McArthur, D. (2007). Laudan, Friedman and the role of the a priori in science. Journal of Philosophical
Research, 32, 169-190.
Michael Akeroyd, F. (1993). Laudan's problem solving model. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
44(4), 785-788.
Munchin, D. (2011). Is theology a science? Paul Feyerabend's anarchic epistemology as challenge test to T. F.
Torrance's scientific theology. Scottish Journal of Theology, 64(4), 439-455.
Naraniecki, A. (2010). Neo-positivist or neo-Kantian? Karl Popper and the Vienna circle. Philosophy, 85(4),
511-530.
Nola, R. (1987). The status of Popper's theory of scientific method. British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 38(4), 441-480.
Oberheim, E. (2005). On the historical origins of the contemporary notion of incommensurability: Paul
Feyerabend's assault on conceptual conservativism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part
A, 36(2), 363-390.
Oberheim, E., & Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2000). Feyerabend's early philosophy. Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science Part A, 31(2), 363-375.
Parvin, P. (2011). The rationalist tradition and the problem of induction: Karl Popper's rejection of
epistemological optimism. History of European Ideas, 37(3), 257-266.
Preston, J.M. (2003). Kuhn, instrumentalism, and the progress of science. Social Epistemology, 17(2-3), 259-
265.
Preston, J. . (1998). Science as supermarket: 'Post-modern' themes in Paul Feyerabend's later philosophy of
science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 29(3), 425-447.
Rowbottom, D.P. (2011a). Kuhn vs. Popper on criticism and dogmatism in science: A resolution at the group
level. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(1), 117-124.
Rowbottom, D.P. (2011b). Popper’s critical rationalism: A philosophical investigation (Routledge Studies in
the Philosophy of Science). London: Routledge.
Rowbottom, D.P. (2013). Kuhn vs. Popper on criticism and dogmatism in science, part II: How to strike the
balance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(2), 161-168.

153

You might also like