You are on page 1of 41

(eBook PDF) Economics for Business

8th Edition by John Sloman


Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebooksecure.com/download/ebook-pdf-economics-for-business-8th-edition-by-
john-sloman/
y; ABOUT THE AUTHORS
Jon Guest Jon is also interested in innovative ways of providing stu-
Jon is a Senior Teaching Fellow at dents with feedback on their work.
Aston Business School and a Teach- 1brough his work as an Associate of the Economics Net-
ing Associate at Warwick Business work,Jon has run sessions on innovative pedagogic practices at
School. He joined Aston University a number of universities and major national events. He is also
in September 2017 having previ- an academic assessor for the Economics Assessment Centres
ously been a Senior Lecturer at run by the Government Economic Service. This involves inter-
Nottingham Business School, a viewing candidates and evaluating their ability to apply eco-
Principal Teaching Fellow at War- nomic reasoning to a range of policy issues. He has also acted as
wick Business School and a Senior an External Examiner for a number of UK universities.
Lecturer Coventry University. The quality of his teaching was formally recognised
Jon has taught on a range of courses including Principles when he became the first Government Economic Service
of Microeconomics, Intermediate Microeconomics, Eco- Approved Tutor in 2005 and won the student nominated
nomic Issues and Behavioural Economics. He has also award from the Economics Network in the same year. Jon
taught economics on various professional courses for the was awarded the prestigious National Teaching Fellowship
Government Economic Service and HM-Treasury. by the Higher Education Academy in 2011.
Jon has worked on developing teaching methods that Jon is a regular contributor and editor of the Economic
promote a more active learning environment in the class- Review and is a co-author of the 1Qth edition of the textbook,
room. In particular, he has published journal articles and Economics. He has published chapters in books on the Eco-
carried out a number of funded research projects on the nomics of Sport and regularly writes cases for the 'Sloman in
impact of games and experiments on student learning. the News' website. He has also published research on the
These include an on-line version of the TV show 'Deal or No self-evaluation skills of undergraduate students.
Deal' and games that involve students acting as buyers and Outside of work Jon is a keen runner and has completed
sellers in the classroom. He has also recently included a the London Marathon. However, he now has to accept that
series of short videos on economics topics and imple- he is slower than both of his teenage sons - Dan and Tom. He
mented elements of the flipped classroom into his teaching. is also a long suffering supporter of Portsmouth Football Club.

Ellz.abeth Jones is a Professor in Studies at Exeter Tutorial College and continues to work as an
the Department of Economics at Examiner in Economics for AQA. She is also a member of the
the University of Warwick. She OCR Consultative Forum and has previously been involved
joined the University of Warwick in reviewing A level syllabi for the main Examining bodies.
in 2012 and was the Deputy Direc- Elizabeth has taught a range of courses including Princi-
tor of Undergraduate Studies for ples of Economics; Economics for Business; Intermediate
2 years. Since 2014, she has been Microeconomics; Economics of Social Policy; Economics of
the Director of Undergraduate Education and Applied Economics. She has won multiple
Studies, with overall responsibility student-nominated awards for teaching at Warwick and
for all Undergraduate Degree pro- Exeter University, winning the Best Lecturer prize at the
grammes within the Economics 2017 Warwick Awards for Teaching Excellence. , where she
Department. She is a Founding and now Alumni Fellow of used her prize money to invest in her development as a
the Warwick International Higher Education Academy and teacher at a conference in Boston. She has a passion for
through this, she has been involved in developing and shar- teaching Economics and particularly enjoys teaching Eco-
ing best practice in teaching and learning within Higher nomics to non-economists and loves interacting with stu-
Education. She was the external panellist for the curriculum dents both inside and outside of the classroom.
review at the London School of Economics, advising on con- Elizabeth has taught on a number of professional courses,
tent, delivery and assessment. with EML Leaming Ltd, where she teaches Economics for
She has previously co-ordinated and taught at the War- Non-economists and Intermediate Microeconomics to the
wick Economics Summer School and has also been involved public sector. She has delivered courses across all govern-
in delivering the Warwick Economics Summer School in ment Departments, including BIS, Department for Trans-
New Delhi, India. Within this, Elizabeth was delivering port, HM-Treasury and the Department for Health. She is
introductory courses in Economics to 16-18 year olds and involved in teaching on the Graduate Development Pro-
has also delivered taster events to schools in Asia about gramme for the new intake of HM Treasury employees twice
studying Economics at University. each year, where she delivers sessions on economics, the
Prior to being at Warwick, Eliz.a.beth was a Lecturer at the role of policy and its implementation.
University of Exeter within the Business School and was in Outside of work, Elizabeth loves any and all sports. She is
this position for 5 years, following the completion of her MSc an avid fan of Formula 1 and tennis and provides ongoing
in Economics. She also taught Alevel Economics and Business support to her father's beloved Kilmarnock FC.
Brief contents

About the authors v


Preface xv
Publisher's acknowledgements xxii

Part A BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS )


1 The business environment and business economics 4
2 Economics and the world of business 16
3 Business organisations 27

Part B BUSINESS AND MARKETS )


4 The working of competitive markets 44
5 Business in a market environment 64

( Part( BACKGROUNDTODEMAND

6 Demand and the consumer 88


7 Behavioural economics of the consumer 111
8 Firms and the consumer 125

Part D BACKGROUND TO SUPPLY )


9 Costs of production 146
10 Revenue and profit 167

Part E SUPPLY: SHORT-RUN DECISION MAKING BY FIRMS

11 Profit maximisation under perfect competition and monopoly 182


12 Profit maximisation under imperfect competition 202
13 Alternative theories of the firm 225
vm BRIEF CONTENTS

( Part F SUPPLY: ALTERNATIVE STRATEGIES

14 An introduction to business strategy 242


15 Growth strategy 257
16 The small-firm sector 277
17 Pricing strategy 290

( Part G THE FIRM IN THE FACTOR MARKET

18 Labour markets, wages and industrial relations 314


19 Investment and the employment of capital 340

( Part H THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN GOVERNMENT AND BUSINESS )


20 Reasons for government intervention in the market 364
21 Government and the firm 390
22 Government and the market 410

( Part I BUSINESS IN THE INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENT )


23 Globalisation and multinational business 443
24 International trade 465
25 Trading blocs 482

( PartJ THE MACROECONOMIC ENVIRONMENT

26 The macroeconomic environment of business 499


27 The balance of payments and exchange rates 537
28 The financial system, money and interest rates 555
29 Busfoess activity, unemployment and inflation 590

Part K MACROECONOMIC POLICY

30 Demand-side policy 626


31 Supply-side policy 651
32 International economic policy 671

Web appendix W:l


Key ideas K:l
Glossary G:l
Index 1:1
Detailed contents

About the authors


Preface xv
v (am BUSINESS AND MARKETS )
Publisher's acknowledgements xxii 4 The working of competitive markets 44
4.1 Business in a competitive market 44
4.2 Demand 47
(llD BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS 4.3 Supply
4.4 Price and output determination
50
53
1 The business environment and business Box4.1 UK house prices 55
economics 4 Box4.2 Stock market prices 58
1.1 The business environment 5 Box4.3 Controlling prices 60
1.2 The structure ofindustry 11 Summary 62
1.3 The determinants of business performance 14 Review questions 62
Box 1.1 A Lidl success story 6
Box 1.2 The biotechnology industry 9 5 Business in a market environment 64
Summary 15
5.1 Price elasticity of demand 65
Review questions 15
5.2 The importance of price elasticity of demand to
business decision making 67
2 Economics and the world of business 16 5.3 Other elasticities 70
2.1 What do economists study? 16 5.4 The time dimension of market adjustment 74
2.2 Business economics: microeconomic choices 18 5.5 Dealing with uncertainty 79
2.3 Business economics: the macroeconomic Box 5.1 The measurement of elasticity 69
environment 22 Box 5.2 Elasticity and the incidence oftax 72
2.4 Techniques of economic analysis 25 Box 5.3 Adjusting to oil price shocks 76
Box2.1 What, how and for whom 20 Box5.4 Bubble, bubble, toil and trouble 80
Box2.2 The opportunity costs of studying economics 22 Summary 83
Box2.3 Looking at macroeconomic data 24 Review questions 84
Summary 25 Additional Part Bcase studies on the Economics for
Review questions 26 Business student website 84
Websites relevant to Part B 85
3 Business organisations 27
3.1 The nature of firms
3.2 The firm as a legal entity
27
30 (mD BACKGROUND TO DEMAND
3.3 The internal organisation ofthe firm 33
6 Demand and the consumer 88
Box3.1 Exploiting asymmetric information 31
Box3.2 Managers, pay and performance 34 6.1 Marginal utility theory 89
Box3.3 The changing nature of business 38 6.2 Demand under conditions of risk and uncertainty 93
Summary 6.3 The characteristics approach to analysing
39
consumer demand 103
Review questions 39
Box6.1 Calculating consumer surplus 91
Additional Part Acase studies on the Economics for
Box6.2 The marginal utility revolution: Jevons,
Business student website 40
Menger, Walras 92
Websites relevant to Part A 40
x DETAILED CONTENTS
Box6.3 Adverse selection in the insurance market 100 Box 10.1 Costs, revenue and profits 171
Box6.4 Dealing with moral hazard and adverse selection 101 Box 10.2 Selling ice cream when I was a student 174
Summary 108 Box 10.3 Monarch's turbulence 175
Review questions 109 Summary 177
Review questions 177
7 Behavioural economics of the consumer 111 Additional Part Dcase studies on the Economics for
7.1 How does behavioural economics differ from Business student website 178
standard theory? 111 Websites relevant to Part D 178
7.2 Framing and the reference point for

~
decisions 115
7.3 Caring about the pay-offs to others
7.4 Government policy to influence behaviour
Box 7.1 Choice overload
120
122
114
[Ill
11 Profit maximisation under perfect
Box 7.2 The endowment effect 116
Box 7.3 The best made plans 118 competition and monopoly 182
Box7.4 Asimple experiment to test for social 11.1 Alternative market structures 182
preferences 121 11. 2Perfect competition 187
Summary 123 11.3 Monopoly 191
Review questions 124 11.4 Potential competition or potential monopoly?
The theory of contestable markets 196
8 Firms and the consumer 125 Box 11.1 Afast food race to the bottom 186
Box 11.2 E-commerce 192
8.1 Estimating demand functions 126
Box 11.3 Premier league football: the Sky is
8.2 Forecasting demand 129
the limit 197
8.3 Product differentiation 132
Box 11.4 'It could be you' 198
8.4 Marketing the product 133
8.5 Advertising 137 Summary 200
Box8.1 The battle of the brands 134 Review questions 200
Box8.2 The use of social media 140
12 Profit maximisation under imperfect
Summary 141
competition 202
Review questions 141
Additional Part Ccase studies on the Economics for 12.1 Monopolistic competition 202
Business student website 142 12.2 Oligopoly 205
Websites relevant to Part C 142 12.3 Game theory 216
Box 12.1 OPEC 208
Box 12.2 Oligopoly and oligopsony 212

(• BACKGROUND TO SUPPLY ) Box 12.3 The prisoners' dilemma


Box 12.4 The Hunger Games
218
222
9 Costs of production 146 Summary 222
9.1 The meaning of costs 146 Review questions 223
9.2 Production in the short run 147
9.3 Costs in the short run 151 13 Alternative theories of the firm 225
9.4 Production in the long run 155 13.1 Problems with traditional theoiy 225
9.5 Costs in the long run 161 13.2 Behavioural economics of the firm 227
Box9.1 Should we ignore sunk costs? 148 13.3 Alternative maximising theories 228
Box9.2 How vulnerable are you? 154 13.4 Multiple aims 234
Box9.3 Lights, camera, action 158 Box 13.1 How firms increase profits by understanding
Box9.4 Minimum efficient scale 162 'irrational' consumers 229
Box9.5 Fashion cycles 164 Box 13.2 In search of long-run profits 231
Summaiy 165 Box 13.3 Stakeholder power 235
Review questions 166 Summary 236
Review questions 237
10 Revenue and profit 167 Additional Part Ecase studies on the Economics for
10.1 Revenue 167 Business student website 237
10.2 Profit maximisation 172 Websites relevant to Part E 238
DETAILED CONTENTS xi

~---
- -----~
THE FIRM IN THE FACTOR MARKET

14 An introduction to business strategy 242


(mD
18 Labour markets, wages and industrial relations 314
14.1 What is strategy? 243 18.1 Market-determined wage rates and employment 314
14.2 Strategic analysis 246 18.2 Power in the Labour market 319
14.3 Strategic choice 251 18.3 Low pay and discrimination 326
14.4 Business strategy in a global economy 253 18.4 The flexible firm and the market for labour 334
14.5 Strategy: evaluation and implementation 255 Box 18.1 What do post, airlines, bins, buses and
Box 14.1 Business strategy the Samsung way 244 universities have in common? 324
Box 14.2 Hybrid strategy 253 Box 18.2 UK tax credits 330
Summary 256 Box 18.3 New ways of working 336
Review questions 256 Summary 338
Review questions 339
15 Growth strategy 257
15.1 Growth and profitability 257 19 Investment and the employment of capital 340
15.2 Constraints on growth 258 19.1 The pricing of capital and capital services 340
15.3 Alternative growth strategies 260 19.2 The demand for and supply of capital services 342
15.4 Internalgrowth 261 19.3 Investment appraisal 344
15.5 External growth through merger 264 19.4 Financing investment 349
15.6 External growth through strategic alliance 269 19.5 The stock market 356
15.7 Explaining external firm growth: a transaction Box 19.1 Investing in roads 346
costs approach 271 Box 19.2 The ratios to measure success 350
Box 15.1 Global merger activity 266 Box 19.3 Financing innovation 354
Box 15.2 How manyfirms does it take to make aniPhone? 272
Summary 359
Box 15.3 The day the world stopped 274
Review questions 359
Summary 276 Additional Part Gcase studies on the Economics for
Review questions 276 Business student website 360
Websites relevant to Part G 360
16 The small-firm sector 277
16.1 Defining the small-firm sector 277
16.2 The surviva~ growth and failure of small businesses
16.3 Government assistance and the small firm
Box 16.1 Capturing global entrepreneurial spirit
282
286
280
[I I THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN
GOVERNMENT AND BUSINESS ]
Box 16.2 Hotel Chocolat 285 20 Reasons for government intervention in the
Summary 289
market 364
Review questions 289 20.1 Markets and the role of government 364
20.2 Types of market failure 365
17 Pricing strategy 290 20.3 Government intervention in the market 376
20.4 The case for less government intervention 381
17.1 Pricing and market structure 291 20.5 Finns and social responsibility 382
17.2 Alternative pricing strategies 292 Box 20.1 Can the market provide adequate protection
17.3 Price discrimination 294 forthe environment? 370
17.4 Multiple product pricing 304 Box 20.2 Acommons solution 375
17.5 Transfer pricing 305 Box 20.3 Deadweight loss from taxes on goods and
17.6 Pricing and the product life cycle 307 services 379
Box 17.1 Online personalised pricing 296 Box 20.4 The body shop 387
Box 17.2 Aquantity discount pricing strategy 300
Summary 388
Box 17.3 Selling goods separately or together?
Review questions 389
The impact of bundling 306
Summary 309
Review questions 309
21 Government and the firm 390
Additional Part F case studies on the Economics For 21.1 Competition policy 390
Business student website 310 21.2 Policies towards research and
Websites Relevant to Part F 310 development (R&D) 399
xii DETAILED CONTENTS

21.3 Policies towards training 401 25 Trading blocs 482


Box 21.1 Expensive chips or are they? 395
25.1 Preferential trading 483
Box 21.2 The R&D scoreboard 402
25. 2 Preferential trading in practice 484
Box 21.3 The apprenticeship Levy 408
25.3 The European Union 486
Summaiy 409 25.4 The UK and Brexit 490
Review questions 409 Box 25.1 Features ofthe European single market 488
Box 25.2 The single market scoreboard 489
22 Government and the market 410 Summaiy 493
Review questions 494
22.1 Environmental policy 410
Additional Part I case studies on the Economics
22.2 Transport policy 423
22.3 Privatisation and regulation
for Business student website 494
430
Websites relevant to Part I 494
Box 22 .1 Astem rebuke about climate change inaction 412
Box 22.2 Trading our way out of climate change 418
Box 22.3 Road pricing in Singapore
Box 22 .4 The right track to reform?
429
432 (mD THE MACRO ECO NO MIC ENVIRONMENT )
Summaiy 436
26 The macroeconomic environment of business 499
Review questions 437
Additional Part Hcase studies on the Economics 26.1 Introduction to the macroeconomic environment 500
for Business student website 438 26.2 Economic volatility and the business cycle 506
Websites relevant to Part H 438 26.3 The circular flow of income 511
26.4 Unemployment 514
26.5 Inflation 520

(Ill BUSINESS IN THE INTERNATIONAL


ENVIRONMENT )
26.6 Long-term economic growth
Box 26.1 Output gaps
Box 26.2 The duration of unemployment
Box 26.3 Output gaps and inflation
526
508
518
524
23 Globalisation and multinational business 443
Box 26.4 The UK's stock of human capital 528
23.1 Globalisation: setting the scene 443
Summaiy 531
23.2 What is a multinational corporation? 446
Review questions 532
23.3 Trends in multinational investment 448
Appendixl: Appendix: Measuring national income
23.4 Why do businesses go multinational? 453
and output 533
23.5 The advantages of MNC investment for the
Summaiy to appendix 536
host state 457
Review questions to appendix 536
23.6 The disadvantages of MNC investment for the
host state 459
23.7 Multinational corporations and developing 27 The balance of payments and exchange rates 537
economies 460 27 .1 The balance of payments account 537
Box 23.1 M&As and greenfield FDI 450 27.2 The exchange rate 541
Box 23 .2 Attracting foreign investment 458 27 .3 Exchange rates and the balance of payments 546
Box 23.3 Grocers go shopping in the Eastern aisle 463 27 .4 Fixed versus floating exchange rates 548
Summaiy 464 Box 27.1 Nominal and real exchange rates 543
Review questions 464 Box 27.2 Dealing in foreign exchange 546
Box 27.3 The importance of intemational financial
movements 547
24 International trade 465 Box 27.4 The euro/dollar see-saw 550
24.1 Trading patterns 465
Summaiy 553
24.2 The advantages of trade 469 Review questions 554
24.3 Arguments for restricting trade 472
24.4 The world trading system and the wro 477
Box 24.1 Strategic trade theoiy 474
28 The financial system, money and interest rates 555
Box 24.2 Giving trade a bad name 476 28.1 The meaning and functions of money 556
Box 24.3 The DOHA development agenda 478 28. 2 The financial system 557
Summaiy 479 28.3 The supply of money 573
Review questions 480 28.4 The demand for money 581
DETAILED CONTENTS xiii

28.5 Equilibrium 583 Box 30.3 The daily operation of monetary policy 641
28.6 Money, aggregate demand and inflation 585 Box 30.4 Quantitative easing 644
Box 28.1 Financial intermediation 558 Box 30.5 Monetary policy in the Eurozone 646
Box 28.2 Growth of ban ks' balance sheets 563 Summary 649
Box 28.3 Residential mortgages and securitisation 566 Review questions 650
Box 28.4 Minsky's financial instability hypothesis 581
Summary 587 31 Supply-side policy 651
Review questions 589
31.1 Supply-side problems 651
31.2 Market-orientated supply-side policies 659
29 Business activity, unemployment and inflation 590 31.3 Interventionist supply-side policies 662
29.1 The simple Keynesian model of business activity 591 31.4 Regional policy 666
29.2 Alternative perspectives on aggregate supply 596 Box 31.1 Measuring labour productivity 654
29.3 Output, unemployment and inflation 601 Box 31.2 Getting intensive with capital 656
29.4 Inflation rate targeting and unemployment 609 Box 31.3 Public funding of apprenticeships 664
29.5 The volatility of private-sector spending 611 Summary 669
Box 29.1 Short-run aggregate supply 599 Review questions 670
Box 29.2 The accelerationist hypothesis 607
Box 29.3 Sentiment and spending 618
32 International economic policy 671
Summary 619
32.1 Global interdependence 671
Review questions 621
32.2 International harmonisation of economic policies 673
Additional Part J case studies on the Economjcs fer
32.3 European economic and monetary union 675
Business student website 622
32.4 Alternative policies fur achieving currency stability 683
Websites relevant to Part J 623
Box 32.1 Trade imbalances in the USA and China 674
Box 32.2 Optimal currency areas 679

(mD MACROECONOMIC POLICY ) Box 32.3 The Tobin tax


Summary
686
688
30 Demand-side policy 626 Review questions 689
Additional Part Kcase studies on the Economjcs fer
30.1 Fiscal policy and the public finances 626 Business student website 689
30.2 The use of fiscal policy 631
Websites relevant to Part K 690
30.3 Monetary policy 637
30.4 Attitudes towards demand management 643 Web appendix W:1
Box 30.1 The financial crisis and UK fiscal policy 632 Keyjdeas K:1
Box 30.2 The evolving fiscal frameworks in the
Glossary G:1
European Union 634
Index I: 1
Preface

( TO THE STUDENT )
If you are studying economics on a business degree or develop a toolkit of concepts that can be used in a host of
diploma, then this book is written for you. Although we different contexts.
cover all the major principles of economics, the focus Summaries are given at the end of each chapter, with
throughout is on the world of business. For this reason, we points numbered according to the section in which they
also cover several topics that do not appear in traditional appear. These summaries should help you in reviewing the
economics textbooks. material you have covered and in revising for exams. Each
As well as making considerable use of business examples chapter finishes with a series of questions. These can be
throughout the text, we have included many case studies used to check your understanding of the chapter and help
(in boxes). These illustrate how economics can be used to you to see how its material can be applied to various busi-
understand particular business problems or aspects of the ness problems. References to various useful websites are
business environment. Many of these case studies cover listed at the end of each Part of the book.
issues that you are likely to read about in the newspapers. The book also has a blog, The Sloman &onomics News Site,
Some cover general business issues; others look at specific with frequent postings by the authors. The blog discusses
companies. Nearly all of them cover topical issues, includ- topical issues, links to relevant articles, videos and data and
ing the rise of online business, the video gaming market, asks questions for you to think about.
entrepreneurship, the social responsibility of business, the There is also an open-access student website. This com-
effects of business activity on the environment, competi- panion website contains 154 additional case studies, answers
tion and growth strategy, mergers and takeovers, executive to 'Pause for thought' questions, animations of key models
pay, the banking crisis of the late 2000s, the sluggish recov- in the book with audio explanations suitable for playing on
ery from recession, quantitative easing, the role of global a smart phone, tablet or computer, a set of videoed inter-
trade, increased competition from newly industrialised views with business people about decision making and
countries and the effects of Brexit. the relevance of economics to their businesses, hotlinks to
The style of writing is direct and straightforward, with 285 websites, plus other materials to improve your under-
short paragraphs to aid rapid comprehension. There are also standing of concepts and techniques used in economics.
questions interspersed throughout the text in 'Pause for We hope that, in using this book, you will share some of
thought' panels. These encourage you to reflect on what our fascination for economics. It is a subject that is highly
you are learning and to see how the various ideas and theo- relevant to the world in which we live. And it is a world
ries relate to different issues. Definitions of all key terms are where many of our needs are served by business - whether
given in definition boxes, with defined terms appearing in as employers or as producers of the goods and services we
bold. Also, we have highlighted 44 'Key ideas', which are buy. After graduating, you will probably take up employ-
fundamental to 'thinking like an economist'. We refer back ment in business. A thorough grounding in economic prin-
to these every time they recur in the book. This helps you to ciples should prove invaluable in the business decisions you
see how the subject ties together, and also helps you to may well have to make.
xvi PREFACE

( TO LECTURERS AND TUTORS )


The aim of this book is to provide a course in economic prin- single lecture or dass. Each chapter finishes with a summary
ciples as they apply to the business environment. It is and review questions, which can be used for seminars or
designed to be used by first-year undergraduates on business discussion sessions.
studies degrees and diplomas where economics is taught The chapters are grouped into 11 Parts:
from the business perspective. It is also suitable for students
• Part A Business and economics (Chapters 1-3) estab-
studying economics on postgraduate courses in manage-
lishes the place of business within the economy and the
ment, including the MBA, and various professional courses.
relevance of economics to business decision making.
Being essentially a book on economics, we cover all the
• Part B Business and markets (Chapters 4 and 5) looks at
major topics found in standard economics texts - indeed,
the operation of markets. It covers supply and demand
some of the material in the principle sections is drawn
analysis and examines the importance of the concept of
directly from Economics (10th edition). But, in addition,
elasticity for business decisions.
there are several specialist business chapters and sections to
• Part C Background to demand (Chapters 6-8) considers
build upon and enliven the subject for business studies stu-
the consumer - how consumer behaviour can be pre-
dents. These have been fully updated and revised for this
dicted and how, via advertising and marketing, con-
new edition. The following are some examples of these
sumer demand can be influenced.
additional topics:
• Part D Background to supply (Chapters 9 and 10) focuses
• The business environment on the relationship between the quantity that businesses
• Business organisations produce and their costs, revenue and profits.
• Characteristics theory • Part ESupply: short-run decision making by firms (Chap-
• Consumer behaviour and behavioural economics ters 11-13) presents the traditional analysis of market
• Advertising and marketing of products structures and the implications that such structures have
• Business strategy for business conduct and performance. Part E finishes
• Alternative aims of firms (Chapter 13) by considering various alternative theories
• Behavioural analysis of firms of the firm to that of short-run profit maximisation.
• Growth strategy • Part F Supply: alternative strategies (Chapters 14-17)
• Strategic alliances and various other forms of co-operation starts by looking at business strategy. It also examines
between firms how businesses attempt to grow and how size can influ-
• The small-firm sector ence business actions. It finishes by considering why
• Pricing in practice, including topics such as mark-up pricing strategies differ from one firm to another and
pricing, an extended analysis of first-, second- and how these strategies are influenced by the market condi-
third-degree price discrimination in various contexts, tions in which firms operate.
multiple product pricing, transfer pricing and pricing • Part G The firm in the factor market (Chapters 18 and 19)
over the product life cycle focuses on the market for labour and the market for cap-
• Government and the firm, including policies towards ital. It examines what determines the factor proportions
research and development (R&D) and policies towards that firms use and how factor prices are determined.
training • Part H The relationship between government and busi-
• Government and the market, including environmental ness (Chapters 20-22) establishes the theoretical ratio-
policy and transport policy nale behind government intervention in the economy,
• Financial markets and the funding of business and then assesses the relationship between the govern-
investment ment and the individual firm and the government and
• The financial well-being of firms, households and gov- the market.
ernments and its impact on the business environment • Part I Business in the international environment
• The multinational corporation (Chapters 23-25) starts by examining the process of
• Globalisation and business globalisation and the growth of the multinational busi-
• Trading blocs and their development ness. It then turns to international trade and the bene-
• Monetary union, the future of the Eurozone and impli- fits that accrue from it. It also examines the issue of
cations for business protection and international moves to advance free
• The impact of Brexit on business trade. Finally, it examines the expansion of regional
trading agreements.
The text is split into 32 chapters. Each chapter is kept • Part J The macroeconomic environment (Chapters 26-
relatively short to enable the material to be covered in a 29) considers the macroeconomic framework in which
PREFACE xvii
firms operate. We focus on the principal macroeconomic • economic analysis and debate has been strengthened and
variables, investigate the role of money in the economy, revised at various points in the book in the light of eco-
and briefly outline the theoretical models underpinning nomic events and developments in economic thinking;
the relationships between these variables. • building on the revisions in previous editions, we have
• Part K Macroeconomic policy (Chapters 30-32) exam- enhanced further our discussion around behavioural
ines the mechanics of government intervention at a economics. In particular, we have expanded our treat-
macro level as well as its impact on business and its ment of consumer demand in a new chapter (Chapter 7).
potential benefits and drawbacks. Demand-side and sup- This has allowed us to explore in more detail the tradi-
ply-side policy and economic policy co-ordination tional economics treatment of the 'rational consumer'
between countries are all considered. alongside insights from behavioural economics;
• we have extended the analysis throughout the book on
the issues of globalisation and financialisation;
Extensive revision • the text provides extensive coverage of the recent devel-
opments in money and banking and their impact on the
As with previous editions, the eighth edition of Economics
economy;
for Business contains a great deal of applied material. Conse-
• all policy sections have been thoroughly revised to
quently, there have been considerable revisions from the
reflect the changes that have taken place since the last
previous editions to reflect contemporary issues, debates
edition. This includes an analysis of the implications of
and policy interventions. Specifically, you will find that:
the Brexit vote and also of the Trump administration's
• many of the boxes are new or extensively revised; policies in several parts of the book;
• there are many new examples given in the text; • most importantly, every part of the book has been care-
• all tables and charts have been updated, as have factual fully considered and, if necessary, redrafted, to ensure
references in the text; both maximum clarity and contemporary relevance.

( SPECIAL FEATURES )
The book contains the following special features: active one. Answers to these questions appear on the
student website.
• A direct and straightforward written style, with short • Highlighted technical terms, all of which are clearly
paragraphs to aid rapid comprehension. The constant defined in definition panels on the page on which they
aim is to provide maximum clarity. appear. This feature has proved very popular in previous
• Attractive full-colour design. The careful and consistent editions and is especially useful for students when
use of colour and shading makes the text more attractive revising.
to students and easier to use by giving clear signals as to • A comprehensive glossary of all technical terms.
the book's structure. • Additional applied material can be found in the boxes
• Double-page opening spreads for each of the 11 Parts of within each chapter. The extensive use of applied mate-
the book. These contain an introduction to the material rial makes learning much more interesting for students
covered and an article from the Finandal Times on one of and helps to bring the subject alive. This is particularly
the topics. important for business students who need to relate eco-
• Key ideas highlighted and explained where they first nomic theory to their other subjects and to the world of
appear. There are 44 of these ideas, which are fundamen- business generally. The boxes are current and include
tal to the study of economics. Students can see them discussion of a range of companies and business topics.
recurring throughout the book, and an icon appears in They are ideal for use as case studies in class. Answers to
the margin to refer back to the page where the idea first the questions in boxes can be found on the lecturer web-
appears. Showing how ideas can be used in a variety of site, which lecturers can make available to students, if
contexts helps students to 'think like an economist' and they choose.
to relate the different parts of the subject. All 44 Key ideas • Boxes containing questions allowing students to assess
are defined in a special section at the end of the book. their own understanding. New to this edition, each box
• 'Pause for thought' questions integrated throughout the contains an activity designed to develop important skills
text. These encourage students to reflect on what they around research, data analysis and the communication
have just read and make the learning process a more of economic ideas and principles. These skills are not
xvm PREFACE

only of use to students while at university but also in the • A series of review questions concluding each chapter to
world of work. They are frequently identified by employ- test students' understanding of the chapter's salient
ers as being especially valuable. Hence, undertaking the points. These questions can be used for seminars or as set
activities in the boxes helps students to increase their work to be completed in the students' own time. Again,
employability. answers are available on the lecturer website.
• Additional case studies with questions appearing on the • References at the end of each Part to a list of relevant
student website are referred to at the end of each Part. websites, details of which can be found in the Web
Again, they can be used for class, with answers available appendix at the end of the book. You can access any of
on the lecturer website, which can be distributed to stu- these sites easily from the book's own website (at www.
dents, if lecturers choose to do so. pearsonblog.campaignserver.co. uk/). When you enter
• Detailed summaries appear at the end of each chapter the site, click on 'Hotlinks'. You will find all the sites
with the points nwnbered by the chapter section in from the Web appendix listed. Click on the one you
which they are made. These allow students not only to want and the 'hotlink' will take you straight to it.
check their comprehension of the chapter's contents, • A comprehensive index, including reference to all
but also to get a clear overview of the material they have defined terms. 'This enables students to look up a defini-
been studying. tion as required and to see it used in context.

( SUPPLEMENTS )
Blog Additional resources for Lecturers
Visit the book's blog, The Sloman Economics News Site, at and tutors
www.pearsonblog.campaignserver.co.uk/. This refers to There are many additional resources for lecturers and tutors
topical issues in economics and relates them to particular that can be downloaded from the Lecturer Resources sec-
chapters in the book. There are frequent postings by the tion of the book's website atwww.pearsoned.co.uk/sloman.
authors, with each one providing an introduction to the These have been thoroughly revised for the eighth edition.
topic, and then links to relevant articles, videos, podcasts, These include:
data and official documents, and then questions which
students and lecturers will find relevant for homework or • PowerPoint" slide shows in full colour for use with a data
class discussion. projector in lectures and classes. These can also be made
available to students by loading them on to a local net-
work. There are several types of slideshows:
Student website - All figures from the book and most of the tables. Each
There is an open-access companion website for students figure is built up in a logical sequence, thereby allow-
with a large range of other resources, including: ing lecturers to show them in lectures in an animated
form. There is also a non-animated version suitable
• animations of key models with audio explanations. These for printing or for display on an OHP or visualiser.
'audio animations' can be watched online or downloaded - Customisable lecture slideshows. There is one for each
to a computer, MP4 player, smart phone, etc; chapter of the book. Each one can be easily edited,
• links to the Sloman Economics News Site blog, chapter by with points added, deleted or moved, so as to suit
chapter, with news items added several times each particular lectures. A consistent use of colour is made
month, with introductions, links to newspaper and other to show how the points tie together. It is not intended
articles and to relevant data, questions for use in class or that all the material is covered in a single lecture; you
for private study, and references to chapters in the book. can break at any point. It is just convenient to organ-
You can search the extensive archive by chapter or ise them by chapter. They come in various versions:
keyword; • Lecture slideshows with integrated diagrams.
• 154 case studies with questions for self-study, ordered These include animated diagrams, charts and
Part-by-Part and referred to in the text; tables at the appropriate points.
• updated list of 285 hotlinks to sites of use for economics; • Lecture slideshows with integrated diagrams and
• answers to all in-chapter (Pause for thought) questions; questions. These are like the above but also in-
• videoed interviews with a number of business people, clude multiple-choice questions, allowing lectures
where they discuss business decision making and the to become more interactive. They can be used with
relevance of economic concepts to them. or without an audience response system (ARS).
PREFACE xix
A special ARS version is available for TumingPoint" lecture theatre or large classroom. Suggestions for use are
and is ready to use with appropriate 'dickers' or given in an accompanying file. Answers to all workshops
with smartphones, tablets or laptops. are given in separate Word" files.
• Lecture plans without the diagrams. These allow • Teaching/learning case studies. There are 20 of these.
you to construct your own diagrams on the black- They examine various approaches to teaching introduc-
board, whiteboard or visualiser or to use pre-pre- tory economics and ways to improve student learning of
pared ones on a visualiser or OHP. introductory economics.
• Case studies. These, also available on the student com- • Answers to all end-of-chapter questions, Pause for
panion website, can be reproduced and used for class- thought questions, questions in boxes, questions in the
room exercises or for student assignments. Answers are case studies on the student website and to the 24 work-
also provided (not available on the student site). shops. They have been completely revised with new
• Workshops. There are 24 of these, each one covering one hyperlinks where appropriate.
or more chapters. They are in Word" and can be repro- The following two pages show in diagrammatic form all
duced for use with large groups (up to 200 students) in a the student and lecturer resources.

( ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS )
As with previous editions, we've had great support from the embedded in this eighth edition and, for that, we once
team at Pearson, including Catherine Yates, Carole Drum- more offer a huge thank you.
mond and NataliaJaszczuk. We'd like to thank all of them our families have also been remarkably tolerant and
for their hard work and encouragement. Thanks, too, to the supportive throughout the writing of this new edition.
many users of the book who have given us feedback. We Thanks especially to Alison, Pat, Helen, Elizabeth, Douglas
always value their comments. Please continue to send us and Harriet, who all seem to have perfected a subtle blend of
your views. encouragement, humour, patience and tolerance.
Kevin Hinde and Mark Sutcliffe, co-authors with John
on previous editions, have moved on to new ventures. f ohn, Dean, Elizabeth and f on
However, many of their wise words and ideas are still
)C
)C

-g

"'~
m

n
m

Student resources

I
Student website
(open access)

News Chapter
blog site resources

Current news Podcasts Links to Animated


articles with ........ on topical news articles -- models with
questions news items by chapter audio (iPod)

News archive Hotlinks Videos of


searchable by
chap or month --- to over
285 sites
Case studies
(154) -- business
interviews

Hotlinks to Answers to pause


news and
data sources
-- for thought
questions
I Lecturer resources I
I
I I I

PowerPoint Economic Word


files experiments f iles

I
I

--
Teaching/ Student
Figures and Models Lecture
learning case studies
tables (animated) slide shows
case studies (154)

I I
I I I I I
Non-animated Non-animated

-
Animated Animated Answers to
for OHTs Workshops
in full colour for OHTs in full colour case study
or printing (24)
for projection or printing for projection questions

I
I I

With Without Answers t o


questions questions workshops

I
I I
- -
Audience Plain (for
response show of
system hands. etc.)

_J_~"l
I I

.l... - _L _ -
Box
Turning Point Poll everywhere
version version uest ions

-a
;;g
rn
"T1

n>
rn

S.
Publisher's acknowledgements

Text increase in vans' By Michael Pooler © The Financial Times


Limited 2015. All Rights Reserved. 87 Crown copyright:
2 The Financial Times limited: Comish, C. (2018) 'Deliv- Philip Collins (2009) Chairman of the Office of Fair Trad-
eroo's speedy expansion belies tricky time for sector', Finan- ing, Preserving and Restoring Trust and Confidence in Mar-
cial Times, 30 April. ©The Financial Times Limited 2018. All kets. Keynote address to the British Institute of International
Rights Reserved. 3 The Financial Times limited: John Kay, and Comparative Law at the Ninth Annual Trans-Atlantic
'Everyday economics makes for good fun at parties', Finan- Antitrust Dialogue, 30 April, www.oft.gov.uk/shared_oft/
cial Times, 2 May 2006 6 BBC: Jamie Robertson, 'Lldl aims to speeches/2009/spe0809.pdf 117 American Marketing
shake off budget image with London stores'; BBC News Association: Brian Wasink, Robert J. Kent and Stephen J.
(10 September 2015) 6 lidl: https://www.lidl.eo.uk/en/ Hoch, 'An anchoring and adjustment model of purchase
Grocer-of-the-Year-Award-3488.htm 9 Independent Digi- quantity decisions', Journal of Marketing Research, vol. 35
tal News &Media:James Thompson, 'Lidl and Aldi see sales (February 1998), pp. 71-81119 Financial Conduct Author-
soar amid economic downturn', Independent (24 June 2008) ity: Financial Conduct Authority 122 Guardian News and
34 The Financial Ti.mes Limited: How paying chief execu- Media Limited: Richard Reeves, 'Why a nudge from the
tives less can help corporate performance Feb 12, 2017 © state beats a slap', Observer (20 July 2008) 134 The Nielsen
The Financial Times Limited. 34 Independent Digital Company (US), LLC.: The Nilesen Company, The rise and
News &: Media: Zlata Rodionova, 'Link between high exec- rise again of private label, 2018 137 John Wiley&: Sons:
utive pay and performance "negligible", study finds'; Inde- From H.A. Lipson andJ.R. Darling, Introduction to Market-
pendent (28 December 2016) 35 MSCI Inc.: Ric Marshall and ing: An Administrative Approach Qohn Wiley&: Sons, Inc.,
Linda-Eling Lee, Are CEOs paid for performance, MSC! Ouly 1971). 138 WARC/Advertising Association: Based on
2016) 35 The Financial Times Limited: Brian Groom, Adspend database takeaway tables (WARC/Advertising
'Executive pay: The trickle-up effect', Financial Times (27 Association, 2018) 144 The Financial Times Limited: 'US
July 2011) 35 Reuters: Many UK CEOs earn more in three airline stocks tumble after warnings of higher fuel costs' By
days than a typical worker does in a year', Reuters (3 January Patti Waldmeir and Pan Kwan Yuk © The Financial Times
2018) 38 European Union: European Commission, Direc- Limited 2018. All Rights Reserved. 145 The Financial
torate-General for Enterprise, Innovation Management and Times Limited: 'UK steel hit by perfect storm of falling
the Knowledge-Driven Economy (ECSC-EC-EAEC Brussels- prices and high costs', Financial Times, 29 September 2015
Luxembourg, 2004). 42 The Financial Times limited: 158 Professor Michael E Porter: M.E. Porter and C.H.M.
'Computerised trading drives up New York cocoa price' By Ketels, 'UK competitiveness: moving to the next stage, DTI
Emiko Terazono © The Financial Times Limited 2018. All and ESRC' (May 2003), p. 5. 176 Independent Digital
Rights Reserved. 43 Harvard Business Publishing: Donald News &: Media: Simon Galder, 'Monarch airlines goes into
Sull, 'How to survive in turbulent markets', Harvard Business administration: what went wrong?', Independent (1 October
Review, February 2009, p. 80 61 BMJ Publishing Group Ltd: 2017) 176 Business Insider Inc.: Will Martin, 'What
Sadie Boniface, Jack W. Scannell and Sally Marlow, 'Evi- brought down Monarch, the UK's biggest ever airline col-
dence for the effectiveness of minimum pricing of alcohol: lapse?', Business Insider (3 October 2017) 180 The Financial
a systematic review and assessment using the Bradford Hill Times Limited: 'Eliminating competition in order to protect
Criteria for causality, BMJ Journal, Volume 7, Issue 5 (6 June itFT View', Finandal Times, 30 April 2018, © The Financial
2017) 71 World Health Organization: Estimating Price Times 2018. All Rights Reserved. 181 The Finandal Ti.mes
and Income Elasticity of Demand, World Health Organisa- limited: 'Supermarket price war moves upmarket', Financial
tion (2015) 80 Investopedia, LLC: Elvis Picardo, 'Five of the Times, 25 June 2015. © The Financial Times Limited. 186
largest asset bubbles in history'; Investopedia (23 June 2015) Latin Post: K. J. Marifto, 'Fast food competition intensifies as
81 Telegraph Media Group limited: 'Bitcoin price tracker: Burger King, McDonald's, Wendy's fight for cheapest meal
live chart'; The Telegraph (6 March 2018) 86 The Financial deal', Latin Post (S January 2016) 187 BBC: Bryan Lufkin, 'How
Times Limited : 'Online shopping boom leads to record can a fast food chain ever make money from a $1 burger?', BBC
PUBLISHER'S ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xxiii
Capital (23 February 2018) 187 BBC: Bryan Lufkin, 'How can Smith, 'Greener datacenters for a brighter future: Microsoft's
a fast food chain ever make money from a $1 burger?', BBC commitment to renewable energy', Microsoft on the Issues
Capital (23 February 2018) 198 The Financial Times lim- blog (19/5/2016) 387 Startups: Anita Roddick interview,
ited: Murad Ahmed, 'Camelot overhauls Lottery as ticket Startups.co.uk 387 Guardian News and Media Limited:
sales fall', Finandal Times, 21 November 2017 6 Organiza- L'Oreal to sell Body Shop to Brazil's Natura in €1bn deal 404
tion of the Petroleum Exporting Cowitries: OPEC 212 Crown copyright: David Sainsbury et al., Report of the Inde-
Ofgem: 'Ofgem refers the energy market for a full competi- pendent Panel on Technical Education, GOV.UK (April
tion investigation', Press Release, Ofgem (26 June 2014) 212 2016) 412 Varldsnaturfonden WWF: Stem Review on the
Crown copyright: Energy Market Investigation: Summary Economics of Climate Change, Executive Summary, HM
of Final Report, Competition and Markets Authority (24June Treasury (2006). 413 United Nations: IPCC Report: 'severe
2016, updated 27 February 2018) 213 Crown copyright: and pervasive' impacts of climate change will be felt every-
Energy Market Investigation: Summary of Final Report, op. where' UN and Climate Change, United Nations (31 March
cit. 214 BBC: https://www.bbc.com/news/busi- 2014) 440 The Financial Times Umited: The G7 consists of
ness-35408064 219 Cengage Learning: Thomas]. Nechyba, Canada, France, Germany, Italy, Japan, the United Kingdom,
Microeconomics: an Intuitive Approach with Calculus, Cen- and the United States© The Financial Times Limited 2018.
gage (2010) 240 The Financial Times Limited: 'Industrial All Rights Reserved. 441 Holtzbrinck Publishing Group:
giants caught in LED headlights' By Chris Bryant, 2015 ©The Torsten Riecke and Jens Ml.inchrath, 'It's time to rewind',
Financial Times Limited 2015. All Rights Reserved. 272 Oper- Handelsblatt Global, 19 August 2016, 444 Lagardere Group:
ations Buzz: Ram Ganeshan, 'The iPhone 4 Supply Chain' P. Legrain, Open World: The Truth about Globalisation (Aba-
Operations Buzz (28 November 2010) 274 Telegraph Media cus, 2003). 444 Organisation for Economic Co-operation
Group Limited: 'Why Northern Rock was doomed to fall', and Development: A. Gurria, Managing globalisation and
Daily Telegraph (17 September 2007) 297 University of the role of the OECD (OECD, 2006). 444 International
Pennsylvania:J.Turow, L. Feldman and KMeltzer, 'Open to Monetary Fund: IMF staff, Globalization: A Brief Overview
exploitation: America's shoppers on-line and off-line', (OECD, 2008). 44S G. Yip: G. Yip, Total Global Strategy
Departmental Papers, Annenberg Public Policy Center of the (Prentice Hall, 1995) 460 Guardian News and Media Llm-
University of Pennsylvania Oune 2005) 312 The Financial ited: Prem Sikka, 'Shifting profits across borders', The Guard-
Times Limited: German employers forced to reveal gender ian, 12 February 2009 463 Bloomberg: 'Tesco stumbles with
pay gap By Tobias Buck© The Financial Times Limited 2018. Wal-Mart as China shoppers buy local', Bloomberg (19 Octo-
All Rights Reserved. 313 The Financial Times Limited: ber 2012) (available at http://www.bloomberg.com/news/
'Zero-hours contracts hold their place in UK labour market', articles/2012-10-18/tesco-stumbles-with-wal-mart-as-china-
Financial Times, 2 September 2015 331 Crown copyright: shoppers-buy-local) 463 Bloomberg: 'Tesco stumbles with
Universal Credit: Welfare that works, DWP 325 Guardian Wal-Mart as China shoppers buy local', Bloomberg (19 Octo-
News and Media Limited: Sally Weale, 'Students demand ber 2012) (available at http://www.bloomberg.com/news/
compensation from universities over lecturer strikes', articles/2012-10-18/tesco-stumbles-with-wal-mart-as-china-
Guardian, 7 February 2018 337 Chartered Institute of Per- shoppers-buy-local) 478 European Union: 'Global policy
sonnel and Development: 'Selection methods', CIPD Fact- without democracy' (speech by Pascal Lamy, EU Trade Com-
sheet, Chartered Institute of Personnel and Development missioner, given in 2001). 489 European Union: Single
(2018) 355 Offshore Wind Journal: David Foxwell , 'UK Market Scoreboard (Performance per governance tool):
offshore wind on track to 2020 target', Offshore Wind foumal Transposition, 07/2017 edition (for reporting period
(17 April 2018) 362 The Financial Times Limited: 'Global 12/2015-12/2016). (European Commission) 492 Organisa-
fines for price-fixing hit $5.3bn record high' By Caroline tion for Economic Co-operation and Development: The
Binham, Legal Correspondent © The Financial Times Lim- economic consequences of Brexit: a taxing decision, OECD
ited 2015. 363 European Union: Neelie Kroes, European (25 April 2016) 496 The Financial Times Limited: Con-
Commission Competition Commissioner, 'Competition, sumer spending continues to decline despite UK wage
the crisis and the road to recovery', Address at the Economic pick-up, Delphine Strauss in London © The Financial Times
Club ofToronto, 30 March 2009 375 The Economist News- Limited 2018 497 Bank for International Settlements:
paper Limited: 'Commons Sense', The Economist, 31 July Mervyn King, Former Governor of the Bank of England,
2008. 375 The Economist Newspaper Limited: 'Com- 'Finance: a return from risk', speech to the Worshipful Com-
mons Sense', The Economist, 31 July 2008. 375 The Econo- pany of International Bankers, at the Mansion House, 17
mist Newspaper Limited: 'Commons Sense', The Economist, March 2009 528 Organisation for Economic Co-operation
31 July 2008. 375 Australian Indigenous cultural herit- and Development: The well-being of nations: the role of
age: Australian Indigenous cultural heritage (https://www. human and social capital,OECD,2001 579 Crown Copy-
australia.gov.au/information-and-services/culture-and- right: Statistical Interactive Database, Banlc of England, series
arts/indigenous-culture-and-history) 383 Microsoft: Brad LPQVWNV and LPQVWNQ (data published 29 March 2018)
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
collection is just as much a “fiction of the mind” as the unity which we
attribute to it. Yet the fact that the thing’s qualities are mainly mere
possibilities does not destroy the existence of the thing. It actually is,
and is somehow qualified by these possibilities. And for that very
reason its existence cannot be identified with the actual realisation of
these possibilities in a group or collection of events. We might add
as a further consideration, that the number of such possibilities is
indefinite, including not only the ways in which the thing has behaved
or will behave on the occurrence of conditions at present non-
existent, but also all the ways in which it would behave on the
occurrence of conditions which are never realised in actual
existence. But the previous argument is already in itself sufficient,
the moment its significance is fairly grasped, to dispose of the notion
that anything can be merely identical with a group of actually existing
sensible qualities. The being of the things must be sought not in the
actual existence of the group of sensible qualities, but in the law or
laws stating the qualities which would be exhibited in response to
varying sets of conditions.[84]
§ 7. Considerations of this kind compel us to forego the attempt to
find the substance or being of a thing in the mere sequence of its
different states considered as an aggregate. To make
Phenomenalism workable, we are forced to say at least that the
thing or substance to which the various attributes are assigned is the
“law of its states,” or again is “the mode of relation of its various
qualities.” Such a definition has obviously a great advantage over
either of the two we have just rejected. It is superior to the
conception of the thing as an unknown substratum of qualities, since
it explicitly excludes the absurd notion of a world of things which first
are, without being in any determinate way, and then subsequently
set up determinate ways of existing among themselves. For a law,
while not the same thing as the mere collection of occurrences in
which it is realised, has no existence of its own apart from the series
of occurrences which conform to it. Again, every law is a statement
of possibilities, a formula describing the lines which the course of
events will follow if certain conditions are operative; no law is a mere
register of actually observed sequences.[85] Hence, in defining the
thing as the “law of its states,” we avoid the difficulty dealt with in the
last paragraph, that the collection of the thing’s states never actually
exists as a “given” collection. Thus for ordinary practical purposes
the definition is probably a satisfactory one.
Yet it should be evident that in calling the thing the “law” of its
states, we merely repeat the metaphysical problem of the unity of
substance without offering any solution of it. For, not to dwell on the
minor difficulty that we might find it impossible to formulate a single
law connecting all the ways in which one thing reacts upon others,
and thus ought more properly to speak in the plural of the laws of the
states, we are now left with two distinct elements or aspects of the
being of the thing, namely, the successive states and the law of their
succession, and how these two aspects are united the theory fails to
explain. We have the variety and multiplicity on the one hand in the
states or qualities of the thing, its unity on the other in the form of the
law connecting these states, but how the variety belongs to or is
possessed by the unity we know no better than before. Thus the old
problem of substance returns upon us; the many qualities must
somehow be the qualities of a single thing, but precisely how are we
to conceive this union of the one and the many?[86]
At this point light seems to be thrown on the puzzle by the doctrine
of Leibnitz,[87] that the only way in which a unity can, without ceasing
to be such, contain an indefinite multiplicity is by “representation.”
Experience, in fact, presents us with only one example of a unity
which remains indubitably one while embracing an indefinite
multiplicity of detail, namely, the structure of our experience itself.
For the single experience regularly consists of a multiplicity of mental
states, both “focal” and “marginal,” simultaneous and successive,
which are nevertheless felt as one single whole because they form
the expression of a coherent purpose or interest. And this conscious
unity of feeling, determined by reference to a unique interest, is the
only instance to which we can point when we desire to show by an
actual illustration how what is many can at the same time be one. If
we can think of the thing’s qualities and the law of their connection
as standing to one another in the same way as the detailed series of
acts embodying a subjective interest of our own, and the interest
itself which by its unity confers a felt unity on the series, we can in
principle comprehend how the many qualities belong to the one
thing. In that case the thing will be one “substance” as the
embodiment of an individual experience, determined by a unique
subjective interest, and therefore possessing the unity of immediate
feeling. Its many qualities will “belong” to it in the same sense in
which the various constituents of an experience thus unified by
immediate feeling are said to “belong” to the single experience they
constitute. And thus our idealistic interpretation of the general nature
of Reality will be found to contain the solution of the problem of
Substance and Quality.
Now it is fairly clear that some such idealistic solution is already
contained in germ in the pre-scientific view of the world of things.
There can be little doubt that our original notion of the unity of the
thing as contrasted with the multiplicity of its qualities has been
obtained by “introjectively” ascribing to whatever groups of qualities
act upon us as one in respect of some interest of our own, the same
conscious unity of feeling which we know in ourselves and our
fellows. We shall have frequent opportunities, as we proceed, of
discovering the enormous extent to which the whole pre-scientific
view of the world is based upon the interpretation of all existence in
terms of our own. Systematic Idealism will thus gradually be found to
be no more than the consistent and deliberate carrying through of
that anthropomorphic interpretation of Reality which lies at the
bottom of all man’s attempts to make his surroundings intelligible to
himself. It will follow, if our general attitude towards the problem of
substance is tenable, that only what we have already defined as an
individual experience can truly be called a “substance,” and that
such experiences are “substances,” if the word is to be retained in
our philosophical vocabulary, to the same degree to which they are
truly individual. And thus we should be led in the end to the
distinction between the one infinite substance which forms the whole
of Reality and the finite and imperfect substances which are its
components.
Again, we should have once more to remember that since, in
general, we call that group of qualities one which acts on our
interests as one, and our insight into those interests themselves is
limited and confused, the boundaries assigned by us to the group of
qualities we ascribe to a single substance as “its” states will be more
or less arbitrary, and dependent upon the degree of our actual
insight. It is possible for us to group together as states of the same
thing qualities which a profounder insight would have disjoined, and
vice versâ. And in the end, if all that is is contained in a single
coherent self-determined system, it is clear that, speaking rigorously,
there will ultimately be only one “substance”—the central nature or
principle of the system itself—of which all subordinate aspects or
parts of existence will be the attributes.
§ 8. The Problem of Relation.—More perplexing than the problem
of Substance and its Qualities is the question to which the pre-
scientific assumption that the world consists of a number of
interrelated things gives rise. This problem of Relation becomes still
more prominent when reflection upon the problem of Substance and
Quality has made it manifest that what we call the qualities of things
are one and all dependent upon their relations either to our
perceptive organs or to other things. Put quite simply the problem is
as follows: Things stand in a variety of relations to one another, and
what we commonly call the qualities of each are dependent on (a) its
modes of relation to other things, (b) its relation to our percipient
organism. Again, the various qualities of one thing stand in relation
among themselves. To begin with, they all exhibit the relations of
identity and difference. They all so far possess a common nature as
to be capable of being compared in respect of the special ways in
which they manifest that nature, and are thus so far identical; again,
they can be discriminated and distinguished, and are so far in the
relation of difference. Further, the qualities of one thing are
interconnected, as we have already seen, by various special laws or
modes of relation, which exhibit the changes in the behaviour of the
thing corresponding to changes in the surrounding circumstances.
Thus Phenomenalism, when it has banished the notion of a
substantial unity in things, has to identify the world of things, as we
have already seen, with qualities in relation to one another. But now
the question arises, How are we to understand the conception of
qualities in relation? Can we, on the one hand, reduce all qualities to
relations or all relations to qualities, or, on the other, can we form an
intelligible idea of the way in which a single whole or system can be
formed by the union of the two? There are, of course, other
questions of great though relatively secondary importance connected
with the problem of relation, e.g., the question as to the number of
ultimately irreducible kinds of relation, but the scope of the present
work will permit of nothing beyond a brief discussion of the central
difficulty. We will take the various alternatives in order.
(1) Philosophers have often been tempted to evade the difficulty of
showing how qualities and relations together can make up a system
by suppressing one member of the antithesis altogether. Thus it has
been maintained, on the one hand, that the world of real things
consists entirely of simple unrelated qualities, and that what we call
relations between these qualities are merely our own subjective
ways of apprehending them. On the other hand, it has been
suggested that there may be nothing in the real world except
relations, and that what we call qualities of various kinds are nothing
but forms of relation. But neither of these views seems seriously
tenable.
For (a) reality cannot consist of mere relations. Every relation
implies two or more terms which are related. And these terms cannot
be created by the relation itself. In every relation the terms have
some character of their own over and beyond the mere property of
being terms in that relation. Thus, to take a simple example, the
successive terms of the series of ordinal numbers express in
themselves nothing beyond determinate position in an ordered
series, but when they are applied to the actual arrangement of any
content in serial order, that content is (c) not created by the
arrangement of it in an ordered series of terms, and (b) is dependent
for the actual order of its terms upon some positive character of its
own. In other words, whenever you actually count you count
something other than the names of the numbers you employ, and
you count it in an order which depends on the character of the
particular things counted.[88] And so generally of all relations. A
question has been raised which presents considerable difficulty and
cannot be discussed here, whether there are or are not merely
external relations (i.e. relations which are independent of the special
qualities of their terms). But even if we admit that there may be such
merely external relations, which do not depend upon the nature of
the terms between which they subsist, it is at least clear that there
cannot be relations without any terms, and that the terms are not
created out of nothing by the relation between them.[89] Perhaps it
might be rejoined that what I call the terms of a certain relation,
though no doubt not created by that particular relation, may be
themselves analysed into other relations, and those again into others
ad indefinitum. Thus it might be said that the term A of the relation A-
B may no doubt have a quality of its own which is not created by this
relation. But this quality, call it A1, is found on analysis to be
resoluble into the relation C-D, and the quality C1 of C again into the
relation E-F, and so on without end. This would not, however,
amount to a reduction of qualities to mere relations. For it would give
us, as the unit of our scheme of things, a pair of terms or qualities in
relation; and however often we repeated the process of analysis, we
should still always be left with the same type of triad, two terms and
a relation, as the result of analysis. Whatever its worth, this particular
solution falls under our second alternative, and must be considered
in connection with it.
(2) But again, it is even more manifest that we cannot reduce all
reality to qualities, and dismiss the relations between them as simply
our subjective mode of apprehension. This line of thought is capable
of being worked out in two slightly different ways. We might hold that
what really exists is disconnected simple qualities, each distinct from
all others as red is from sweet, or loud from hot, and that the whole
network of relations by which everyday and scientific thought bring
these “reals” into connection is a mere intellectual scaffolding to
which nothing in the real world corresponds. Something like this
would be the logical outcome of the Humian doctrine that all relations
are “the work of the mind,” and that reality is the residuum left after
we have removed from our conception of the world everything which
is of our own mental fabrication. The grounds upon which this
doctrine was advanced by Hume and his followers have already
been destroyed by the progress of Psychology and the consequent
abandonment of the old hard-and-fast distinction between sensation
and mental construction. It was the belief of Hume, and apparently of
Kant, that what is given in “sensation” is single uncompounded
qualities, and that all relations between these psychical atoms are
produced by a subsequent process of subjective synthesis. But the
advance of Psychology, by leading to the recognition that sensation
itself is a continuous process containing a multiplicity of “marginal”
elements which in all sorts of ways modify the character of its central
or “focal” element, has made it impossible any longer to maintain an
absolute distinction between the sensory and the intellectual factor in
cognition.
And apart from the illusory nature of the distinction on which the
theory was based, it is sufficiently condemned for Metaphysics by its
own inherent absurdity. For the fundamental presupposition of
Metaphysics, as of all serious science, is that Reality is a coherent
system. But, according to the view which regards relations as pure
“fictions of the mind,” just that element in our thought which gives it
its systematic character is an unwarranted addition of our own to the
real. Order and system are in fact, on this view, mere illusion. And,
as has often been pointed out by the critics of Hume, it is quite
inconceivable how, in a world where nothing but disconnected simple
qualities exist, the illusion should ever have arisen. If even our own
inner life is simply incoherent, it is quite impossible to see how we
can ever have come, even by a fiction, to read system into the world
of fact.
A more plausible attempt to reduce all relations to qualities
proceeds on the following lines. Relations, it is said, are of subjective
manufacture, but they are, for all that, not mere fictions. For every
relation between two terms, say A and B, is based upon the
presence in A and B of certain qualities, which are called the
fundamenta relationis or basis of the relation. These qualities may be
the same in both the terms, in which case the relation is called
symmetrical; such a case is that, e.g., of the equality of A and B, a
relation having for its fundamentum the fact that A and B have both
the same magnitude. Here the real fact is taken to be that A has this
magnitude, and again that B has it. The subjective addition to the
facts is thought to come in in the voluntary comparison of A and B in
respect of this property and the consequent assertion of their
equality. Or the qualities which are the foundation of the relation may
be different in each of the terms, in which case the relation is
technically called asymmetrical. Examples of such asymmetrical
relations are, e.g., A greater than B, B less than A, or again, A father
to B, B son to A. Here the actual facts would be taken to be A
possessed of magnitude x, B of magnitude x-y, A qualified by the
circumstance of begetting B, B by the circumstance of being
begotten by A. The subjective addition would come in, as before,
when we brought A and B under one joint of view by comparing them
in respect of these properties.
The inherent difficulties of the reduction of relations to qualities
are, however, only thinly disguised in this version of the doctrine. To
argue that the establishment of judgments of relation presupposes
subjective comparison of the related terms from a more or less
arbitrarily chosen point of view, is metaphysically irrelevant. The
whole question is as to whether the result of the process is to make
things more intelligible as a systematic whole; if it is, the subjectivity
of the process is no ground for discrediting the result as truth about
the real. If it is not, the philosophers who insist on the subjectivity of
relations should explain how we can coherently think of a systematic
whole of reality in terms of quality apart from relation. This they have
never been able to do, and that for obvious reasons. It is manifestly
impossible to give any intelligible account of the qualities which we
recognise as fundamenta of relations without introducing previous
relations. Thus the possession of the common magnitude x may be
assigned as the foundation of the relation of equality between A and
B; but when we ask what is meant by predicating of A and B
possession of the magnitude x, we find that we are thrown back
upon a relation between A, B, and some third term S, which we take
as our unit of measurement. A and B are both of magnitude x
because each contains S, let us say, x times exactly. So again the
fact “A begetter of B” was assigned as the fundamentum of the
asymmetrical relation of paternity between A and B, and the same
fact under another name as the fundamentum of the asymmetrical
relation of filiation between B and A.
But now what is meant by saying that the same fact qualifies A
and B in different ways? Any answer to this question plunges us
back at once into a perfect network of relations. For first, that a fact x
may be known to qualify A and B differently, A and B must
themselves be discriminated, i.e. they must be compared and found
different, and without relation difference is unmeaning. For ultimately
two terms are different only when they also possess a common
character which admits of their comparison with reference to a
common standard. Thus only things which are like can be different,
and the problem of the relation of their likeness to their difference is
inevitably forced upon us by the very existence of the difference. And
similarly, the common fact x qualifies either term in a definite way,
which can be discriminated from the ways in which other facts qualify
the same term, and this discrimination leads in precisely the same
manner to the assertion of various relations among the different
qualities of A and again of B.[90]
It is not difficult to see the common source of the difficulties which
beset both the attempt to reduce all reality to qualities, and the
attempt to identify it with mere relations. In actual experience our
world always comes to us as at once many and one, never as
merely single nor as merely discrete. If you pay exclusive regard to
the aspect of unity and interconnection, you will naturally be tempted
to dwell on the relations between your elements to the exclusion of
the various elements themselves; if you think solely of the aspect of
variety, it is equally natural to treat the elements as real and their
relations as fictions. But in either case you arbitrarily concentrate
your attention on a single aspect of the experienced fact taken in
isolation from the other, and are thus led to results which are bound
to collide with the whole facts. A true view, if possible at all, can only
be got by impartial adherence to the whole of the facts.
§ 9. We are thus brought to the second of our alternatives. Can we
conceive of Reality as qualities in relation or qualities and their
relations? This is really, in a somewhat more developed form, the
same problem as that suggested by the definition of a thing as the
“law of its states.” We are now to take the qualities as fixed terms
with a character of their own which stand in or support further
relations, and we have to ask if the view of the world thus formulated
is entirely intelligible. And it speedily becomes clear that such a view
is confronted by a formidable difficulty. For suppose that A and B are
two qualities which stand in any relation C. (For simplicity’s sake we
might suppose this relation C to be, e.g., that of being discriminated,
and we might take as instances of A and B, say, two definitely
discriminated shades of the same colour.) Then A and B, standing in
the relation C, are not identical with A and B as they would be apart
from this relation. (A, for instance, as qualified by contradistinction
from B, is not the same thing as mere A not in any way affected by
B, a fact which is frequently brought home to us with startling force
by the effects of contrast.) At the same time the relation C cannot
create its own terms; A, which is qualified in some special way by its
standing to B in the relation C, may also exist out of this relation, and
the mere fact of our recognising it as A shows that, both in the
relation C and outside it, it has a recognisable identical character.
(E.g., A as discriminated from B is not precisely the same thing as A
before discrimination, but the difference of A from B has not been
created by the act of discrimination; it must previously have been
different in order to be discriminated.)
Thus we seem forced to split up the quality A, which we took as
one of the terms of our relation, into two aspects, A (A1) the quality
as it was before the establishment of the relation, and A (A2) the
quality as it is after the establishment of the relation. And the two
aspects thus discovered in what we took for the single quality A must
again be somehow in relation to one another. Hence within A (A1)
and A (A2) itself the same process will be repeated, and what we
began by regarding as the fixed terms of the relation will turn out to
be themselves systems of qualities in relation, and this process will
have no limit. The classification of the contents of experience into
fixed terms with relations between them, it is contended, is no
solution of the problem how the experienced world can be both one
and many but a mere restatement of it. “We have to take reality as
many and to take it as one, and to avoid contradiction.... And we
succeed, but succeed merely by shutting the eye which if left open
would condemn us.” Hence the conclusion is drawn that “a relational
way of thought ... must give appearance and not truth. It is a
makeshift, a device, a mere practical compromise, most necessary
but in the end most indefensible.”[91]
§ 10. The foregoing reasoning, which has been condensed from
the fuller exposition in Mr. F. H. Bradley’s Appearance and Reality,
demands most careful examination, as the consequence to which it
leads is of supreme importance for our whole metaphysical view of
the nature of ultimate Reality. If the conclusion of Mr. Bradley is
sound, it is clear that our discursive thought with its scheme of
predication, which is from first to last relational, can never give us
adequate insight into the nature of the union of the one and the
many. We shall then have to conclude that it is not in thought about
Reality, but in some mode of experience, if such there is, which
enables us to transcend the separation of subject from predicate,
and is therefore suprarelational, that we come nearest to
experiencing the real as it really is. We should thus be more or less
in sympathy with the traditional Mysticism which has always made
the transcending of the distinction of subject from predicate the
keynote of its special way of experiencing the Divine. On the other
hand, if the relational scheme of ordinary knowledge could be
defended as a self-consistent way of regarding the facts, we should
have the advantage of being able to construe the absolute
Experience in terms of our own intellectual life much more
completely than Mysticism allows.
How, then, might the interpretation of the world as a system of
qualities in relation be defended against Mr. Bradley’s powerful
formulation of the mystic’s objection, and what is the worth of the
defence? Two possible lines of argument suggest themselves as
sufficiently plausible to call for examination. (1) The edge of the
objection would be turned, as far as it rests upon the
unsatisfactoriness of the indefinite regress, if we could regard all
relations as “external,” that is, as making no difference in the
qualities they relate. Now, some relations, it has been asserted, are
merely external, e.g., relations of position and again of sense in the
geometrical meaning of the word (like the difference between a right-
hand and a left-hand glove). Why, then, may this not ultimately be
the case with all relations? But if all relations are external, we can no
longer argue that the related terms must contain a further relation
between themselves as the basis and themselves as the result of the
first relation, and so the whole anti-relational case falls to the ground.
Such a view seems, however, to suffer from fatal deficiencies. For
(a) it is at least hard to see how any relation can be ultimately
external to its terms. For you cannot hold two terms in a relation of
any sort without discriminating them; until they are at least
discriminated as two they cannot be terms with a relation between
them. Thus discrimination, and therefore the relation of distinction, is
fundamental in all relation. But where we can distinguish there must
already be in the discriminated terms some difference to afford a
basis for discrimination. Only what is already different can be
distinguished. And with this admission the door is once more opened
for the indefinite regress.
(b) And even if this were not so, it seems unthinkable that all
relations should be in the end external to their terms. If no relation in
the end makes any difference to its terms, and thus has no
foundation in their nature, it becomes a standing miracle how or why
the terms should enter into relations to which they are all the time
absolutely indifferent. The logical consequence of such a view would
surely be the dismissal of all relations as pure illusion, and the
reduction of real existence to a chaos of disconnected reals which
we by some inexplicable intellectual perversity persist in taking for a
system. The now universally recognised failure of Herbart’s attempt
to work out a theory of Realism on these lines seems ominous for
the success of any future doctrine of the same kind.
(2) Much more subtle is the line of thought suggested by Professor
Royce in the Supplementary Essay appended to his book, The
World and the Individual, First Series. Professor Royce admits the
indefinite regress as an inevitable consequence of the reduction of
the world to terms in relation, but denies that it affects the soundness
of the reduction. On the contrary, he regards it rather as a proof of
the positive correctness of the interpretation of existence which gives
rise to it. His argument, which is based upon the modern doctrine of
infinite series, may be briefly summarised as follows:—It is a
recognised characteristic of an infinite series (and of no others) that
it can be adequately “represented” by a part of itself. That is to say, if
you take any infinite series you please, you can always construct a
second series such that it consists of a selection, and only of a
selection, from the terms of the first series, and that every term is
derived from and answers to the corresponding term of the first
series according to a definite law. And this second series, as it is
easy to prove, is itself infinite, and therefore capable of being itself
represented adequately in a third series derived from it in the same
manner as it was derived from the first, and so on indefinitely.
For instance, let the first series be the infinite series of the natural
integers 1, 2, 3, 4, ... then if, e.g., we construct a second series, 12,
22, 32 ... of the second powers of these integers, the terms of this
second series are derived by a definite law from those of the first to
which they correspond, and again they constitute a selection out of
the terms of the first series. Every one of them is a term of the first
series, but there are also terms of the first series which are not
repeated in the second. Again, if we make a third series from the
second in the same way as the second was made from the first, by
taking the terms (12)2, (22)2, (32)2, and so on, the terms of this third
series fulfil the same conditions; they correspond according to a
fixed law with the terms of the second, and are also themselves a
selection from those terms. And thus we may go on without end to
construct successive infinite series each of which “adequately
represents” the preceding one. And we are led into this indefinite
regress by the very attempt to carry out consistently a single definite
principle of correspondence between our original infinite series and
its first derivative. In constructing the first derived series in our
illustration 12, 22, 32 ... we necessarily also construct the series (12)2,
(22)2, (32)2, ... and the other successive derivatives. Therefore Prof.
Royce claims that any consistent attempt to make an orderly
arrangement of the terms of an infinite whole must lead to the
indefinite repetition of itself. Hence that each term of every relation
on analysis turns out itself to consist of terms in relation, is no valid
objection to the soundness of our principle of interpretation, but a
necessary consequence of the infinity of Reality.[92] Any consistent
attempt to exhibit an infinite whole as an orderly system of terms
must lead to the indefinite regress.
Now it strikes one at once that Professor Royce’s conclusion is in
danger of proving too much. You certainly do not show a method of
dealing with facts to be sound by showing that it leads to the
indefinite regress. It is a common experience that the liar who tells
his first lie must tell a second to back it, and a third to support the
second, and so on indefinitely. And you cannot put a quart of liquor
into a pint pot without first putting half the quart into half the space,
and so forth ad indefinitum. Yet these considerations do not prove
that lying or putting quarts of liquor into pint pots is a consistent way
of dealing with reality. A purpose may lead in execution to the
indefinite regress because it is self-contradictory and therefore self-
defeating, as these familiar illustrations suggest. And this raises the
question whether the purpose to arrange an infinite whole in an
ordered system of terms may not lead to the indefinite regress for
the same reason, namely, that the treatment of a true whole as a
sequence of terms is incompatible with its real nature. It is at least
worth while to ask whether Professor Royce’s own treatment of the
subject does not contain indications that this is actually the case.[93]
To begin with, we may note one point of some importance in
reference to which Prof. Royce’s language is at least ambiguous. He
speaks of the indefinite succession of infinite series which arise from
the single purpose of “representing” the series of natural integers
adequately by a selection out of itself as if they could be actually
constructed in pursuance of this purpose. But this is clearly not the
case. All that you can actually do is to construct the various series
implicitly by giving a rule for their formation. The actual construction
of the series would be a typical instance of a self-defeating and
therefore internally contradictory purpose, inasmuch as it would
involve the actual completion of an unending process. Hence we
seem forced to make a distinction which Prof. Royce has perhaps
unduly neglected. If your purpose of ordering the number series on a
definite plan means no more than the formulation of a rule for
obtaining any required number of terms of the successive series, it
can be executed, but does not involve the indefinite regress; if it
means the actual completion of the process of formation of the
series, it does involve the indefinite regress, but is therefore self-
contradictory and cannot be realised in act. Similarly, we may say of
the scheme of qualities in relation, that if it is taken for no more than
a rule for the systematic arrangement and organisation of a finite
material, it does not involve the completion of an infinite process,
and is both workable and useful; but if presented as an account of
the way in which a completed all-embracing and perfectly
harmonious experience of the whole of Reality is internally
organised, it involves the completion of the infinite process, and is
therefore self-contradictory and finally inadequate.[94]
This reflection may serve to lead up to another which seems to
take us into the heart of the matter. The researches upon which Prof.
Royce’s defence of the relational scheme is based were in the first
instance investigations into the significance of the number-series. As
such they start with the conception of a system which is a whole of
parts external to one another[95] as the object of inquiry.
Consequently, while such investigations are of the highest
philosophical importance as bringing out the implications of this
concept, they are only valid as an analysis of ultimate Reality,
provided that the concept of whole and part is an adequate
expression of the way in which the whole Reality is present in its
constituents and they in it. But if, as we ourselves urged in a
previous chapter, the conception of a whole of parts is entirely
inadequate to express the intimate union between the absolute
experience and finite experiences,[96] the proof that the indefinite
process is logically implied in the relation of whole and part does not
show it to belong to the structure of ultimate Reality. Rather, we
should be inclined to urge, the fact that the relational scheme leads
to the indefinite process proves that the conception of whole and part
upon which it is based does not truly represent the mode of union
between a completed experience and its components. And therefore
the attempt to interpret this union in terms of the number-series
cannot stand the test of criticism.
At the same time, Professor Royce’s argument in any case throws
considerable light upon the problem of relation. For it shows why the
attempt to construct the world as a system of qualities in relation
leads to the indefinite regress. For a complete experience
embodying at one stroke the whole of existence, such a construction
would, as we have seen, because essentially incomplete, be
impossible. But when we try to piece together the data of our
fragmentary experience into a connected whole, we inevitably have
to start with more or less isolated facts as fixed terms and weld them
together by a relation. In doing so we unavoidably put ourselves at
the point of view from which the numerical series arises; we
unavoidably treat existence as if it were a whole of mutually external
parts. And so the indefinite regress involved in the nature of the
number-system inevitably parades the whole of our discursive and
relational thinking about existence. But its presence is due to the
inadequacy of the conception of Reality with which discursive
thought has to work.
On the whole, then, it seems that Prof. Royce’s investigations only
make it more apparent than before that the relational scheme which
discursive thought uses does not adequately express the true nature
of the real, and that the mystics of all ages have been so far justified
in their contention that the form of our experience which presents the
truest analogy to the experience of the Absolute must be supra-
relational, or, in other words, that the most real type of finite
experience must be one which transcends the distinction of subject
and predicate. To admit this is, however, not to admit that we are
altogether ignorant how the one and the many are united in Reality.
For there are many other types of human experience besides that
which is dominated by the discursive and relational intellect.
In immediate simple feeling we have obviously a type of conscious
experience in which distinction and relation have as yet not
emerged. And I have tried in Bk. I. chap. 2 to show how in the direct
intuition of an æsthetic whole by trained artistic perception we have
at a higher level an experience which contains the results of an
elaborate process of distinction and relation, but contains them in a
way which transcends the relational form and reverts in its directness
to the unity of immediate feeling. While again we have in the
personal love which is one with mutual insight a form of experience
that, if translated into the language of the intellect, would require for
its description a whole world of relations and predicates, and is yet,
as experienced, an intimate unity no relational scheme can more
than faintly adumbrate. And it is worthy of consideration that religious
emotion in all ages has borrowed from these forms of experience its
favourite expressions for the highest modes of communion between
the finite and the infinite, the “beatific vision,” the “love of God,” etc.
It seems indeed as if the function of the mere intellect were always
that of a necessary and valuable intermediary between a lower and a
higher level of immediate apprehension. It breaks up, by the
relations and distinctions it introduces, the original union of the what
and the that of simple feeling, and proceeds to make the what, which
it deals with in its isolation, ever more and more complex. But the
ultimate issue of the process is only reached and its ultimate aim
only satisfied so far as it conducts us at a higher stage of mental
development to the direct intuition of a richer and more
comprehensive whole in the immediate unity of its that and its what.
The besetting philosophical sin of the mere mystic is not so much his
refusal to accept the work of the mere intellect as the highest and
truest type of human experience, as his tendency to satisfy his
demand for the fuller union of the what with the that by reverting to
the lower forms of immediacy upon which intellectual reflection has
not done its work, instead of pressing on to the higher in which the
effect of that work is preserved though its form is transcended.
These reflections may serve to obviate the objection that to reject
the relational scheme when it is offered as the ultimate truth is to
deny the value and significance of the scientific work we accomplish
by means of it. Though the scheme of relations cannot adequately
express the mode of union between the finite and the infinite, there is
no fresh addition to the system of relations into which scientific
analysis translates the real world of experience that does not
increase our knowledge of what the real world must contain, though
it may fail to explain how it contains it. And, in conclusion, let it be
remembered that it is true not only of the religious mystic’s special
experience of union with deity, but of all direct experience, that the
relational scheme is quite inadequate to explain how it holds its
double aspects, its unity and its multiplicity, its that and its what, in
complete interpenetration. For no living experience is a mere whole
of parts, and none, therefore, can be fully represented by a scheme
based upon the concept of whole and part.[97]

Consult further:—F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality, chaps. 1-


3, 15, 27; L. T. Hobhouse, Theory of Knowledge, pp. 172-181
(Qualities and Relations), 540-557 (Substance); H. Lotze,
Metaphysic, bk. i. chap. 1 (The Being of Things), chap. 2 (The
Quality of Things), chap. 3 (The Real and Reality); J. Royce, The
World and the Individual, First Series, Supplementary Essay; B.
Russell, “The Concept of Order” (Mind, January 1901), and article on
“Position in Space and Time” (Mind, July 1901); G. F. Stout, “Alleged
Self-contradictions in the Concept of Relation” (Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, New Series, vol. ii. pp. 1-14, with the
accompanying discussion, pp. 15-24).

SUPPLEMENTARY NOTE TO CHAPTER IV.

Dr. Stout’s Reply to Mr. Bradley’s Criticism


of the Concept of Relation.
Since the preceding chapter was written, I have had the
opportunity of studying Dr. Stout’s paper in the current volume of
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. I have not thought it
necessary to make any alterations in the text of Chapter 4, in
consequence of Dr. Stout’s criticism, but I may perhaps be permitted
to add the following remarks, which must not be regarded as a
systematic appreciation or examination of Dr. Stout’s views. The
latter, as he himself pleads, cannot indeed be finally judged until he
has worked out the theory of Predication for which his present paper
merely prepares the way.
1. Dr. Stout begins by admitting what to my own mind is the
essence of the anti-relational argument. “No relation or system of
relations can ever constitute a self-subsistent and self-contained
Reality. The all-inclusive universe cannot ultimately consist in (? of) a
collection of interrelated terms” (op. cit., p. 2). This being once
conceded, I should have thought it an inevitable consequence that a
“collection of interrelated terms” cannot give us the final truth about
the nature of anything. For the whole idealist contention, as I
understand it and have tried to sustain it in the present work, is that
the structure of the whole is so repeated in any and every one of its
members that what is not the truth about the whole is never the
ultimate truth about anything. precisely because there is ultimately
nothing apart from the whole, and the whole again is nothing apart
from its members. So much, I had thought, we have all learned from
Hegel, and therefore Dr. Stout’s dilemma that any proposition
asserting relation (p. 5) must be false, unless the relational scheme,
so long as it is not affirmed of the ultimate whole itself, gives us truth,
does not seem to me to possess any real cogency. With Mr. Bradley
himself, as quoted by Dr. Stout, I should urge that if the relational
scheme is not itself internally discrepant, there remains no valid
ground for disputing its applicability to the whole.
2. Dr. Stout’s introduction into a “relational unity” of the third term,
—relatedness does not seem to me to remove the difficulties
inherent in our problem. And the illustration by which he supports it
appears to be unsound. He argues that when my hat is on my head
this state of things implies (1) the two related terms, the hat and the
head,(2) a relation of on and under. (3) the fact that the terms stand
in this relation—their relatedness. For (1) and (2) by themselves
would be compatible with my hat being on the peg and my head
bare. But surely there is here a confusion between the relation of
above and below, and the very different relation of on and under.
The latter relation includes, as the former does not, immediate
contact as part of its meaning. If there are (1) a hat and a head, and
(2) the relation on and under—in this sense—between the two, there
is surely no need of a third factor to complete the concrete actuality
of “hat on head.” If the hat is not actually on the head, then (2), the
supposed relation, is not there at all. And if (2) is there the whole fact
is already there. In a word, Dr. Stout seems to me to count in the
concrete fact of “thing exhibiting related aspects” as a third
constituent in itself, precisely as popular Logic sometimes counts in
the actual judgment, under the name of Copula, as one factor of
itself.[98]
Then to Dr. Stout’s use of his distinction between the relation and
the fact of relatedness, I think it may be replied that it leaves us
precisely where we were before. The hat is qualified by being on the
head, the head by being in or under the hat, and hat and head
together by the relation of on and under between them. But how
these various aspects of the fact are to be combined in a single
consistent view we are no nearer knowing.
3. The endless regress. I think it will be seen from the preceding
chapter that in my own view a genuine endless regress is evidence
of the falsity of the conception which gives rise to it, and that I hold
this on the ground that the endless regress always presupposes the
self-contradictory purpose to sum an admittedly infinite series.
Hence I could not concur, so far as I can see at present, in Dr.
Stout’s distinction between the endless regress which does and that
which does not involve self-contradiction. As to his illustration of
endless regress of the second kind, the infinite divisibility of space
(p. 11), I should have thought that there is no actual endless regress
in question until you substitute for infinite divisibility infinite actual
subdivision, and that when you make this substitution it commits you
at once to the self-contradictory completion of an unending task. (Cf.
what was said above, § 10, with reference to infinite numerical
series.)
4. Dr. Stout goes on to deny that there is any endless regress,
self-contradictory or not, involved in the relational scheme. According
to him, what connects the relation with its terms is not another
relation (which would of course give rise to an endless regress), but
their relatedness, which is “a common adjective both of the relation
and the terms” (p. 11). I have already explained why this solution
appears to me merely to repeat the problem. The relatedness, so far
as I can see, is a name for the concrete fact with its double aspect of
quality and relation, and I cannot understand how mere insistence
upon the concrete unity of the fact makes the conjunction of its
aspects more intelligible.
5. Dr. Stout further supports his contention by a theory of the
nature of continuous connection which I have perhaps failed to
understand. Replying in anticipation to the possible objection of an
opponent, that if the “relatedness” connects the terms with their
relation there must be a second link to connect the term with its
relatedness, he says “there is no intermediate link and there is need
for none. For the connection is continuous, and has its ground in that
ultimate continuity which is presupposed by all relational unity” (p.
12, cf. pp. 2-4). And, as he has previously told us, “so far as there is
continuous connection there is nothing between [i.e. between the
connected terms], and there is therefore no relation.”
Now there seems to me to be a contradiction latent here.
Continuous connection, of course, implies distinct but connected
terms which form a series. Where there are no such distinct terms
there is nothing to connect. Now it is, as I understand it, part of the
very nature of a continuous series that any two terms of the series
have always a number of possible intermediate terms between them.

You might also like