You are on page 1of 67

Mutation, Randomness, and Evolution

Arlin Stoltzfus
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/mutation-randomness-and-evolution-arlin-stoltzfus/
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/2/2021, SPi

Mutation, Randomness, and Evolution


OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/2/2021, SPi

Mutation,
Randomness, and
Evolution

Arlin Stoltzfus
Fellow, Institute for Bioscience and Biotechnology Research,
Rockville, Maryland, USA

1
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© Arlin Stoltzfus 2021
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
First Edition published in 2021
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Control Number: 2020952665
ISBN 978–0–19–884445–7
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198844457.001.0001
Printed and bound by
CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to many individuals—scientists, his- This book surely includes some mistakes, which
torians, and philosophers—for discussions about are my own. For topics that are not in my narrow
topics covered in this book, especially David area of expertise, I have cited relevant work without
McCandlish, Pablo Razeto-Barry, Sahotra Sarkar, always knowing the most recent or most relevant
Davide Vecchi, John Beatty, Joanna Masel, Ingo Brig- work. I apologize to those authors whose relevant
andt, Eric Haag, Arnaud Martin, Lee Altenberg, and work was not highlighted.
Wes Anderson the Philosopher; also Wallace Arthur, I thank the developers of freely available soft-
Lindley Darden, Jean-Baptiste Grodwohl, Astrid ware products involved in the creation of this
Haase, Philippe Hunemann, Yogi Jäger, Tom Jones, book: LATEX (TEXShop, MacTEX, BibTEX), R, RStudio,
Rees Kassen, Eugene Koonin, Francesca Merlin, TextWrangler (BBEdit), and GraphViz.
Kira Makarova, Roberta Millstein, Stuart Newman, I am particularly indebted to David McCandlish.
Josh Payne, Josh Plotkin, Justin Pritchard, Premal Every week for the past eight years, David and I
Shah, David Stern, Jay Storz, Jake Weissman, and have had a regularly scheduled one-hour conversa-
Julian Xue. I thank Andrei Chabes, Alex Couce, Ron tion, typically about collaborative projects, but also
Ellis, Darin Rokyta, Gloria Rudenko, and Premal about this book and any other aspects of evolu-
Shah for sharing data or figures. I thank Ian Sher- tionary biology. On innumerable occasions, he has
man for encouragement and advice, and Charles helped me to clarify my thinking, offered incisive
Bath and the staff at Oxford for production exper- interpretations of the theoretical literature, and sug-
tise. For camaraderie during thousands of hours of gested how to explain difficult concepts. This book
writing in the local coffee shop, I thank Ramyar, is partly an expression of our ongoing dialog.
Cary, Arcely, Elaine, Lauren, Lucas, Melanie, Nada,
Ben, Peter, Valerie, and especially Isabel.

v
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

Contents

List of figures xi
List of tables and boxes xiii

1 Introduction: a curious disconnect 1


1.1 Mutational origination as an evolutionary cause 1
1.2 What this book is about 5
1.3 Who this book is for 9
1.4 How the argument unfolds 11
1.5 Synopsis 13

2 Ordinary randomness 15
2.1 Introduction 15
2.2 Lacking in foresight 16
2.3 Uniformity or lack of pattern 16
2.4 Stochastic or probabilistic 20
2.5 Indeterminate 21
2.6 Subjectively unpredictable 22
2.7 Spontaneous 24
2.8 Independent (part 1) 28
2.9 Independent (part 2) 30
2.10 Synopsis 33

3 Practical randomness 35
3.1 Introduction 35
3.2 What good is a randomness assumption? 35
3.3 Uniformity 39
3.4 Independence 40
3.5 Predictability 41
3.6 The random null hypothesis 43
3.7 Beyond randomness: the principle of indifference 44
3.8 Synopsis 45

vii
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

viii CONTENTS

4 Evolutionary randomness 47
4.1 Introduction 47
4.2 Rejection of pervasively directed mutations 47
4.3 Rejection of Lamarckism 48
4.4 Independence from adaptation or evolution 52
4.5 Independence from fitness effects 53
4.6 Exceptions and possible exceptions to independence 56
4.7 Conditional independence and related ideas 60
4.8 Mutation and altered development 63
4.9 Synopsis 64

5 Mutational mechanisms and evolvability 67


5.1 Introduction 67
5.2 What a specially evolved mutation system looks like 68
5.3 Specialized systems of germline mutation in microbes 70
5.3.1 Multiple-inversion systems (shufflons) 70
5.3.2 Diversity-generating retroelements 71
5.3.3 CRISPR-Cas and piRNAs 71
5.3.4 Multiple cassette donation 74
5.3.5 Phase variation 75
5.3.6 Mating-type switching 76
5.4 Formulating plausible scenarios 77
5.5 Challenges and opportunities 82
5.6 Conditional independence and specialized mutation systems 85
5.7 Evolvability 86
5.8 Synopsis 89

6 Randomness as irrelevance 93
6.1 Introduction 93
6.2 Arguments from analogy and metaphysics 94
6.2.1 The “raw materials” metaphor 94
6.2.2 Creativity 95
6.2.3 Levels and types of causes 96
6.3 Direct empirical arguments 98
6.4 Mechanistic arguments 100
6.4.1 Creativity arguments 100
6.4.2 Directionality: the “opposing forces” argument 100
6.4.3 Initiative and rate: the “gene pool” arguments 102
6.5 The methodological argument 103
6.6 The explanatory argument 105
6.6.1 Darwin’s architect 106
6.6.2 Later arguments 107
6.7 Synopsis 107
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

CONTENTS ix

7 The problem of variation 111


7.1 Introduction 111
7.2 The power of the morphotron 112
7.3 Source laws and consequence laws 113
7.4 The Mendelian challenge 116
7.5 The contemporary challenge 118
7.5.1 The G matrix as predictor 119
7.5.2 The challenge to gradualism 120
7.5.3 The new genetics of adaptation 122
7.5.4 Evo-devo 124
7.5.5 Molecular evolution: the case of codon usage bias 126
7.5.6 The genomic challenge to adaptationism 130
7.6 Synopsis 132

8 Climbing Mount Probable 135


8.1 Introduction 135
8.2 Climbing Mount Probable 136
8.3 One-step adaptive walks under mutation bias 137
8.4 Extended adaptive walks under mutation bias 140
8.5 Protein adaptation under mutation bias 143
8.6 Origin-fixation dynamics 145
8.7 The sushi conveyor and the buffet 146
8.8 Why the theory of forces fails 149
8.9 The sources and forms of biases 152
8.10 Understanding developmental biases as evolutionary causes 155
8.11 An interpretation of structuralism 157
8.12 Parallel evolution 159
8.13 Conditioning on mutational effects 161
8.14 Synopsis 162

9 The revolt of the clay 165


9.1 Introduction 165
9.2 A predictive model of protein sequence evolution 166
9.3 Mutation-biased adaptation in the lab 169
9.4 CpG mutational hotspots and altitude adaptation 176
9.5 Transition bias in natural parallelisms 177
9.6 Preferences for regulatory or structural changes 183
9.7 Developmental bias 186
9.8 Evaluating the argument 188
9.8.1 Cryptic fitness biases actually explain the data 188
9.8.2 The connection to theory is thin 189
9.8.3 Selection did all the hard work 191
9.8.4 Mutation only affects the boring parts 192
9.9 Synopsis 194
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

x CONTENTS

10 Moving on 197
10.1 Introduction 197
10.2 Summary as historical narrative 197
10.3 A synopsis of key points 201
10.4 The objects and forms of explanations 203
10.5 The importance of verbal theories of causation 206
10.6 Discerning theories and traditions 210
10.7 Synopsis 214

Appendix A: Mutation exemplars 217


A.1 A replication error 217
A.2 Error-prone repair of DNA damage 218
A.3 A symbolic mutation process in a computer program 220
A.4 Human-engineered mutations 221

Appendix B: Counting the universe of mutations 223


B.1 Preliminaries 223
B.2 A necessary simplification 224
B.3 Point mutations 224
B.4 De novo insertions 225
B.5 Inversions, deletions, and tandem duplications 226
B.6 Transpositions (translocations) 226
B.7 Lateral gene transfers 227
B.8 Compound events 228
B.9 Summing up 228
B.10 Recurrences 229

Appendix C: Randomness quotations 231


C.1 Introduction 231
C.2 List of quotations 232

Appendix D: Irrelevance quotations 237


D.1 Introduction 237
D.2 List of quotations 237

Bibliography 243
Index 267
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

List of figures

1.1 Mutation rate, fitness, and frequency evolved 2


2.1 Rates of mutation span many orders of magnitude 17
2.2 The length distribution of indels in pseudogenes 18
2.3 Mutations templated by an imperfect palindrome 18
2.4 A pattern indicating context-dependence of nucleotide mutations 19
2.5 Spontaneous combustion 24
2.6 The Luria-Delbrück fluctuation test 25
2.7 Switching of VSG genes in Trypanosoma brucei 27
2.8 The chance conjunction of numbers on two dice 29
2.9 Rainfall plot showing kataegis in a pancreatic cancer cell line 30
2.10 How dNTP concentrations influence mutation 31
2.11 Negative correlation of mutation rate and cell density 33
3.1 Prediction is improved by knowledge of a bias 42
4.1 Dependence of experimental adaptation on mutation 53
4.2 Nucleotide changes differ systematically in fitness effects 57
4.3 Singlet, doublet and triplet replacements differ in fitness effects 58
4.4 Correspondence of mutation and selection across environments 60
4.5 Independence, conditional independence, and dependence 61
4.6 Dependence of mutation and fitness via intermediates 62
5.1 Scheme of VDJ recombination of antibody genes 69
5.2 Scheme of an inversion shufflon 70
5.3 Scheme of diversity-generating retroelemens (DGRs) 71
5.4 How CRISPR-Cas9 confers resistance 72
5.5 Scheme of cassette donation 74
5.6 Schemes of phase variation by STR and inversion 76
5.7 Scheme of yeast mating-type switching 77
6.1 An illustration of raw materials 94
6.2 A theory of evolution by shifting gene frequencies 105
7.1 The morphotron, an imaginary device 112
7.2 Fisher’s geometric model 121
7.3 Expected sizes of effects fixed in adaptation 121
7.4 Codon usage, mutation bias, and gene expression level 127
7.5 A neo-Darwinian model of lateral gene transfer 129

xi
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

xii LIST OF FIGURES

8.1 A rugged mountain landscape 136


8.2 The Yampolsky-Stoltzfus model 137
8.3 Effect of population size in the Yampolsky–Stoltzfus model 137
8.4 Effects of the sizes of s and u in the Yampolsky-Stoltzfus model 138
8.5 Chemotaxis with unbiased or biased tumbling 139
8.6 Special cases of evolutionary walks on an NK landscape 141
8.7 Adaptive walks on simplified smooth and rugged NK landscapes 142
8.8 Genetic code table with AT- and GC-rich codons 143
8.9 Adaptive walks on a smooth protein NK landscape 144
8.10 Adaptive walks on a rugged protein NK landscape 144
8.11 The origin-fixation model 145
8.12 The buffet and the sushi conveyor 147
8.13 The Yampolsky-Stoltzfus model in the buffet regime 148
8.14 Population-genetic “forces” operating in an allele-frequency space 149
8.15 Transition-transversion bias and GC:AT bias 153
8.16 A drunkard’s walk through gene-scrambling space 154
8.17 A molecular developmental bias induced by a GP map 155
8.18 A bias induced by a GP map, via the phenocopy effect 156
8.19 Networks of identical folds (phenotypes) in sequence space 158
8.20 The chance of parallelism is a sum of squares 160
8.21 The chances of parallelism with equivalence classes 161
9.1 A potter at work shaping clay 166
9.2 Observed tendencies of amino acid change 166
9.3 A simplified model of nucleotide mutation rates 167
9.4 Prediction of observed tendencies of amino acid change 167
9.5 The mutational component of the model, considered alone 168
9.6 Distribution of fitness effects for transitions vs. transversions 168
9.7 Mutation rate, fitness, and frequency evolved 170
9.8 Cefotaxime resistance with different mutation spectra 170
9.9 Two prediction models applied to Rokyta et al. (2005) 171
9.10 Results of replicate one-step adaptation of 4 related bacteriophages 173
9.11 Transition bias in experimental adaptation of λ phage 174
9.12 Parallel changes in ATPα1 (glycoside resistance) 178
9.13 A developmental bias in hermaphrodite sperm size 187
9.14 Fitness results from Sackman et al. (2017) 189
A.1 Pathways of proof-reading and mismatch repair 217
A.2 Forward and reverse wobble pairs for A and C 218
A.3 Two kinds of pyrimidine photo-dimers 219
A.4 Nucleotide excision repair pathway 219
B.1 Model for deletions, inversions and duplications 226
B.2 Model for counting possible transpositions 227
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

List of tables and boxes

Tables
2.1 Concepts of randomness summarized 34
9.1 Parallel adaptation results of Rokyta et al. (2005) 171
9.2 Origin-fixation expectations from the data of Rokyta et al. (2005) 172
9.3 Transition bias in experimental adaptation cases (summary) 175
9.4 Transition bias in highly repeated adaptive events 176
9.5 Transition bias in natural adaptation cases (summary) 182
B.1 A crude tally of the universe of mutations 229

Boxes
Box 1.1 TheoryA and theoryC 8
Box 2.1 Counting the universe of mutations 21
Box 2.2 Specialized mutation systems 27
Box 3.1 Three kinds of adaptationism 39
Box 3.2 A simple point about prediction and biases 42
Box 4.1 Darwin’s theories of evolutionary modification 50
Box 4.2 Aristotle’s 4-fold view of causation 59
Box 5.1 Understanding evolvability claims 81
Box 6.1 The essence of neo-Darwinism is a dichotomy of roles 98
Box 6.2 The Shifting-gene-frequencies Theory of Evolution 104
Box 7.1 The Mendelians in history and in Synthesis Historiography 114
Box 7.2 When “Darwinian adaptation” is neither 123
Box 7.3 Taking neo-Darwinism seriously: a practical example 128
Box 8.1 Dual causation: lessons from chemotaxis 139
Box 8.2 Population genetics without the introduction process 151
Box 9.1 The conservative transitions hypothesis 168
Box 9.2 The emergence of “molecular” evolution 184

xiii
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/2/2021, SPi

CHAPTER 1

Introduction: a curious disconnect

To see what is in front of one’s nose needs a constant struggle


George Orwell

1.1 Mutational origination as an ural evolution in diverse taxa (including animals


evolutionary cause and plants)—that biases in mutation influence the
course of adaptation. Such results suggest a cause–
MacLean et al. (2010) evolved resistance to the effect relationship between the rate at which vari-
antibiotic rifampicin in many replicate cultures of ants are introduced by mutation, and their chances
the bacterium Pseudomonas aeruginosa. Resistant of being manifested as evolutionary changes. As we
strains typically have mutations in the rpoB will see, this effect can be large, in the sense that
gene, encoding RNA polymerase. For 11 resistant a several-fold effect in evolution is a large effect.
mutants in rpoB, MacLean et al. (2010) measured Tendencies of mutation may impose predictable biases
the mutation rate, the effect on fitness, and the on evolution. Conversely, patterns in evolution may
frequency evolved. The inter-relationships of these have mutational explanations, not merely in the
three variables are shown in Fig. 1.1. sense that mutation is necessary for change, but
What do the results show? The frequency with in the sense that mutation is a difference-maker, a
which an outcome evolves is strongly correlated dispositional factor that causes one kind of change
with the rate of mutation (middle panel). That is, the to happen more often than another.
higher the rate at which a resistant variant emerges Evolutionary biology is the science of evolution-
by mutation, the more likely its appearance in repli- ary causes and effects. What are the terms that evo-
cate cultures, reaching a high frequency in each lutionary biologists use to describe this causal rela-
population. This effect does not occur because muta- tionship? What is the theory for its operation? How
tion rates are correlated with mutant fitness (right), widespread are its effects? What notable evolution-
which has little effect (left), given that all the muta- ary thinkers have espoused its importance? The
tions are strongly beneficial, with a similarly large inter-relationships of the three variables measured
chance of fixation. by MacLean et al. (2010)—rate of mutational origi-
This immediately prompts questions about the nation, fitness effect, and frequency evolved—seem
causes of the 50-fold range in mutation rates evident very fundamental. What is known about these rela-
in Fig. 1.1—all for single-nucleotide mutations. That tionships, generally?
is, when faced with evidence that the course of According to standard accounts in the evolution-
evolution reflects what is mutationally likely, one is ary literature, Darwin discovered the principle of
naturally concerned with the causes of those ten- selection, and by 1930, Fisher, Haldane, and Wright
dencies. Yet, in the case of MacLean et al. (2010), combined this principle with genetics to yield a
no attempt was made to predict or understand such general framework for understanding evolutionary
effects. causes. Thus, if we were to guess at the answers
In Chapter 9, we review additional evidence— to the questions in the previous paragraph, we
both from experimental evolution, and from nat- would begin by supposing that Haldane, Fisher, and

Mutation, Randomness, and Evolution. Arlin Stoltzfus, Oxford University Press (2021). © Arlin Stoltzfus. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198844457.003.0001
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

2 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

(a) Frequency evolved vs. fitness (b) Frequency evolved vs. mutation rate (c) Mutation rate vs. fitness

1e-07
50.0

50.0
R2 = 0.01, p = 0.77 R2 = 0.60, p = 0.0052 R2 = 0.01, p = 0.77
Frequency evolved

Frequency evolved

1e-08
Mutation rate
5.0

5.0

1e-09
0.5

0.5

1e-10
0.1

0.1
1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0 1e-10 5e-10 5e-09 5e-08 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.8 2.0
Fitness Mutation rate Fitness

Figure 1.1 Inter-relations of mutation rate, fitness effect, and frequency of evolution for 11 rifampicin-resistant variants (data from
MacLean et al., 2010).

Wright discovered the impact of biases in variation its power over our imagination has withered. Once
and developed the theory for it. this task is completed, we can begin to rebuild our
In fact, this is not the case at all. As we will understanding of the role of variation in evolution,
discover, Fisher, Haldane, and Wright each argued drawing on some available theory and data.
against the idea that the course of evolution The results of MacLean et al. (2010), and those of
might reflect internal tendencies of variation, on the more well known study of parallelism by Rokyta
the grounds that mutation rates are too small to et al. (2005), roughly fit the behavior expected from
have an appreciable effect. Classical population- origin-fixation models depicting evolution as a
genetics theory lacks an account of the causes and simple two-step process, with a rate determined
consequences of biases in the introduction process, by multiplying the rate of mutational introduction
as do the classic works of Mayr, Simpson, Stebbins, of new alleles by their probability of fixation. For
Dobzhansky, Huxley, and others. The kind of instance, for the 11 mutations from MacLean et al.
causation in which a bias in mutational origination (2010), the total rate of evolution can be represented
imposes a bias on evolution was formally described as a sum over 11 origin-fixation rates
just two decades ago.

11
How could such a basic idea escape recognition r= μik Nπik (1.1)
for so long? As will become clear, the effects of k=1
the introduction (origination) process fall within a denoting the parental genotype as i and the
blind spot or gap in evolutionary thinking. This alternatives with k. Here, μN is a rate of origin
blind spot is not accidental: it represents the shadow (mutation rate times population size), and π is a
cast by a dense nexus of arguments constructed probability of fixation. The chance that a particular
deliberately to promote and defend the belief that mutation j will be observed in a given replicate is a
variation is merely a source of random raw mate- fraction of that sum:
rials for selection—supporting a high-level view of
μij Nπij μij πij
selection as the potter and variation as the clay—and pj =  =  (1.2)
to discourage alternatives, particularly the idea that k μik Nπik k μik πik

evolution might exhibit internal tendencies due to This probability is linearly dependent on both the
the way that variation emerges. rate of mutational introduction, and the probability
A main task of this book is to document this nexus of fixation. Thus, for sites evolving according to
of arguments thoroughly, and then to deconstruct origin-fixation dynamics, the 50-fold range of rates
it. Because this nexus was built deliberately, over of mutation evident in Fig. 1.1 has an expected
decades, it cannot simply be excised or deflated with 50-fold effect on the chance of evolving. The 11
a single precise stroke: it must be attacked vigor- mutational changes have measured fitness effects
ously in all its manifestations, like a cancer, until ranging from s = 0.3 to s = 0.9, thus the probability
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

M U TAT I O N A L O R I G I N AT I O N A S A N E V O L U T I O N A RY C A U S E 3

1−e −2s
of fixation, using Kimura’s formula π = 1−e −2Ns ,
That is, some evolutionary geneticists have
ranges less than 2-fold from 0.45 to 0.83 (assuming rejected the idea that all of evolution, including
N = 106 ). Under these conditions, the difference- long-term and large-scale changes, follows from
making power of mutation is strong and that of the kind of selection-driven process of shifting
selection is modest (with more data, one expects to allele frequencies that one sees in experimental
see a correlation between frequency evolved and populations of animals and plants over small
fitness). numbers of generations. This extrapolationist
By contrast, an influence of mutation bias on the doctrine is usually expressed by stating that
outcome of evolutionary adaptation is not expected macroevolution follows from microevolution (see
under the theory that adaptation results from Dobzhansky, 1937, p. 12).
shifting the frequencies of alleles already present in The implications of this foundational shift are
an initial population. For instance, if all 11 variant still emerging, and they have not penetrated very
rpoB alleles are present initially, the outcome of far into evolutionary thinking. The orthodoxy that
evolution will be essentially deterministic, with the emerged in the mid-twentieth century depends for
fittest allele prevailing every time. Mutational shifts its validity on rejecting the view that the outcome of
among pre-existing alleles may occur, but because evolution reflects the timing and character of indi-
mutation rates are so small, their influence will vidual mutational events, and instead, embracing
be negligible compared to the much larger shifts the view that evolution is a higher-level mass-action
caused by selection. process of shifting allele frequencies in a population.
The notion that natural populations maintain an Over the years, this position has been quietly
abundant stock of variation, so that selection never abandoned, and is no longer a foundation of evolu-
has to wait for a new mutation—the “gene pool” tionary genetics. As a result, there is a curious discon-
theory—was a key conceptual innovation of the nect between what formal models imply about the possible
Modern Synthesis, providing the rationale to rede- dispositional role of variation in evolution, and the
fine evolution as a selection-driven shift in the fre- guidance provided by familiar verbal theories that depict
quencies of alleles. mutation as merely the ultimate source of raw materials
Yet, in the 1960s, as soon as this shifting-gene- for selection, or as a weak force incapable of influencing
frequencies view became an established orthodoxy, the outcome of evolution. Of particular interest here is
molecular sequence comparisons prompted bio- that, when the dynamics of evolution depend on the
chemists to depict evolution quite differently, as a dynamics of the introduction process, evolutionary
process of the acceptance or rejection of individual change is biased by mutation, in the sense that, if
mutations. This led King and Jukes (1969) and the rate of mutation for A → B is greater than for
Kimura and Maruyama (1969) to propose origin- A → C, this elevates the chances of evolving from A
fixation models relating the rate of evolution to B relative to A to C. That is, a bias in mutational
directly to the rate of mutational introduction (see introduction is a prior bias on evolution.
McCandlish and Stoltzfus, 2014). For years, the Importantly, nonuniformities in individual muta-
significance of this development was muted by tion rates, as in MacLean et al. (2010), are not the
the sense that “molecular evolution” is a special only sources of biases in the introduction of variation.
case, an isolated world of neutrality irrelevant to For instance, in the study of laboratory adaptation
adaptation and other major issues. Yet, eventually, of bacteriophages by Rokyta et al. (2005) (see Ch. 9),
theoreticians interested in adaptation and other a Met → Ile change is observed repeatedly, due to
major issues began to remark on the inadequacy mutations at position 3850. The genetic code dic-
of treating evolution as a process of shifting allele tates that this particular amino acid change can take
frequencies, arguing instead that the dynamics of place by three different single-nucleotide mutations:
long-term evolution depend on discrete events by ATG → ATT, ATG → ATC, and ATG → ATA. By
which mutation introduces new types (Hartl and contrast, other amino acid pairs typically have only
Taubes, 1998; Eshel and Feldman, 2001; Yedid and one or two possible mutational paths interconnect-
Bell, 2002). ing them (e.g., Met → Val, ATG → GTG). Because of
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

4 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

this, the Met → Ile change has a kinetic advantage. and-altered-development, or (3) B and C are pheno-
Even if all rates of mutation from one codon to typically defined networks in genotype-space, and
another are the same, this amino acid change is states in B are 3 times more accessible from the
probabilized by having multiple mutational routes parental network A.
of origination. In fact, two of the three different Note that, when we invoked this kind of
mutational pathways at position 3580 are seen by causation to interpret the results of MacLean et al.
Rokyta et al. (2005). (2010), we did so within a distinctive explanatory
This is not a bias in the mechanism of mutation paradigm. Confronted with a spectrum of changes,
itself, but a bias in how mutations are expressed, each with an observed frequency (Fig. 1.1), our
formally identical to a kind of developmental bias focus was on explaining why evolution has the
suggested repeatedly in the evo-devo literature tendencies that it has. Molecular evolutionists are
(e.g., Emlen, 2000), by which some phenotypes familiar with this paradigm—as old as Dayhoff’s
are more likely to arise by mutation-and-altered- empirical matrices of amino acid replacement—in
development because they have more mutationally which evolution is a process with propensities, and
accessible genotypes. Molecular and morphological our job as evolutionists is to predict and explain
versions of this proposal are united by the concept of these propensities.
a genotype-phenotype (GP) map. The genetic code The traditional approach, by contrast, is to estab-
is the GP map that relates triplet genotypes to amino lish a plausible narrative for a unique evolutionary
acid phenotypes. Disrupting the ATG genotype outcome that is considered as a conclusion or end-point,
underlying the methionine phenotype is more likely i.e., what Sober (1984) calls “equilibrium explana-
to result in the isoleucine phenotype, accessible tion.” As Reeve and Sherman (1993) put it, the focus
via three mutations, than valine, accessible by one of the adaptationist research program is on explain-
mutation. ing “phenotype existence,” e.g., why the zebra has
Likewise, if we generalize further on this effect, its stripes. The paradigm of an explanation is to
we can understand the basis of arguments in the lit- show that the observed phenotype is the most fit
erature of self-organization and evolvability about possible, given the various constraints at work. This
the differential accessibility of alternative pheno- paradigm has had a profound influence on concep-
types in genotype-space (Fontana, 2002). Concepts tions of explanation and causation.
like genetic proximity or mutational accessibility are To apply the traditional paradigm to MacLean
relevant to evolution precisely because the evolu- et al. (2010), one would begin with the observa-
tionary exploration of genetic spaces is subject to tion of a single instance, a token outcome, as if
kinetic biases due to mutation. we have only a single rifampicin-resistant strain,
That is, whereas the patterns of mutation-biased e.g., the one with arginine at site 518. The existence
adaptation in MacLean et al. (2010) are specifically of this amino acid would be credited to the role
(1) an effect of asymmetries in mutation rates, and of selection shifting the Arg518 allele deterministi-
do not represent (2) asymmetries in developmental cally from a low frequency to a high frequency, e.g.,
responses to perturbation, nor (3) asymmetries in we could use the measured selection coefficient to
the density and accessibility of genotype networks, model the dynamics of allele replacement, and we
all three kinds of asymmetries are potential sources of could test this experimentally by examining how
biases in the introduction of variation. If, starting from selection increases the frequency of the Arg518 allele
state A, the rate of introduction of B is three times from low to high.
higher than C, the expected evolutionary conse- By contrast to this deterministic appeal to selec-
quences of this 3-fold bias are the same whether tion, the involvement of the Arg518 allele would
(1) B and C are unique genetic alternatives, and be described (in the traditional paradigm) by refer-
the differential effect reflects mutation bias per se, ence to a mutation that occurred by chance at some
(2) B and C are alternative phenotypic states, and time in the past. Evolution was “contingent” on
(aggregating effects over the entire mutation spec- the presence of this allele in the gene pool of the
trum) B is three times more accessible via mutation- starting population, so that selection could raise
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

W H AT T H I S B O O K I S A B O U T 5

its frequency deterministically from low to high. If process have biological causes and evolutionary
some other allele, e.g., leucine 531, provides greater consequences. Their causes reside in properties
rifampicin resistance, then our account of Arg518 of the mutation-generating system, properties of
would stress “constraints” or “limits” on the “power development, and broad features of the architecture
of selection” to achieve perfection (Barton and Par- of genetic spaces. The consequences of biases in
tridge, 2000). Our explanation would note that the the introduction process are in the province of
Arg518 allele was present in the gene pool, and the population genetics. Expanding our understanding
Leu531 allele (for instance) was absent, by chance. of population-genetic causation to include the
When we look at the traditional paradigm in this consequences of biases in the introduction of
way, we can see that it relies on the idealization that variation provides a cohesive and previously
selection deterministically ensures that the fittest unrecognized basis for addressing key concerns of
survives. As this idealistic paradigm has broken scientists interested in neutral evolution, evo-devo,
down, some evolutionary thinkers have turned to evolvability, and self-organization.
denoting exceptions by appealing to chance, contin- Re-thinking the evolutionary role of varia-
gency, and constraints (e.g., Futuyma, 2010). tion along these lines is a major challenge for
These concepts make it possible to rescue the tra- twenty-first-century evolutionary biology. A broad
ditional paradigm, but only superficially. Chance, approach to this challenge would require a book
constraints, and contingency do not denote causal much larger than this one, and it would necessarily
theories to account for evolutionary dispositions leave many issues unresolved, dependent on
or preferences. Chance is not a cause of anything. experiments that have not yet been designed or
Contingency is not a causal force. Constraints do carried out. To respond adequately to this challenge
not cause outcomes, but explain nonoutcomes, and will require the work of many scientists over many
in the case of mutation biases, they fail even to be years.
explanatory (there is no constraint preventing muta- This book focuses more narrowly on the
tions that occur at lower rates—they simply occur development and application of basic principles,
at lower rates). That is, these concepts are explana- relying on molecular examples to establish key
tory rather than causal: they refer not to pistons or arguments. Rather than fully answering the grand
levers, but to excuses. They are not alternative theo- challenge of rethinking the role of variation, it aims
ries, but verbal markers indicating departures from to prepare the ground by (1) illustrating some of the
ideals of determinacy and equilibration. Their use complexity of mutational processes and using that
in the evolutionary literature represents the unsta- information to explain why biases are inevitable,
ble transition-state between a failed paradigm and and why various precise senses of randomness
some alternative. fail to apply, (2) showing that the mutation-is-
That is, these concepts fail to satisfy the scientific random claim common in evolutionary discourse is
imperative to explore causal theories in which best understood in terms of a historically popular
quantities such as mutation rates are used to make view in which the internal details of mutation and
precise predictions. However, as demonstrated development are irrelevant to how evolution turns
earlier, a different and more suitable explanatory out, and (3) articulating an alternative view based
paradigm exists that allows us to treat variational on exploring propensities of variation as causes of
causes as causes, rather than as limits to the evolutionary propensities, and summarizing the
imaginary omnipotence of selection. current theoretical and empirical support for this
connection.
Mutation is often mischaracterized and misun-
1.2 What this book is about
derstood. For instance, the adjective “accidental” or
The recognition that biases in the introduction of “spontaneous” is often applied, but mutation is not
variation are a cause of evolutionary bias has far- an accident like a branch falling on the roof of your
reaching implications for evolutionary research and home during a storm and leaving a hole. Damage
for evolutionary theory. Biases in the introduction is not mutation. When cells leave unrepaired holes
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

6 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

in their DNA, the typical outcome is cellular death, that justifies the doctrine retroactively. We will
not mutation. Instead, mutation is like a branch devote considerable space to exploring these ideas,
falling on a house and leaving a hole in the roof, including the possible conditional independence of
followed by a repair-bot detecting the damage and mutations and fitness effects—conditional upon a
then shingling over the hole using the wrong color common environment. Yet, conditional indepen-
of shingles. The mutation is not the hole (which has dence and other attempts to make sense of the
been repaired), but the slight depression in the roof randomness doctrine either fail to match the facts
and the patch of differently colored shingles. of mutation, or fail to match what evolutionary
As will become apparent, mutations emerge by biologists have been saying.
complex pathways, often stimulated by damage, yet Other cases exist in which scientists have used
carried out by enzymes. No unified theory of muta- a concept for many years without a clear consen-
tion exists. To learn about mutation as a biological sus on its meaning. Indeed, the history of science
process is to learn about a vast assortment of dif- repeatedly shows that confusion or conflicts over
ferent processes that contribute to the emergence of the meaning of key concepts is normal and may per-
mutations. However, because teaching about muta- sist for generations. Scientists took centuries to settle
tion is not the main purpose of this book, no chap- on a common understanding of “heat.” The concept
ters are devoted specifically to mutation. Instead, of “probability” has proven enormously useful in
this book approaches the topic indirectly, describ- spite of two centuries of debate over what it means,
ing mutational processes in order to consider the whether it refers to something real, and whether
implications of randomness, and to illustrate key it can be derived from first principles. Many prac-
concepts (e.g., mutation spectrum) important for tically useful concepts, e.g., entropy, are subject to
conceptualizing mutation. rarefied disputes.
The doctrine that mutation is random is not what Yet probability, heat, and entropy are undoubtedly
it seems. Ordinary scientific claims typically are useful concepts: their use supports precise calcula-
justified by appeal to (1) first principles, which in tions that help us to understand the world bet-
this case might prohibit nonrandomness, or (2) sys- ter. What is the purpose of the randomness doc-
tematic observations or experiments, which in this trine? What precise and useful calculations does
case might have shown again and again, under it support? What logical conclusions depend on
a variety of conditions, that mutation is random. it? What advantage would be lost by rejecting it?
The first option is ruled out because the random- One often finds evolutionary thinkers urging cau-
ness doctrine long preceded any detailed knowl- tion, warning us that “random” is a problematic
edge of how mutation works—indeed, the claim word, yet if the subject requires caution, why take
is made by evolutionary biologists, not by muta- a position at all? These same authors do not feel
tion researchers. The second option seems unlikely obliged to stake out a carefully worded position
because sources that promote the randomness doc- on the randomness of anything else. Why did it
trine do not cite a large body of systematic evidence, become so important to associate mutation with
that is, one does not see statements like “mutation randomness?
has been shown to be completely random in a vari- A closer look at the classic Synthesis literature
ety of species (Smith, 1939; Johnson, 1944; Jones, reveals that randomness attributions co-occur with
1951).” other arguments that minimize the importance of
“Randomness” has many possible connotations, variation in evolution, and that these arguments all
and the literature of evolution draws on them refer to the same contrast-case: selection. Mutation is
in diverse ways. The situation has become so random, selection is not; mutation is weak, selection
confusing that, in the past 25 years, multiple is not; selection acts at the (right) population level,
authors—including professional philosophers— mutation acts at the (wrong) individual level; selec-
have waded into the confusion, aiming to sort out tion provides direction, variation merely provides
what evolutionary biologists really mean to say. The raw materials. In this context, the randomness doc-
typical approach is to assume that a special “evo- trine proclaims a deeper mutation-is-unimportant
lutionary” meaning of randomness can be found doctrine in which variation is made subservient to
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

W H AT T H I S B O O K I S A B O U T 7

selection, supporting the assignment of roles that As we will discover, the shifting-gene-frequencies
one finds in the topic article on “natural selection” theory underlying the sweeping claims made by
(Ridley, 2002) in the Oxford Encyclopedia of Evolution- the architects of the Modern Synthesis (see Box 6.2)
ary Biology: does not correspond to the open-ended framework
that some scientists imagine today, when they refer
In evolution by natural selection, the processes gener- to a mid-century “Synthesis.” To justify a neo-
ating variation are not the same as the process that Darwinian division of labor between variation
directs evolutionary change . . . What matters is that the
(source of raw materials) and selection (source
mutations are undirected relative to the direction of
of creativity, direction, etc), the shifting-gene-
evolution. Evolution is directed by the selective process
(p. 799).
frequencies theory of evolution posits a “buffet”
view of population genetics, designed precisely
In this way, the randomness doctrine provides a to circumscribe the role of mutation, in which
metaphysical guarantee of the classic dichotomy of everything selection needs to adapt to current
selection and variation as the potter and the clay, circumstances is already present in the gene pool,
that is, it differentiates selection, the source of order, in carefully maintained abundance. Contemporary
shape, and direction, from mutation—not the source thinking still relies on terms and concepts from
of those things, because it’s “random.” Patterns and this narrow theory, including a “forces” theory that
interesting features and other orderly outcomes seems to rule out a dispositional role of mutation
in evolution may be safely attributed to selection, (on the grounds of being a “weak force” easily
because mutation is random. No ordinary definition overcome by selection), even though such a role
of randomness cleanly distinguishes one biological is perfectly compatible with a broader conception
process from another, thus a special “evolutionary” of evolutionary genetics.
definition is developed to fill this gap. The nature of The successful promotion of this theory by Ernst
the required “evolutionary” definition is now obvious: Mayr and his cohort of influencers left a blind spot
it must apply to mutation but not to selection, e.g., in the development of evolutionary thinking about
the randomness claim is interpreted to mean that mutation. Where one might expect to find a descrip-
mutation, unlike selection, does not invariably tion of the propensities of mutation (variation), and
increase fitness (Section 4.2; see Eble, 1999). the causal principles linking them to propensities of
The final aim of this book is to articulate an evolution—what we will call the source laws and con-
alternative view, and to make a case for its impor- sequence laws of variation—one instead finds a denial
tance. Evolution is change. The goal of evolutionary that any such principles exist. Theoretical and empiri-
research, in my opinion, is to understand change, cal results have been encroaching on this blind spot
and particularly to understand why some types for decades, with little overt recognition.
of changes happen more often than others. The In this book, we consider some simple theoretical
early geneticists, who first contemplated the results that are fundamental to understanding the
role of mutation in Mendelian populations, saw role of mutation and development in evolution, but
mutation as a difference-maker, as a potentially which are not explained in textbooks. We discover
important source of initiative, creativity, direction, that the introduction of variant forms by mutation-
and discontinuity in evolution (Stoltzfus and and-altered-development is a predictable cause of
Cable, 2014). This position was rejected by the nonrandomness in evolutionary change. We find
architects of the Modern Synthesis, who argued that this kind of cause can be modeled using prin-
that mutation is merely a random source of raw ciples of population genetics, and its effects can be
materials, and further claimed that the view held by studied using conventional scientific methods. Pat-
early geneticists—in which the course of evolution terns of change can have mutational causes, not simply
may reflect the timing and character of individual in the sense that mutation is materially necessary for
mutations—was incompatible with the genetics of evolution, but in the sense that tendencies of mutation
natural populations, which always have abundant can be difference-makers, causing one kind of thing to
standing variation to fuel evolution. happen more often than another.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

8 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

Box 1.1 TheoryA and theoryC

The concept of a theory plays an important role in evo- theoryA . Fisher (1930b) wrote that “No practical biologist
lutionary discourse. The term “theory” has been used in interested in sexual reproduction would be led to work
the sense of a grand conjecture for hundreds of years, out the detailed consequences experienced by organisms
and continues to be used this way in evolutionary biology, having three or more sexes; yet what else should he do if
e.g., Kimura’s “Neutral Theory” is the conjecture that most he wishes to understand why the sexes are, in fact, always
changes at the molecular level result from random fixation two?” (in fact, the sexes are not always two, but this is not
of selectively neutral alleles; the “Exon Theory of Genes” relevant here). The collection of all the models for different
(Gilbert, 1987) proposes that genes evolved from combining numbers of mating types would be part of the theoryA of
exon-minigenes; the endosymbiotic theory holds that mito- sexes. A concrete theoryC of sexes would be something quite
chondria and chloroplasts arose from primordial bacterial different, e.g., it might propose a causal explanation for the
endosymbionts. actual historic phenomenon of the origin and maintenance
However, the word “theory” does not always mean this. of sexual reproduction in animals.
Population genetics theory, for instance, is not the conjecture Although the distinction between theoryA and theoryC
that populations have genetics, nor is music theory the is not always clear, applying the distinction remains a use-
conjecture that music exists. Instead, these are bodies of ful exercise. For instance, the theory of kin selection (“kin
abstract principles. Indeed, scientific writings use the same selection theory” or “inclusive fitness theory”) is frequently
term for both (1) theoryC (concrete, conjectural), a grand described as a set of “tools” (Michod, 1982), implying
conjecture or major hypothesis to account for some set of theoryA . Yet, the context for the use of these tools is the
observed phenomena, as in the “continental drift theory” or broad conjecture of Hamilton that kin selection is crucial
“Lamarck’s theory of evolution,” and (2) theoryA (abstract, to account for the evolution of social behavior in animals.
analytical), a body of abstract principles relevant to some dis- Most of the disputes about kin selection theory are theoryA
cipline, methodology, or problem area, as in “music theory,” disputes among mathematicians and philosophers about
“quantum field theory,” or “population genetics theory.” such things as whether the assumptions underlying certain
Usually one must rely on context to determine which formulations of Hamilton’s rule are correctly described, or
meaning applies. For instance, a white paper on “The Role whether kin selection theoryA is equivalent with group selec-
of Theory in Advancing 21st Century Biology” (National tion theoryA (Birch and Okasha, 2014).
Academy of Sciences, 2007) emphasizes the development of Obviously, there is a connection between the two types
formalisms rather than conjectures, and says that “a useful of theories, in that abstract principles of theoryA , rendered
way to define theory [note the abstract noun] in biology is concrete with observed or conjectured values, can provide
as a collection of models,” clearly a reference to theoryA (the the basis of a theoryC . In the case of Kimura’s Neutral
report also refers to a few theoriesC ). Theory (Kimura, 1983), the theoryC —the conjecture that
The two types of theory are evaluated in different ways. most changes at the molecular level result from the random
The standard of truth for a theoryC is verisimilitude—how fixation of selectively neutral alleles—and theoryA were
well does it match the actual world? A theoryC takes developed somewhat separately. The definition of effec-
risks, and can be refuted by facts. Because a theoryC is a tively neutral alleles (perpetually misunderstood by critics)
conjecture—not necessarily a correct one—it still is called and the probability of fixation under pure drift had been
a “theory,” even by those who doubt its verisimilitude. By known for decades (see Wright, 1931; Fisher, 1930b, Ch. IV;
contrast, to evaluate a statement in theoryA , one does not Haldane, 1932, Appendix). Kimura combined mostly pre-
consider any facts about the world, but only whether the existing theoryA (including plausibility arguments based on
statement is correctly derived from its assumptions. Once a the “cost” of selection) with the concrete assertion that
piece of theoryA is valid (correctly derived), it remains valid the values of certain quantities (relating to population sizes
forever, even if it relies on imaginary things such as infinite and mutant effects) were such that, for DNA and protein
populations. sequences, neutral evolution by mutation and random fixa-
To derive expectations for some possibilities, prior to hav- tion would be far more common than anyone had imagined
ing any reason to prefer one over another, one requires some previously.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

WHO THIS BOOK IS FOR 9

Opponents of the Neutral Theory, who deny the truth world in which neutrality is true, i.e., the theoryA statement
of the theoryC , are nonetheless quite happy to make use X ⇒ Y must be abstractly true. The paradox in Kreitman’s
of its theoreticalA infrastructure in efforts to reject neutral title “The neutral theory is dead. Long live the neutral theory”
models, as in the review by Kreitman (1996). That is, valid is perfectly resolved by the fact that it refers first to theoryC ,
theoryA is required to carry out modus tollens reasoning, and then to theoryA .
in which X is rejected based on its implication X ⇒ Y In the remainder of this book, the distinction between
and the observation that Y is absent. In the case of neutral theoryA and theoryC is not made explicit except in a few
models, X = neutrality, and Y is some expectation about cases, so that the reader may apply the distinction and assess
rates or patterns. To reject neutrality based on evidence its utility, without suffering the annoyance of being forced
requires a correctly derived model of an imaginary abstract to do so.

1.3 Who this book is for For instance, for decades, even as evo-devo has
gained in popularity, others have appealed to pop-
In the process of untangling the conceptual mess ulation genetics—widely regarded as the language
at the intersection of mutation, randomness, and of causation in evolution—to argue that evo-devo
evolution, this book addresses various topics has not contributed any new principles or causes to
that are timely and of central importance to evolutionary thinking. In the absence of a general-
evolutionary biology. Nevertheless, the way that cause claim, attempts to justify evo-devo turned
the topics are framed may be unfamiliar, even to to fuzzy claims about alternative “narratives” and
professional scientists. I would not expect readers “explanatory paradigms.” In this book we discover
to have a clear sense of whether or not they might that classic arguments about causation used against
be interested in reading this book, based solely on evo-devo, such as Mayr’s “proximate cause” objec-
the title, or based on a phrase such as “biases in tion, Dobzhansky’s “wrong level” argument, or the
the introduction of variation,” or even based on the weak-pressure objection (e.g., Reeve and Sherman,
earlier reference to a conceptual mess. Therefore, it 1993), are inadequate, and this is not a matter of
may help to explain how the main arguments relate paradigms or reductionism, but a matter of making
to several issues that are more familiar. the wrong assumptions about population genetics,
First, in the past two decades, interest has and failing to recognize the introduction process as
emerged in taking a more detailed look at the role of an evolutionary cause with distinctive implications.
variation in evolution, including an interest in the The ability of generative processes to impose a bias
“arrival of the fittest” rather than the “survival of the on the outcome of evolutionary change is the first-
fittest,” apparent in discussions of developmental order cause implicitly at work in various evo-devo
constraints, evolvability, robustness, facilitated ideas about higher-order effects.
variation, and so on. Most of the previous interest Second, this book is tailor-made for those in
in this issue has been focused on development molecular evolution, microbiology, and compara-
of visible phenotypes of macroscopic organisms, tive genomics who feel that evolutionary biology
whereas my background, training, and inclinations has been stubbornly resistant to the lessons of the
are much more molecular than organismal. This molecular era, which has only partially shifted our
book presents a nontraditional view of the role of views of evolution when it should have transformed
variation that is firmly grounded in theory and in them. In this regard, several highly original books
empirical data, in which tendencies of evolution are have appeared recently, including Nei (2013)
related to tendencies of variation. It builds a founda- (mutation, not selection, drives evolution), Lynch
tion of basic concepts, which it then uses to address, (2007b) (nonadaptive mechanisms make genomes
and sometimes resolve, long-standing problems. complex), Shapiro (2011) (engineering, not accident,
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

10 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

provides innovation), and Koonin (2011) (after geneticists. Today theoreticians who make models
Darwinism, things get complicated). of this process call it “Darwinian adaptation” or
The present book shares something with each of “Darwinian evolution,” while Darwin and Fisher
these, though the overlap in content is small. Like roll over in their graves. In molecular evolution
Lynch, I am concerned to justify a novel position and evolutionary genetics, scientists frequently
on the causes of observed evolutionary patterns assume a form of mutation-limited dynamics
in terms of theoretical implications of population that directly contradicts the theory of shifting
genetics. Like Shapiro, Koonin, and Nei, I believe gene frequencies underlying the original Modern
that evolutionary thinking is deeply shaped by Synthesis.
vestiges of a neo-Darwinian view—selection and This has an important implication for high-
variation as the potter and the clay—that is broadly level debates on evolutionary theory. Most of
incompatible with the facts of molecular evolution. these debates seem to assume that evolutionary
More than any of these authors, I believe that biology must have a Grand Unifying Theory
progress depends on conceptual and cultural of Evolution covering all of biology. A shape-
reform, to include re-evaluating core concepts (“raw shifting “Synthesis” is then put forward, typically
materials,” “forces”), developing new concepts and defined, not as genuine scientific theory, but as a
metaphors to guide our thinking, changing what tradition consisting of people and their changing
is taught to students, and reforming the distorted distribution of beliefs: this puts an impossible
historiography of our field. burden on would-be reformers, who must come up
Third, every scientist, philosopher, or lay-person with an alternative that is (1) equally comprehen-
interested in evolution has surely encountered sive, and yet (2) obviously distinct from the shape-
the idea that, beginning in the 1980s, a high- shifting “Synthesis.” This debate has muddied the
level dispute has been simmering, regarding the waters and prevented reform for decades. In reality,
adequacy of a mid-twentieth-century orthodoxy the actual historic Modern Synthesis ceased to be a
formerly known as the “Modern Synthesis.” In valid universal theory some time in the 1970s: it was
recent years, this dispute has taken the form of not useful for understanding long-term sequence
a call for an “Extended Evolutionary Synthesis.” divergence, nor did its theory of recombination-
This book explains and thoroughly documents fueled change in the diploid sexual “gene pool”
the commitment of the architects of the Modern apply usefully to the asexual prokaryotic organisms
Synthesis to a mistaken conception of the role that have dominated the planet through most of its
of variation that remains deeply embedded in history. Evolutionary biology has not had a Grand
evolutionary thinking, e.g., in the “raw materials” Unified Theory for nearly 50 years. Apparently, one
doctrine, the “mutation is random” doctrine, and is not needed.
the “forces” theory. Finally, many scientific readers may be drawn
These historic commitments have been obscured to this book, due specifically to their interest in
by a subsequent process of normality-drift that the “directed mutation” or “adaptive mutation”
has perpetually redefined the “Synthesis” (and, to controversy that erupted in 1988 based on exper-
some extent, “neo-Darwinism”), creating a false iments by Cairns, Foster, Hall, and Shapiro, and
impression of permanence. We will see exactly their skepticism of the “mutation is random” claim.
how the meanings of key terms have changed, In brief, Cairns and others suggested that cells
e.g., “raw materials” used to be an analogy to have evolved ways of (probabilistically) generating
raw materials, and now is merely a synonym for situation-appropriate mutations, an argument that
“variation,” used even for mutations such as gene sets traditional thinking against itself, pitting a
duplications that are in no way analogous to raw hopeful belief in the adaptation of mutational
materials. Originally, the term “adaptation” did not mechanisms against the simplifying explanatory
implicate the lucky mutant view (the adventitious paradigm in which selection receives all the credit
fixation of a beneficial mutant), which was called for the hard work of evolution, on the grounds that
“pre-adaptation” and associated with pre-Synthesis mutation merely supplies random raw materials.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

HOW THE ARGUMENT UNFOLDS 11

The sustained hostile reaction to this idea bias, without ever considering specialized mutation
indicates the willingness of evolutionists to sacrifice systems.
a belief in the pervasiveness of adaptation so as to
preserve the neo-Darwinian explanatory dichotomy
1.4 How the argument unfolds
in which variation plays a strictly passive material
role. The focus of this book shifts significantly through
Readers who (like myself) followed the directed its three main parts. The first part, comprising
mutations controversy will be interested in several Chapter 2, Chapter 3, and Appendices A and
relevant points. First, CRISPR-Cas is unarguably B, addresses how well the biological process of
an evolved system that generates situation- mutation is described by some of the ordinary
appropriate mutations, and which contradicts meanings of “chance” or “randomness” in science:
conventional wisdom (e.g., Luria–Delbrück ran- lack of purpose or foresight, uniformity (homogene-
domness). Second, many systems for generating ity), stochasticity, indeterminacy, unpredictability,
situation-appropriate mutations have been reported spontaneity, and independence (chance).
in microbial pathogens, though they rarely receive Throughout this part, I refer to four pathways
attention from evolutionary thinkers, e.g., diversity- of mutation described in Appendix A, which
generating retro-elements, elaborate cassette- explains the process by which a T → C mutation
switching schemes, phase variation systems, and (1) arises from an error during genome replication,
multiple-inversion “shufflons.” Such systems often (2) arises from error-prone repair of damage, (3)
play a critical role in immune evasion or host- emerges symbolically in a computer-generated
phage arms races. Third, these systems do not Monte Carlo simulation, and (4) is engineered
generally exhibit the kind of nonrandomness in in a gene using human technology. Nearly all
which the chances of mutations are influenced by readers will benefit from reading Appendix A:
their incipient fitness effects, as was the case for the examples are provided specifically to build a
some models proposed for “directed mutations” foundation for explaining and evaluating concepts
(e.g., Cairns’s generalized reverse transcription of randomness. Computer-simulated mutations, for
model). Understanding the origin and maintenance instance, are fully deterministic and predictable
of these specialized mutation-generating systems (thus not “random” in those senses), but they
is a major challenge for scientists interested in the can be uniform and their use in a simulation
evolution of evolvability. can represent “chance." Human-engineered muta-
Thus, the random mutation doctrine breaks tions typically are not fully deterministic, but
down in two distinct ways, based on two distinct can be highly predictable, nonuniform, and
meanings of the doctrine: independence from nonindependent.
fitness, and explanatory irrelevance. Microbial Some basic concepts of randomness are recon-
pathogens have specialized systems of mutation sidered in a more practical context in Chapter 3.
that enhance the chances of mutations useful This chapter introduces the idea that some ways
for immune evasion, contrary to the doctrine of thinking about mutation are useful, even if they
that mutations occur statistically independently are only approximately correct. Approximations
of fitness. However, these contradictions will come at a cost, and thus the practical use of an
probably be viewed as exceptions, and they approximation, e.g., the assumption that mutation
will not win any arguments against the broader is uniform when it really is not, is a matter of weigh-
doctrine of chance variation, which really means ing costs and benefits. Chapter 3 also introduces the
that variation cannot be a dispositional factor idea that the application of probabilistic reasoning
in evolution. This version of the randomness to problems of mutation may be understood as
doctrine also breaks down, much more broadly, an extension of logic that does not rely on any
not just in microbes. As we will see, this break- concept of “randomness.” In this context, references
down can be documented by reference to ordinary to “chance” or “randomness” as something that
mutation biases such as transition-transversion exists in the physical world, rather than in our
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

12 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

minds, represent what E.T. Jaynes called a “mind mutation systems have been shown experimen-
projection fallacy.” tally to enhance long-term survival, thus they
The second part of the book, comprising Chapters represent legitimate examples of the evolution of
4, 5, and 6, along with Appendices C and D, focuses evolvability.
on what “mutation is random” means, or could In Chapter 6 we consider the randomness doc-
mean, in evolutionary discourse. The evolutionary trine in the context of a broader view of the irrele-
biologists and philosophers who have addressed vance of mutation, supported by a catalog of quota-
the issue frequently argue that the “mutation is tions in Appendix D. In this context, the “mutation
random” claim does not refer to the ordinary mean- is random” claim goes along with “raw materials,”
ings of randomness, but to a special “evolution- “weak force,” and so on, as one of a variety of claims
ary” sense, by which (1) the process of mutation to the effect that mutation, however necessary, is
is independent of selection, evolution, or adapta- inconsequential or uninteresting. Sometimes these
tion; or (2) the outcome of mutation is observed to other arguments are implicated as the explanation
be statistically uncorrelated with selection, evolu- for the randomness claim. Furthermore, every type
tion, or adaptation. Appendix C provides a catalog of argument about the unimportance of mutation
of statements by evolutionary thinkers referring to has the same contrast case: selection. The arguments
mutation and randomness. all support a dichotomy in which selection is cre-
Chapter 4 reviews these ideas and shows that ative, influential, important, predictable, and so on,
nearly all of them fail for relatively obvious rea- whereas mutation is none of those things.
sons. For instance, adaptation depends on muta- Chapter 7 is an interlude in which we consider
tion and so is not independent of it; when selec- the problem of variation in evolutionary theory
tion and mutation occur in the same milieu, they more broadly, before proceeding to devote two
are subject to common factors and thus not inde- chapters to a specific theory about biases in
pendent. Only two of these “evolutionary” ideas variation. Under the classical neo-Darwinian view
survive initial scrutiny. One of them is that “muta- that variation merely plays the role of supplying
tion is random” signifies the rejection of a view in random infinitesimal raw materials, with no
which the process of variation is pervasively biased determinative impact on the course of evolution,
toward adaptation, regularly generating situation- a substantive theory of form and its variation
appropriate mutations. Another promising idea is a is not required to specify a complete theory of
recent proposal that refers to the independence of evolution. Alas, reality is not so simple. This view
selection and mutation given (i.e., conditional on) a has been breaking down from the moment it
common environment. was proposed, and is now seriously challenged
In Chapter 5, we consider some specialized by results from evo-devo, comparative genomics,
mutation systems in microbes, in relation to molecular evolution, and quantitative genetics. To
the randomness doctrine and the “evolvability” address a dispositional role of variation in evolution
literature. The evolvability research front tends will require, at minimum, an understanding of
to focus on three types of claims concerning (1) tendencies of variation (source laws), and an under-
the efficacy of internal factors to shape evolution, standing of how those tendencies affect evolution
(2) the structural principles that account for (consequence laws).
differences in evolvability, and (3) the emergence In Chapter 8, we explore the theoretical possibil-
of evolved systems with enhanced evolvability. ity that variational tendencies are consequential in
In the microbiological literature, CRISPR-Cas evolution by way of biases in the introduction of
spacer acquisition, cassette shuffling, diversity- variation. In the classic view of evolutionary genet-
generating retroelements, and multiple inversion ics, mutation cannot be a source of directionality
shufflons are all depicted as evolvability features, in evolution because mutation rates are too small
i.e., mutation strategies that facilitate long-term to overcome the opposing pressure of selection: for
survival, e.g., enhancing immune evasion by anti- mutational tendencies to influence evolution would
genic variation. In a number of cases, specialized require either the absence of selection (i.e., neu-
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

SYNOPSIS 13

tral evolution), or unusually high mutation rates. 1.5 Synopsis


However, subsequent theoretical work shows that
The following represents a brief guide to the book,
this way of thinking is based on assuming a “buf-
which has three parts that correspond roughly to the
fet” regime in which the alleles relevant to the out-
three combinations of terms
come of evolution are already abundantly present
in an initial population. Instead, one may imagine • mutation and randomness—how does the biolog-
a “sushi conveyor” regime in which evolution is a ical process of mutation seem random, or not?
two-step proposal-acceptance process, i.e., a process • randomness and evolution—what role does the
that follows the classic mutationist mantra, “muta- concept of “random variation” play in evolution-
tion proposes, selection disposes.” When the out- ary thinking?
come of evolution depends on the introduction of • mutation and evolution—what is the role of
novel forms, mutational and developmental biases mutation in evolution, and particularly, the role
may impose biases on evolution, and this does not of mutational tendencies?
require neutral evolution, absolute constraints, or
high mutation rates. The main goal of the first part is to build a foun-
In Chapter 9, we shift from theory to evidence. dation of knowledge and understanding about the
Readers familiar with molecular evolution will nature of mutation, and apply that to evaluating the
be aware that genome composition and other merit of common statements about the randomness
aggregate properties reflect effects of mutation bias. of mutation.
Claims of mutational effects have been featured in
• In Ordinary randomness (Ch. 2), we draw
the literature of molecular evolution for 50 years,
on mutation research and the exemplars in
usually in association with claims about neutral
Appendix A to probe ordinary ideas of ran-
evolution. In this chapter, however, we are only
domness such as uniformity, independence,
interested in changes associated with adaptation.
spontaneity, indeterminacy, and so on.
We examine cases in which adaptive changes have
• In Practical randomness (Ch. 3), we briefly draw
been traced to the molecular level, and the evidence
some practical conclusions, and also consider
shows that the mutations involved in adaptation
(1) randomness as a strategy for generating
are enriched for kinetically favored mutations, that
null hypotheses, and (2) randomness as a mind
is, the ones with higher rates of occurrence. The
projection fallacy that is not necessary for
ability of ordinary mutation biases to influence
reasoning under uncertainty.
adaptive evolution—without requiring neutrality,
absolute constraints, or high mutation rates— Whereas the first part considers the relation of
confirms a key prediction of the theory developed in mutation and randomness as a question of biology
Chapter 8. and plausible reasoning, without much attention to
In Chapter 10, we end by reviewing what has been evolution, the second part is specifically about the
learned and considering it in the context of broader role that the randomness doctrine plays in evolu-
issues in evolutionary biology. Looking back over tionary thinking and research.
the previous chapters, it will now be possible to
make some clearer statements about mutation • In Evolutionary randomness (Ch. 4), we consider
and the idea of randomness itself, randomness the idea that randomness has a special “evolu-
and its role in evolutionary theories, and the tionary” meaning. Most versions of this idea can-
role of mutation in evolution. The material in not be justified by logic or evidence; and some of
the first nine chapters also provides a basis to the justifiable ideas (e.g., mutation is not caused
reflect on the nature of explanations (explanatory by future events) are not particularly useful for
paradigms), the role of verbal theories in accounts reasoning.
of causation, and the importance of discerning • Mutation systems and evolvability (Ch. 5)
theories and distinguishing them from people and probes several more challenging topics, includ-
traditions. ing evolved systems that generate situation-
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 15/2/2021, SPi

14 INTRODUCTION: A CURIOUS DISCONNECT

appropriate mutations, and their relationship to theory without a substantive theory of form
the topic of evolvability. and its variation? What is the current basis for
• In Randomness as irrelevance (Ch. 6) we con- abandoning this premise?
sider a variety of metaphors, analogies, mecha- • In Climbing Mount Probable (Ch. 8), we con-
nistic arguments, empirical arguments, explana- sider the conceptual and population-genetic basis
tory arguments, and methodological arguments, for understanding the introduction of variation
all to the effect that mutation is just not worth by mutation (or, for phenotypes, by mutation-
your time. Appendix D is a catalog of supporting and-altered-development) as a source of initiative
quotations. and direction in evolution.
• In the Revolt of the clay (Ch. 9), we review
The final part of the book draws heavily on recent
results, largely from recent work, that provide
work that is familiar only to a small fraction of evo-
support for previously unacknowledged roles
lutionary biologists. This part focuses on building
of mutation in evolution, finding strong evidence
the conceptual, theoretical, and empirical basis of
that mutation biases are important in determining
an alternative theory of variation as a dispositional
the course of adaptive evolution.
factor in evolution.
• We begin by defining The problem of variation The final chapter, Moving on (Ch. 10), includes a
(Ch. 7): what happens after we abandon the summary of key points, and reflections on theories
premise that we can build an evolutionary and explanatory agendas.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/2/2021, SPi

CHAPTER 2

Ordinary randomness

R.A. Fisher (1930) has assumed that mutation occurs in every conceivable direction; and some of
the most important of his conclusions regarding the outcome of natural selection, and the degree
of adaptation of a species at any moment, depend upon the correctness of that assumption.
There are many things, however, which indicate that in the deal out of mutations the cards are
stacked. A. Franklin Shull (1936)

2.1 Introduction mutations. Appendix B establishes this point by


mapping out the universe of mutations, providing
A convenient simplification, pervasive in the
formulas to estimate the number of mutations in
research literature, is to divide mutations into (1)
each category. This appendix is also useful for
one set representing common mutations, typically
explaining what is meant by point mutations,
comprising all single-nucleotide substitutions or
insertions, deletions, inversions, transpositions
point mutations (Section B.3), which typically are
(translocations), lateral transfers, and compound
assumed to occur uniformly and independently,
mutations.
and (2) other mutations, which are ignored. This
A second aspect of complexity is that, for any spe-
simplification is especially helpful if one has no
cific type of mutation, the mutations may emerge by
interest in understanding the role of mutation in
distinct mechanisms, and their occurrence typically
evolution, but must include it as a nuisance factor,
violates the usual simplifying assumptions about
i.e., a factor that is required to make a model
uniformity, homogeneity, and independence.
work, but whose effects are not relevant to testing
This chapter focuses on the latter aspect of
hypotheses or explaining interesting behavior.
complexity, mostly in regard to nucleotide sub-
The focus of this book, however, is the evolution-
stitution mutations. The material is structured by
ary role of the process of mutation (and of varia-
reference to various connotations of “randomness”
tion, more broadly). The goal is not to marginalize
or “chance” in science, including lack of purpose
mutation, but to make it a focus of research, perhaps
or foresight, uniformity or homogeneity (lack of
even the focus of a research program motivated
bias or structure), stochasticity, indeterminacy,
by the potential breadth and power of mutational
unpredictability, spontaneity, and independence
explanations for evolutionary outcomes.
(chance). This chapter addresses each concept in
Thus, in the book, we take steps to confront the
turn, considers what it means, and how it might
complexity of mutation, and to explore ways to inte-
apply to mutation (in subsequent chapters, we
grate that complexity into evolutionary thinking. consider the notion of a special “evolutionary”
One aspect of this complexity is that the typically meaning of randomness). To supplement this
ignored class of “other” mutations—including material, Appendix A provides four exemplars of a
insertions, deletions, inversions, transpositions, T → C nucleotide substitution mutation: an error
lateral transfers, and compound mutations— during genome replication; error-prone repair of
actually represents the vast majority of possible DNA induced by damage; a symbolic mutation in

Mutation, Randomness, and Evolution. Arlin Stoltzfus, Oxford University Press (2021). © Arlin Stoltzfus. DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198844457.003.0002
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

16 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

a computer simulation; and a human-engineered as to learn patterns, or to apply an internal model


mutation. of the world that can be used for generalized, adap-
tive learning. If this is what evolutionary biologists
mean by the randomness claim, they are saying that
2.2 Lacking in foresight
natural mutation systems cannot have evolved in
An obvious meaning of chance or randomness in such a way as to leverage past experience, so as
evolutionary writings is that mutations must reflect to learn valuable patterns of mutation. Mutation
a nonintelligent, mechanistic process that does not researchers (as opposed to evolutionary biologists)
have a purpose, move toward a goal, or antici- have often endorsed precisely this idea (e.g., Rosen-
pate future needs (e.g., Dickinson and Seger, 1999). berg and Hastings, 2004; Shapiro, 2011). Box 2.2
Note that this is a negative definition: it refers to introduces this notion using the example of shuf-
the absence of something. A variety of statements fling of antigen genes in Trypanosoma brucei. The
by evolutionary biologists (see Appendix C) can topic is addressed in greater detail in Chapter 5.
be interpreted as suggesting a lack of foresight or Note that, although mechanistic processes do
future causation, e.g., “Mutation is random in that not have goals, a dynamical system may show
the chance that a specific mutation will occur is not behavior in which the system predictably moves
affected by how useful that mutation would be” toward an “attractor” state from a large area of
(Futuyma, 1979, p. 249). Sober (1984) says that “The state-space (the attractor’s “basin of attraction”).
defensible idea in the claim that mutation is random A simple one-dimensional example would be a
is simply that mutations do not occur because they deterministic population-genetic model of alleles
would be beneficial” (p. 105). Here, “would be” A and a, in which the frequency of A converges
indicates the conditional future, i.e., the future that to a particular value f (the attractor), as in the
might happen. classic mutation-selection balance equation f = μ/s
One way to interpret such claims is that they (Crow and Kimura, 1970). We can imagine a
are rejections of backwards causation, from the variety of population-genetic models with this
future to the present, e.g., this is the most obvious property, including a pure mutation model (e.g.,
interpretation of the words “because they would a balance of forward and reverse mutation rates),
be beneficial.” This concept of randomness makes thus the capacity of a dynamic system to converge
the statement “mutation is random” a metaphysical (exhibiting what seems like goal-directed behavior)
claim: once one accepts a universe without future- under the influence of some process does not
causation, one may deduce that mutation—along distinguish mutation from other processes.
with disease, foul weather, and every other
process—is “random.” As Sober (1984) says, “One
2.3 Uniformity or lack of pattern
might just as well say that the weather occurs at
random, since rain doesn’t fall because it would Modern probability theory had its origins in the
be beneficial” (p. 105). This meaning would make seventeenth century, in the context of the need for
it problematic when evolutionary biologists say (as rational actions or decisions in the face of uncer-
they often do) that mutation is random but selection tainty (Gigerenzer et al., 1989). Given that the out-
is not. come of a possible investment is uncertain, how
Another interpretation of such claims is that they does a rational investor behave? Given that the testi-
are based on a dualist philosophy in which one may mony of witnesses is uncertain, how may a rational
attribute a capacity for foresight to minds, but not judge decide? Given that the chances of a gamble are
to mutation systems or other things that are not uncertain, what is the rational basis of making a bet?
minds, i.e., “because it would be beneficial” means Once one replaces certainty with uncertainty, the
“because it is judged (predicted, expected) to be first challenge in formulating a quantitative theory
beneficial.” This is different from future causation. of action or decision-making is to define what is
Human foresight does not require future causation, meant by the probability of an outcome. As Gigeren-
but only some ability to leverage past experience so zer et al. (1989) explain, the mathematicians who
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

U N I F O R M I T Y O R L A C K O F PAT T E R N 17

set out to define probabilities came up with three uniformity would be defined relative to this total set
approaches that we still use today: “equal possibili- of paths.
ties based on physical symmetry; observed frequen- Typically, mutations are identified by the topol-
cies of events; and degrees of subjective certainty or ogy and scale of the change, e.g., a 2-bp deletion,
belief” (p. 5). Laplace developed a system based on a 10-kb inversion, a single-nucleotide substitution,
the first case, in which the possibilities are all equal, and so on. The rates of these types of mutation
as in the rolling of a fair die or the drawing of a are not all the same: they occur at widely varying
card from a well-shuffled deck. More generally, the rates, as illustrated in Fig. 2.1, which shows a range
distribution of outcomes is said to be uniform when of ten orders of magnitude in the average rates
a process (a trial or experiment) has many possible for various types of mutations in humans. Short
outcomes, each with equal probability. tandem repeats or STRs, like the repeats of CAG
This corresponds to one meaning of randomness found in some genes, typically mutate at rates on the
as uniformity or homogeneity, i.e., sampling from order of 10−3 per generation, with most mutations
the universe of possibilities without preference. adding or subtracting a single repeat unit (Weber
Whereas this concept of randomness is easily stated, and Wong, 1993). Presumably the rates for some
generating uniform random outcomes requires an epigenetic mutations, like changes in methylation
actual procedure, and finding an efficient procedure states, are even higher.
is challenging. The table of random digits that one Small insertions occur less often than small
finds in the back of a classic statistics textbook deletions, and for either type of mutation, the
typically was produced by rolling dice. The chal- rate decreases with length, by a power law. The
lenge of generating random numbers has led to the rates in Fig. 2.1 are based on the power-law
development of numerous computational random relationship in Lynch (2010), although a nearly
number generators, and to the development of identical relationship is apparent in Fig. 2.2 based
numerous tests for nonuniformities and serial on the accumulation of indels in pseudogenes
correlations (see Appendix A). (see Yampolsky and Stoltzfus, 2008). Deletions
Random number generators, or more properly, (triangles) accumulate 4-fold faster than insertions
pseudo-random number generators (PRNGs), are (pluses), but the power-law relationship for both is
engineered to be superficially random in the sense similar in slope. Because these changes take place
of producing sequences of uniform uncorrelated in pseudogenes, their rates are assumed to reflect
numbers. A PRNG generates an endless (but recur-
ring) series of numbers from a formula of the form
xi+1 = f (xi ), carefully chosen so that statistical tests
fail to uncover deviations from an equal chance of STR repeat number
–2

drawing a number from any equally sized interval DMD duplication


(Brent, 2007). Appendix A (Section A.3) provides
large-CNV exposure
–4
Rate per generation (log10)

an example formula, along with a more detailed


transition at CpG site
description of PRNGs and their uses.
–6

substitution
When “random” refers to uniformity, “mutation
is random” means that the process of mutation 1-bp deletion
–8

ensures that probabilities are uniformly distributed 1-bp insertion


over the space of possible outcomes. For instance,
–10

3-bp insertion
a common assumption is that mutation has a
Alu insertion
uniform probability per genomic site, so that the
–12

9-bp insertion
rate of mutation for a genomic segment, such as a
gene, may be computed from its length alone (e.g., 36-bp insertion
–14

Houle, 1998). Alternatively, the space of mutational


outcomes could be defined as the set of paths Figure 2.1 Some rates of mutation that span 10 orders of
from the current genotype to mutants, so that magnitude (see text for sources).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

18 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

10000 T T T
T T T T T T
A G A G A G
G C G C G C
y = 4077 x–1.682 T A T A T A
1000
R2 = 0.96 T A T A T A
G C G C G C
T G T G T G
Count

C G C G C G
100 A T A T A T
C G C G C G
y = 1113 x–1.616 C G C G C G
A A A thyA131 T A
R2 = 0.92 G C
10 C G C
C G
G C G C G
G C G C
G A thyA124-127 T A
1 A A T A
A
0.1 1 10 100 A G G
Length (nucleotides) T A G G
C G T T
Figure 2.2 The length distribution of short insertions and deletions C G 5’ 5’
in pseudogene divergence (see Yampolsky and Stoltzfus, 2008). A T
3’ 5’

Figure 2.3 Model of mutations templated by an imperfect


the mutation rate (without any differential effect of palindrome (quasipalindrome) in the antisense strand of E. coli thyA
selection). (after Fig. 1a of Dutra and Lovett, 2006). If the hairpin (left) begins to
Robust estimates are not available for the average form during an interruption in DNA replication (center), continued
rate of per-locus duplication in humans. Instead, strand synthesis (grey dotted arrow) may result in two different
mutations (right), the thyA131 mutation from A to T (T to A on the
Fig. 2.1 shows the rate of copy-number variation
sense strand), and the thyA124-127 mutation from GGAA to T (TTCC
(CNV) exposure of 5 × 10−6 , which is the chance that to A on the sense strand).
a base-pair will be included in a large duplication
(Campbell and Eichler, 2013). This per-bp rate will
be less than the per-locus rate, but will be very Due to the quasipalindrome, a nascent strand may
close when loci are much smaller than duplications. fold back on itself during DNA synthesis, so that
An example of a rate of duplications for a single mutations are templated by base-pairing. Mutations
locus would be the rate of 1 × 10−5 reported by van of this type have been implicated in a number of
Ommen (2005) for the aggregate rate of duplications human diseases (Bissler, 1998). This process shows a
of the Duchenne muscular dystrophy (DMD) locus. strand-asymmetry due to differences in replication
Even within a single class of mutations, rates of leading and lagging strands (Kim et al., 2013).
are not uniform, as emphasized in recent analyses Golding (1987) looked for, and found, evidence that
(Hodgkinson and Eyre-Walker, 2011; Johnson and such templated mutations are important in natural
Hellmann, 2011; Nevarez et al., 2010; Cooper et al., divergence.
2011). For instance, we previously learned that Likewise, the endpoints of rearrangements are
MacLean et al. (2010) found a 50-fold range of not uniformly distributed among all sites in the
mutation rates among just 11 single-nucleotide genome, but frequently map to repeated sequences.
changes that lead to rifampicin resistance (see This applies both to large rearrangements (Love
Fig. 1.1). et al., 1991; Morris and Thacker, 1993; Kidd et al.,
In some cases, the reasons for context-dependent 2010; Conrad et al., 2010) and to short insertions
nonuniformity are understood. For instance, Dutra and deletions (Ball et al., 2005; Kondrashov and
and Lovett (2006) show that a mutational hotspot Rogozin, 2004), which are often strongly associated
in the thyA gene of Escherichia coli, responsible for in genomic location with short “homopolymeric”
most of the mutations in the gene, is associated with sequences, i.e., repeats of the same nucleotide
the quasipalindromic sequence shown in Fig. 2.3. (Schroeder et al., 2016). In the mutation research
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

U N I F O R M I T Y O R L A C K O F PAT T E R N 19

literature, such patterns typically are not described of the deletion between points A and B is higher to
as mutation biases, because the focus typically is on the extent that A and B have a matching sequence
dissecting the mechanism for a specific mutation, context.
not on providing modelers with generalizations Among nucleotide substitution mutations, tran-
about rates. However, descriptions of patterns are sitions (A ↔ G or C ↔ T) generally occur at a rate
readily translated into generalized statements about several-fold higher than transversions (Stoltzfus
rates, e.g., to say that repeats typically are found and Norris, 2016; Katju and Bergthorsson, 2019).
at the endpoints of deletions is to say that the rate Among the many known effects of context on

(a)
7
Log chi-squared value
5 4 6

–200 –100 0 100 200


Position relative to coincident SNP

(b)
7
Log chi-squared value
5 4 6

–200 –100 0 100 200


Position relative to SNP

Figure 2.4 Sitewise heterogeneity of triplet frequencies at sites where humans share (above) or do not share (below) a SNP with chimpanzees
(see text for explanation). Figure from Hodgkinson et al. (2009), reproduced under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0)
license.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

20 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

substitution mutations, one may include the higher (upper panel), heterogeneity is highly unusual over
mutability of CpG sites (Boland and Christman, a surprisingly long distance.
2008; Cooper et al., 2011; Shen et al., 1994; see
Section 9.4 for a brief explanation), effects of
other immediately upstream and downstream
2.4 Stochastic or probabilistic
nucleotides (Blake et al., 1992; Krawczak et al., 1998),
and heightened rates in runs of the same nucleotide In mathematics, a “random” or “stochastic” variable
(e.g., TTTTT), and in the vicinity of direct or inverted does not have a unique value, but may take on many
repeats (Gordenin et al., 1993; Wojcik et al., 2012). values, each of which may have an associated proba-
Some heterogeneity is not attributable to the few bility, i.e., Pr(X = xi ) = pi . Stochasticity has nothing
sites immediately upstream and downstream of to do with independence, e.g., we could define a
a mutated site. To assess the amount of cryptic variable x that is simply the sum of the values of
variability in mutation rates along the genome, all other variables in a system of interest, plus a
Hodgkinson et al. (2009) identified cases in which stochastic error term, making x a stochastic variable
a SNP occurs at precisely the same site in human whose value is dependent on, and correlated with,
and chimp populations. They found twice as all other system variables.
many matching SNPs as expected under a triplet This mathematical concept has no consistent
model, i.e., a model that addresses only effects physical meaning: we may find it convenient to use
of neighboring upstream and downstream sites, a stochastic variable x to represent the outcome of
including the CpG effect. They estimate that “the any process, including a fully deterministic one that
variance due to simple context, including CpGs, is is subjectively unpredictable (see Section 2.6), or
0.59, whereas the variance due to cryptic variation when the causes of variability in x are not of interest,
at non-CpG sites is 1.05.” Because the vast majority relative to something else that depends on the
of the coincident SNPs are not in coding regions, variability of x. For instance, in population genetics,
and because the SNPs are not actually clustered selection coefficients may be treated as random
in local regions (as might be expected under a variables (e.g., Park et al., 2010; Waxman, 2011).
model of locally variable effects of selection), they In short, the concept of “stochastic” is not
argue that selection is not a likely explanation for biological. One may say that, within a particular
this excess variability in the sitewise chance of model, selection (or mutation or recombination) is
a SNP. treated as a stochastic variable, but to attribute a
The excess variability may be due to long- property of “stochasticity” to a physical process
range context effects suggested in Fig. 2.4 (from would be to make a category error. The same
Hodgkinson et al., 2009). The upper figure is based point is made by Rosenberg (2001) when he warns
on 11,000 alignments in which humans and chimps against confusing models with reality, saying that
have a coincident SNP at position 0, and the lower “a theory can be statistical even though the world
figure is computed from 300,000 alignments where is deterministic, and vice versa.” The inclination
the chimp SNP is at position 0, and there is a of some authors to declare that an aspect of the
human SNP within 200 sites, but not at the same physical world is stochastic may indicate certain
site. The vertical position of a dot (for each of the beliefs about its origins (e.g., that it cannot be
200 sequence positions upstream or downstream) controlled) or its consequences (e.g., that it has no
represents the heterogeneity of triplet frequencies; important consequences).
the horizontal line is drawn such that one expects Thus, where “random” refers to stochasticity, the
5 % of the dots to fall above the line under a correct translation of “mutation is random” is “in a
null model of no effect. When the SNPs are not formal model, I have chosen to represent the out-
coincident (lower panel), the heterogeneity in come of mutation as a variable that may take on
triplet frequencies is not different from the null many values.” In Sections 3.6 and 3.7, we reconsider
expectation, except for the focal site and the nearest the value of this concept from a more practical per-
neighboring positions, yet for coincident SNPs spective.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

I N D E T E R M I N AT E 21

Box 2.1 Counting the universe of mutations

When one encounters a mutation rate in the evolutionary sizes of 2 × 106 bp and 109 bp for prokaryotes and
literature, typically the implication is that there is a class eukaryotes, respectively (other assumptions are explained in
of relevant mutations, each member of which occurs at the Appendix B). The universe of mutations is probably domi-
same rate u. Actually, many types or classes of mutations nated by compound events like kataegis, but we know so
are possible, and they tend to occur at widely varying rates. little about these events that no calculation is possible. If
Figure 2.1 shows a small fraction of this diversity. we ignore compound events, the universe of mutations is
To understand the depth of nonuniformity in mutation dominated by lateral gene transfers (horizontal gene trans-
rates, it helps to count the universe of mutations, i.e., fers), with 8 × 1028 or 4 × 1031 possibilities for prokaryotic
the possibility-space for mutations. One way to define the and eukaryotic recipients, respectively. If we ignore lateral
possibility-space is to imagine that a genome of length n can gene transfers, the universe of mutations is dominated by
mutate to any of 4n − 1 genomes of the same length. This transpositions. In any case, the universe of mutations is far,
number is enormous, e.g., a genome size of n = 2 × 106 bp far larger than the set of point mutations, which is only on
(typical for a prokaryote) would imply about 10million possible the order of 107 or 1010 for prokaryotes and eukaryotes,
mutations. respectively.
What if we assume instead that mutations only take This universe is so large that, if all mutations were to occur
the familiar forms of point mutations, insertions, deletions, at the same rate, it becomes unlikely for us to ever see the
inversions, and transpositions, each with sizes in the range same mutation twice. According to the calculation provided
we observe for natural mutations? This question is addressed in Section B.10, if we could monitor every mutation occurring
in Appendix B, which provides formulas for the numbers in a prokaryotic population of 1010 cells, we would have to
of each type of mutation. For instance, the numbers of wait for 500 years for it to become likely to see the same
inversions, deletions, and duplications are each rn, and mutation twice under the assumption of uniformity. If we
the number of transpositions is ≈ 4rn2 , where n is the aim to consider parallel adaptation in eukaryotes, finding
genome length, and r is the maximum size of a rearranged an exact parallelism would require us to track changes in
segment. thousands of eukaryotic species for millions of years. That
The table below depicts the universe of mutations given is, if we ever see the same mutation twice under ordinary
r = 104 bp (r = 10 for insertions) and assuming genome circumstances, we know that mutation is nonuniform.

Type Formula Prokaryotic Eukaryotic

Point mutation 6.7n 1.3 × 107 6.7 × 109


Deletion rn 2 × 1010 1013
Tandem duplication rn 2 × 1010 1013
Inversion rn 2 × 1010 1013
Insertion (4r+1 /3)n 2.8 × 1012 1.4 × 1015
Transposition 4rn2 1.6 × 1017 4 × 1022
Lateral gene transfer 2rnd nr D 8 × 1028 4 × 1031
d e
Compound e t n/d ? ?

2.5 Indeterminate ity may be subjective (see Section 2.6), physical inde-
terminacy is an objective distinction, i.e., it refers
A trial or experiment is said to be indeterminate to the actual world, not merely our sensation of it.
if the outcome is not determined by initial condi- If “mutation is random” refers to indeterminacy, it
tions, i.e., if different outcomes may emerge from means that the outcome of the process of mutation
exactly the same conditions. Whereas unpredictabil- cannot be predicted even with perfect knowledge.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

22 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

This is clearly not the case for the artificial muta- damage leading to mutation is extremely common,
tions in a computer simulation of evolution (see and the source of UVB photons is ultimately
Appendix A.3). The simulations used in computer nuclear fission reactions in the sun. Thus, whether a
modeling are deterministic, just like the series of particular TT dinucleotide (for instance) is going
“random” numbers computed by a PRNG (pseudo- to be hit by a photon, causing it to dimerize
random number generator): given the same initial into a TT dimer that may (via error-prone repair)
seed, every simulation gives the same outcome. In result in a T → C mutation, is indeterminate. An
a computer simulation of evolution, mutation is not example of indeterminacy arising internally would
“random” in the sense of indeterminate. be when damage is caused (directly or indirectly)
Is there indeterminacy in the biological world? by the spontaneous radioactive decay of some
Organisms are composed ultimately of fundamental atom within the cell. Whether or not subsequent
particles, and phenomena at the scale of fundamen- events are determinate, the initiating event is
tal particles are subject to physical indeterminacy. indeterminate, therefore the entire causal sequence
In our everyday “macroscopic” experiences, is indeterminate.
we are “screened off” from (i.e., isolated from, The argument applies more broadly to the entire
buffered from) microscopic indeterminacy, because class of mutations that result when electromagnetic
we experience the world through the collective radiation damages DNA, and the (possibly larger)
behavior of huge ensembles of microscopic events, class of events where radiation acts indirectly
whereas individual microscopic events, like the by damaging precursors incorporated into DNA.
behavior of a single subatomic particle, are beyond Indeed, the three main sources of nucleotide
our direct experience. Schrödinger (1944), in his mutations identified by Maki (2002) are replication
influential book What is Life?, was perhaps the errors, direct damage to DNA, and incorporation
first to suggest that mutations represent quantum of damaged precursors. Quantum indeterminacy
fluctuations. Authors such as Monod (1972) or clearly affects the latter two categories, and may
Wicken (1987, p. 89) assert (without explanation) affect the first, as argued by Stamos (2010).
that mutation is indeterminate due to quantum- Given that (1) the occurrence of some events of
mechanical indeterminacy. mutation is indeterminate, and (2) evolutionary
For the biologist, the physicist’s terminology of change sometimes begins with an event of mutation
“macroscopic” is misleading: if we look at a living (Blount et al., 2008; Rokyta et al., 2005), the
cell with an ordinary microscope, we see only conclusion that evolution sometimes depends
“macroscopic” processes (e.g., the movement of rather directly on indeterminate events is secure.
cells, vesicles, or chromosomes). Indeed, even ordi- To summarize, some aspects of mutagenesis (the
nary biochemical and enzymatic processes, such as mutation process) are physically indeterminate:
the diffusion of a substrate to the active site of an they cannot be predicted, even with perfect
enzyme, are predominantly macroscopic, though knowledge, because they rely on events affected
there is some room for debate about the extent to by quantum-mechanical indeterminacy. In turn,
which quantum events “filter up” and affect these evolutionary outcomes that depend on the timing
processes. For instance, quantum tunneling may of the resulting mutations are also physically
affect the thermal motion and the solvent charac- indeterminate.
teristics of water (Kolesnikov et al., 2016), which
would mean that diffusion in an aqueous solution
2.6 Subjectively unpredictable
is indeterminate; the active sites of some natural
enzymes appear to be sites of quantum-mechanical Laplace developed a probability theory to deal with
effects (e.g., Sutcliffe and Scrutton, 2000). events whose outcomes were not predictable, yet he
However, we do not need to resolve such subtle believed that the world is deterministic. He imag-
issues to arrive at an intermediate answer, because ined a superior intellect able to know all the posi-
mutational processes clearly show some physical tions of natural things and all of the forces acting
indeterminacy. For instance, UVB-induced DNA on them, and able to analyze all of these data in a
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

S U B J E C T I V E LY U N P R E D I C TA B L E 23

single formula; for such an intellect “nothing would evolution do not preclude the emergence of such
be uncertain, and the future, like the past, would systems by natural processes. Indeed, in Chapter 5
be present to its eyes” (Laplace, 1951, p. 4). Subjec- we consider the evolution of specialized systems of
tive unpredictability is due to ignorance, whereas germline mutation.
objective unpredictability arises from the kind of Nevertheless, most mutations are not very pre-
quantum-mechanical indeterminacy addressed in dictable. Why? Could they be predictable in the
Section 2.5. future, given advances in technology?
The symbolic mutation process in a computer A few considerations of basic physics suggest
simulation illustrates Laplace’s concept. A superior that, for ordinary mutations, prediction methods
intellect, knowing the seed number and the gen- will never achieve high accuracy, due to subjec-
erating formula xi+1 = f (xi ), could compute any tive unpredictability. Consider the scenario in which
xi . However, without this knowledge, we cannot an energetic particle is absorbed somewhere in a
predict the next number in the series. cell, creating a free radical that may cause genomic
We can imagine predictable, deterministic damage, which is likely to be repaired, possibly
mutation in the laboratory, although this is inducing a mutation. The challenge is to predict
typically a scattershot approach (see Appendix what will happen in a specific cell in the interval
A). For instance, microsurgery could be used to of time from the generation of the free radical to
remove a chromosome or a mitochondrion from the resolution of any damage. To solve this kind
a cell, changing its genotype deterministically. of problem requires us to track the identities and
Microsurgery has been used to alter the ciliate movements of a large number of molecules—all of
cortex—a nongenic mediator of heredity—resulting the molecules in a living cell that might affect a
in patterns that propagate from one generation to mutational outcome positively or negatively. This
the next (Shi et al., 1991). represents the dual challenge in Laplace’s scenario
Do highly predictable mutation processes exist? of omniscience above: (1) knowing the in vivo loca-
The answer is positive. Yeast mating-type switching tions and trajectories of all relevant molecules in the
(see Section 5.3.6), for instance, occurs reliably when cell, and (2) applying a physical model of forces to
spores germinate and begin to bud. Many examples compute the future state of the system.
could be given of mutational changes to genomes How could we map out all the molecules in a
that take place reliably during development, often cell? Many methods of three-dimensional imaging
called “programmed DNA rearrangements” (for use visible light and other forms of electromagnetic
review, see Zufall et al., 2005). Such changes radiation. The effective diameter of a small molecule
often occur by complex, multi-step pathways, as such as water or potassium ion (∼ 0.3 nm) is
in the case of chromatin diminution in somatic 100-fold below the resolution limit for optical
cells of nematodes (Muller and Tobler, 2000), the microscopy. Decreasing the wavelength used in
generation of macronuclear chromosomes in ciliates microscopy 100-fold to the range of X-rays would
(Noto and Mochizuki, 2017), or the maturation of improve resolution, but bombarding a cell with
antibody genes by shuffling and targeted hyper- X-rays will destroy it, and we have not even
mutation (Jung and Alt, 2004), explained further in come to the question of measuring momenta.
Section 5.2. Nuclear magnetic resonance (NMR)-based methods
Because most of these are somatic (not germline) of imaging depend on dynamic reorientation of
mutational phenomena, they typically are not dis- molecules to an external magnetic field, i.e., NMR
cussed in regard to the role of mutation in evolu- is an intrusive or disruptive method with respect to
tion, i.e., they are a separate topic from the main detecting the momenta of molecules.
focus of this book. However, the existence of spe- In short, assigning identities, locations, and
cialized systems of somatic mutation demonstrates momenta to all molecules in a cell at the requisite
conclusively that (1) the rules of biology do not pre- scale of precision, without changing the state of the
clude the existence of mutation-generating systems cell, is apparently impossible, due to what is called
with highly predictable effects, and (2) the rules of the “observer effect” in physics.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

24 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

Furthermore, the forward simulation problem is


many orders of magnitude beyond current tech-
nology. Fine-grained computer molecular dynamics
(MD) simulations may follow up to ∼ 106 atoms
for a timescale of many microseconds (Aminpour
et al., 2019), and these simulations are not complete
physical models, but include shortcuts (e.g., ignor-
ing higher-order interactions, using a bulk-solvent
model). By contrast, the timescale for a peroxide
radical or a repair enzyme to diffuse a substantial
distance in a cell is on the order of milliseconds or
seconds (e.g., see Elowitz et al., 1999), i.e., the time-
scale is 102 to 105 times larger. Figure 2.5 Spontaneous combustion. Due to the capacity to trap
Also, the number of atoms to represent in a whole- heat from decomposition, large compost piles can catch fire. Image by
cell simulation is far more than 106 . If we think of an Ramiro Barreiro reproduced under the Creative Commons Attribution
Share-alike (CC-BY-SA-3.0) Unported license.
E. coli cell as a 1-micron by 3-micron cylinder, with
a density several times that of water, a single cell
weighs ∼ 10−11 grams, which is ∼ 1013 daltons, or
∼ 1012 atoms, given that living matter is predom- “spontaneous combustion,” e.g., of a compost heap
inantly hydrogen (1 dalton), carbon (12), nitrogen (Fig. 2.5), we mean that a substance ignites from
(14), oxygen (16), and phosphorous (31). That is, an internal heat-generating process, without an
bacterial cells have 106 times more atoms than a external spark. The widely used term “spontaneous
large fine-grained MD simulation. Merely storing mutation” implies that mutations emerge from
the three-dimensional coordinates of 1012 atoms for internal processes, without external impetus or
one time-point would require 1013 bytes, i.e., 10 ter- constraint.
abytes, and the time-points of MD simulations are Within this broad definition, the spontaneousness
typically femtoseconds (10−15 seconds), thus 1012 of mutation could mean several different things.
time-points per millisecond (Aminpour et al., 2019). Sometimes “spontaneous mutation” is applied
If the problem is ∼ 104 times longer in time and in the mutation research literature with a narrow
106 times larger in number of atoms, then (given technical meaning of “natural” or “not artificially
that computational intensity increases greater than enhanced,” as a way of indicating that the process
linearly with number of atoms), the forward MD of mutation under investigation is that of a wild-
simulation to predict a mutation is much more than type cell under ordinary conditions, without any
1010 times harder than current fine-grained MD attempts to artificially enhance mutation rates.
targets. The context of this usage is that, until recently,
Such considerations suggest that subjective mutation researchers nearly always increased the
unpredictability of mutation is unavoidable. rate of mutation artificially, to make the process
of mutation easier to study. Most of the mutation
2.7 Spontaneous research literature is based on experiments with
repair mutants or mutagens, so that the resulting
When biologists use the word “spontaneous,” rates and spectra of mutations are of little use to the
the connotations are the same as for the ordinary evolutionary biologist. Better sources of information
English adjective that may be applied to persons or on evolutionarily relevant mutation rates include
events. A spontaneous event (or person) proceeds mutation-accumulation experiments (Halligan and
from an internal cause (or impulse), without Keightley, 2009), as in Katju and Bergthorsson
external impetus or constraint. When we refer to (2019), and analyses of the presumptively neutral
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

S P O N TA N E O U S 25

divergence of sequences such as pseudogenes (e.g., to T1, then the number of resistant colonies will
Hwang and Green, 2004). follow a Poisson distribution, with a variance equal
An additional meaning of “spontaneous” (e.g., to the mean. If the mutations are not induced, but
Schroeder et al., 2018) is suggested by a series may occur at any time during growth, they will
of classic experiments on mutation reviewed in follow what became known as the Luria–Delbrück
depth by Sarkar (1991). The most famous of these distribution.
is Luria and Delbrück’s “fluctuation test” based The key feature of this distribution is that the vari-
on mutations in E. coli conferring resistance to ance is much higher than the mean, due to “jackpot”
bacteriophage T1. When a suspension of bacterial cultures in which the mutation occurs early in the
cells is plated (i.e., spread on a petri dish filled with process of growth, leaving many resistant descen-
growth medium), each cell grows up into a colony dants that grow up into many separate colonies.
that is easily visible to the naked eye. If the growth In their experiment with E. coli and T1 phage,
medium contains bacteriophage T1, the cells will Luria and Delbrück found that the ratio of the
die unless they happen to contain a mutation that variance to the mean was much higher than 1,
confers resistance. and consistent with the results being due primarily
The protocol of the fluctuation test is simply to to mutations that occurred prior to selection, thus
repeat this procedure using separate cultures, each uninduced (though the experimental design is not
grown from a single cell, and to count the resis- sensitive enough to exclude the possibility of a
tant colonies on each plate. The distributions of small minority of induced mutations). To say that
resistant colonies will differ depending on whether mutation is “random” or “spontaneous,” in the
mutations occur prior to plating, or are induced by sense defined by the fluctuation test, is to say that
exposure to T1 phage, as illustrated in Fig. 2.6. If the process, because it begins and ends prior to the onset
rare resistant mutations are induced by exposure of selection, is neither induced nor directly shaped
by the current environment.
As Sarkar (1991) relates, this experimental
protocol was repeated in the 1940s with the same
biological system, and with other systems. The
results tended to support the interpretation of
predominantly noninduced mutations, with some
deviations that were attributed tentatively to other
effects, such as phenotypic lag. Phenotypic lag refers
to the fact that the expression of the phenotype
that survives selection does not necessarily emerge
immediately after the mutation, but may take
time to build up. For instance, if the resistance
phenotype involves the loss of a surface protein
that a phage uses to infect a cell, the mutation does
not take effect immediately because the membranes
of daughter cells still carry unmutated proteins
synthesized prior to the mutation: if turnover is
slow, the shift to complete resistance may take
several generations. That is, the experiments
Figure 2.6 The difference between induced (left) and spontaneous
(right) mutations in the Luria–Delbrück experiment (see text for become difficult to interpret when the phenotypic
explanation). Wikipedia image by MadPrime, reproduced under the realization of the mutation, i.e., its developmental
Creative Commons CC0 1.0 Universal Public Domain Dedication. expression, is not complete prior to the onset of selection,
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

26 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

an issue to bear in mind for the discussion in of the cell, thus the mutation is not spontaneous in
Chapter 4. the sense of being entirely internal.
Let us consider a more stringent sense of In short, the widely held notion that mutations
“spontaneous,” in which the process of mutation are normally spontaneous, in the sense of normally
is entirely internal to cells, uninfluenced by any arising from internal processes such as replication
external conditions. To say that a mutation is errors, is not a firmly established conclusion based
spontaneous in this sense is to say that it arises on empirical findings or on basic principles.
entirely as the result of internal processes, without Finally, some kinds of mutations are strongly non-
outside influences. Some kinds of mutations seem spontaneous in the sense of being strongly shaped
fully spontaneous in this sense. For instance, a by external inputs. For instance, a strong form of
replication error that takes place with a template nonspontaneity applies when hereditary substances
and precursors undamaged by external radiation are transferred into a cell from the outside. Not only
seems to reflect events that happen entirely inside does this happen every day in the laboratory, when
the cell (see Appendix A). One also could imagine biologists introduce human-modified genes into
the case where an atom inside a cell spontaneously cells (see Section A.4), it also happens every day in
decays, releasing an energetic particle that causes the wild, when cells take up foreign matter—nucleic
damage to DNA, which is then repaired in an error- acids, viral particles, and even cells—containing
prone way that introduces a mutation. hereditary material (Mell and Redfield, 2014). For
Teaching resources and textbooks frequently instance, the insertion of a transposable element
equate mutations with copying errors, but this is or a bacteriophage genome into a prokaryotic
misleading. Even for the most prevalent mutations, genome is an event of mutation that—considering
nucleotide substitutions, the relative contributions the enormous numbers of prokaryotic cells on the
of the three categories of Maki (2002)—replication planet—must occur enormous numbers of times
errors, incorporation of damaged precursors, every minute. These nonspontaneous processes
and direct damage (see Appendix A)—are not may lead to evolutionary events of lateral gene
known for any organism. Several lines of evidence transfer (Smith et al., 1992; Koonin and Wolf,
indicate that the contribution of damage to ordinary 2008). The CRISPR-Cas system of acquired bacterial
nucleotide mutations is substantial. For instance, immunity that we discuss later (5.3.3) is based on
new mutations in humans identified by genomic the nonspontaneous incorporation of fragments of
sequencing show an effect of parental age that foreign DNA.
suggests a major contribution of damage-induced To summarize, the “spontaneity” of mutation
mutations (Gao et al., 2019). Context-dependent might mean several things. In the research
patterns of mutation inferred for mammalian literature, it sometimes has a technical meaning,
genomes show a strong correlation with context- referring to natural mutation under ordinary
dependent patterns of susceptibility to damage by conditions, rather than laboratory mutation using
reactive oxygen species (Stoltzfus, 2008). mutant strains or chemical mutagens. Mutations
When a pathway of mutation begins with dam- are spontaneous in the Luria–Delbrück sense if they
age, this is often damage due to radiation (or to emerge prior to a condition of interest (e.g., the
free radicals that result from radiation), repaired presence of toxins or pesticides), rather than being
in an error-prone way by the cell’s internal DNA induced by the condition. Most mutations are not
repair systems. For instance, ultraviolet radiation spontaneous in the sense of reflecting an entirely
may generate a TT dimer, an external influence that internal process. Instead, many kinds of mutations
triggers damage repair and possible mutation (see are influenced by external factors, and some are
Appendix A.2). The radiation comes from outside shaped strongly by external inputs.
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

S P O N TA N E O U S 27

Box 2.2 Specialized mutation systems

Most mutations can be understood as side effects of mecha- ing infections characterized by repeated cycles of decline
nisms of DNA replication and repair, but this is not always and regrowth in which the dominant antigen “is replaced
the case. For instance, mutations that result from mobile by another of sufficient antigenic distance that current anti-
elements reflect an ongoing battle between hosts and bodies are ineffective against cells expressing the second
their highly evolved genomic parasites, e.g., the transposase antigen” (Dai et al., 2006). This cycle can go on indefinitely,
enzyme encoded by a transposon catalyzes the movement so long as the pathogen continues to vary its antigens and
of genomic segments in a predictable way that reflects the the host continues to produce new antibodies to target
transposon lifestyle: typically very specific for the source them.
segment (the transposon, as distinct from other segments The system of antigenic variation in Trypanosoma brucei
of DNA), but typically indiscriminate in regard to the point of (a single-celled eukaryote), the causative agent of trypanoso-
insertion. miasis, provides a dramatic example. Trypanosoma species
More interestingly, some mutation-generating systems express a surface glycoprotein in enormous amounts, as a
are specialized so as to enhance specific types of useful kind of external shield. Though only a single variable surface
mutations or to target critical genes underlying adaptation. glycoprotein (VSG) gene is expressed at any given time,
This phenomenon is most familiar in the context of microbes the genome of T. brucei has about 15 possible expression
that evade host immune responses by antigenic variation, sites (see Mugnier et al., 2016), and about 2,000 silent
i.e., switching of antigen proteins. That is, mutational mech- VSG genes, most of which are partial (Glover et al., 2013;
anisms of antigenic variation in microbial pathogens (see Ch. Horn, 2014). Key aspects of the genomic organization are
5) are routinely described in the microbiological literature as shown schematically in Fig. 2.7, which illustrates arrays of
evolved “strategies” or “mechanisms” for survival or adap- VSG genes in subtelomeric regions, and telomeric expression
tation or persistence by immune evasion, in discussions of sites, including one active bloodstream expression site. The
the causative agents of trypanosomiasis (Barry et al., 2012; active expression site (ES) corresponds to a single physical
Hall et al., 2013; Horn, 2014), Lyme disease (Bankhead and location within the nucleus, analogous to a nucleolus.
Chaconas, 2007; McDowell et al., 2002), relapsing fever (Dai Variability in the VSG coat protein is the result of several
et al., 2006; Norris, 2006), and malaria (Recker et al., 2011; distinct mechanisms: (1) transcriptional switching that turns
Guizetti and Scherf, 2013), and in broad reviews of multiple off expression of one ES and turns on another, (2) ectopic
systems (Foley, 2015; Vink et al., 2012; Palmer et al., 2016). recombination that swaps segments between an inactive
The context for the evolutionary emergence of muta- and active ES, and (3) gene conversion events that transfer
tional strategies of immune evasion is the vertebrate adap- information from the thousands of silent VSG genes into
tive immune system, which has the capacity to generate the ES (Barry et al., 2012; Hall et al., 2013; Horn, 2014). In
new antibodies that target previously unknown microbial addition, the silent VSG genes are located in subtelomeric
pathogens by recognizing specific surface proteins. When regions subject to higher rates of mutation than the rest
this system is successful on a pathogen in the blood- of the genome (Barry et al., 2012). The rate of antigenic
stream, for instance, the pathogen is “cleared” by the switching from all of these effects is about 10−3 per cell per
immune response. However, some pathogens cause relaps- generation (Barry et al., 2012).

x 11: megabase chromosomes

50-bp repeats VSG ~ 5: intermediate chromosomes


70-bp repeats Active BES
T2AG3 repeats Silent BES
~ 100: minichromosomes

Figure 2.7 A genome-wide system of surface antigen switching with thousands of cassettes in T. brucei. Figure from Glover et al. (2013),
reproduced under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license.
Continued
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

28 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

Box 2.2 Continued

To understand the significance of this rate, note that, in the microbiological literature. The five additional types
in the context of an infection, a single individual expands of schemes listed below are described in more detail in
into a clan, and success depends on the capacity of the Chapter 5.
clan, in aggregate, to survive host defenses. As Barry et al. • Diversity-generating retroelements (DGRs) represent a
(2012) point out, “The first wave of parasites in a cow can widely distributed (Paul et al., 2017; Wu et al., 2018) scheme
peak with a total in excess of 1011 trypanosomes, therefore of targeted hypermutation mediated by error-prone reverse-
> 108 will have switched to a different variant, while a transcription (Guo et al., 2014), typically inducing variability
mouse can support > 108 parasites with > 105 emerging of C-type lectin domains.
variants." That is, a mutation that is a remote possibility in
• Inversion systems like the R64 “shufflon” have a small num-
a single individual may become the guaranteed mass-action
ber of unique DNA segments interspersed with repeated
response of a clan.
motifs that serve as endpoints for inversion mutations,
The trypanosome system exemplifies a larger class of
resulting in combinatorial shuffling by inversion (Komano,
systems. Palmer et al. (2016) describe three such systems in
1999; Sekizuka et al., 2017).
bacterial species of the genera Borrelia (causing relapsing
• Mating-type switching is a regular part of the life history of
fever and Lyme disease), Neisseria (gonorrhea, meningitis),
several yeast species, including S. cerevisiae, which switches
and Anaplasma (anaplasmosis in livestock). In generic terms,
by a gene-conversion event that is programmed in regard to
these systems all have a recipient locus or expression site
timing and outcome (Hicks and Herskowitz, 1977; Hanson
subject to overwriting (by gene conversion or ectopic recom-
and Wolfe, 2017).
bination) with sequence information from multiple silent
donor loci, typically nonfunctional partial genes. Such sys- • The widespread phenomenon of phase variation, known for
tems typically allow, not simply an n-fold switch among types nearly a century, refers to switching between expression
determined by the n donor loci, but > n-fold diversity due states, often by mutation but also by epigenetic mechanisms
to the potential for mosaics (with segments from multiple (van der Woude and Bäumler, 2004).
donor loci) and hypermutation, as is the case for T. brucei • In CRISPR-Cas systems of phage defense used in
(Hall et al., 2013). prokaryotes, pieces of phage DNA are added to spacer
Furthermore, such schemes of cassette shuffling are not arrays that are used to encode site-specific DNA shears
the only kinds of specialized mutational systems described (Koonin, 2017).

2.8 Independent (part 1) Pr(A) and Pr(B) when they are (unconditionally)
independent. For instance, in the case of the six-
According to a definition often attributed to Aristo-
sided uniform dice, the chance of getting 5 on the
tle, a “chance” event is the intersection of indepen-
first roll, and 5 on the second, is (1/6)2 = 1/36, if the
dent causal sequences (e.g., Eble, 1999). An example
two rolls are independent causal sequences.
would be tossing two dice and finding the same
Our main interest in regard to independence is
number on both of them (Fig. 2.8). The two tosses
to ask whether mutation is independent from biotic
are independent causal sequences: whether they
or environmental conditions, e.g., temperature or
converge on the same number is a matter of chance.
Importantly, this sense of randomness refers to a physiological states. That issue is addressed in the
relation rather than to an intrinsic property—a mat- next section. This section is devoted to the issue of
ter of one thing relative to another, e.g., the chance whether one mutation is independent from another.
of a mutation relative to the current temperature. Some examples of this type of independence or
This notion of causal independence invites the use nonindependence were encountered earlier. For
of the corresponding concept of independence from instance, in the analysis depicted previously in
probability theory, allowing joint probabilities to Fig. 2.4, which involved a comparison of SNPs
be determined simply by multiplication, e.g., the between humans and chimps, it was assumed
joint probability Pr(A, B) is simply the product of that each coincident SNP arose independently
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

I N D E P E N D E N T ( PA RT 1 ) 29

clusters of mutations occur more often than would


be expected if mutations were independent of
each other.
Though the exact causes are unknown in most
cases, one obvious explanation for clusters of
linked mutations is that DNA repair stimulated
by damage or recombination frequently involves
excision and error-prone re-synthesis of a strand
over many nucleotides, not just a single site (see
Section A.2). Appendix A.2 also notes that a single
particle of ionizing radiation can produce a burst
Figure 2.8 The chance conjunction of numbers on two dice is an of free radicals, which can then go on to create a
example of independence. Image by Steaphan Greene, reproduced
localized burst of damage. Clusters of nucleotide
under Creative Commons Attribution Share-alike (CC-BY-SA-3.0)
license. mutations that occur in the same generation
have been observed in a variety of organisms, on
length-scales ranging from one to hundreds of kb
by mutation, in the sense that the mutation that (Chan and Gordenin, 2015).
occurred in the chimp lineage was independent of The extreme case of such clustering is the recently
that in the human lineage. This assumption seems named phenomenon of kataegis (Greek, “thunder”),
safe for most mutations, though not for lateral which refers to regional domains of hypermuta-
gene transfers, because the frequency of a donor tion that may extend over many thousands of sites.
sequence in a particular environment affects the Alexandrov et al. (2013) studied this phenomenon in
rate of acquisition in all recipient genomes in that human cancer cells, with results shown graphically
environment. in the “rainfall” plots in Fig. 2.9. The upper cloud
However, when we are considering the emer- of points between 105 and 106 bp indicates that a
gence of different mutations in the same cell, or mutation is typically far from the next mutation.
the same lineage, the assumption of independence However, the vertical streaks each represent clus-
is not safe. Double-nucleotide changes at adjacent ters of many mutations that are much more closely
sites are rare, but not nearly as rare as one would spaced, on the scale of 102 or 103 bp.
predict from independence (Hill et al., 2003; Reid Another possible mechanism for an excess of mul-
and Loeb, 1993). Compound events involving tiple mutations, discussed by Drake et al. (2005),
multiple changes in the same vicinity are seen in is transient hypermutation, when some fraction of
laboratory mutation assays (e.g., Lang and Murray, cells enters a transient state with a greatly increased
2008; Phear et al., 1987; Drobetsky et al., 1987) and rate of mutation.
mutation-accumulation experiments (e.g., Keith A final possible mechanism of nonindependence
et al., 2016), and appear regularly in clinical studies would cause mutations to occur preferentially
(e.g., Cordella et al., 2006), e.g., large clinically near the sites of previous mutations. This idea
important rearrangement mutations often include is based on observations from yeast indicating
additional changes near the endpoints (Conrad that gene conversion and DNA repair events
et al., 2010). Occasionally, evolutionary comparisons tend to be induced by the presence of sequence
suggest nonindependence, e.g., between indels differences between chromosomes. Thus, the chance
and nearby nucleotide substitutions (Jovelin and of mutagenic gene conversion and repair events
Cutter, 2013). Recently, Venkat et al. (2018) argued is increased to the extent that the inheritance of
that phylogenetic tests for positive selection often past mutational changes makes homologous alleles
produce misleading results due to compound differ. Data on clustering of variations for human
mutations affecting nearby sites. Drake et al. (2005) SNPs and microsatellite variants provide some
review results from diverse taxa suggesting that support for this hypothesis (Amos, 2010).
OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 12/2/2021, SPi

30 O R D I N A RY R A N D O M N E S S

Somatic Mutations - APGI_1992


Density

7
Distance between mutations (log10)

1
r1

r2

r3

r4

r5

r6

r7

r8

r9

ch 5
ch 6
ch 7
ch 18
ch 19
chr20
chr21
2
rX
rY
r1

r1

r1

r1

r1

r1
r1
r1

r2
ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch
ch
r
r
ch

ch

ch

ch

ch

ch
Figure 2.9 Rainfall plot showing kataegis in a pancreatic cancer line (data from Alexandrov et al., 2013, plotted using code modified from Bernat
Gel at https://bernatgel.github.io). The horizontal axis is genomic position, covering the entire genome of 23 chromosomes. The vertical axis is
distance to the next mutation on a log-scale. In this case of kataegis, mutations are heavily biased toward C → G and C → T mutations (black
and red dots, respectively).

2.9 Independent (part 2) was always a smallish number, which meant that
the next step in the simulation algorithm—choosing
Having addressed (in Section 2.8) whether muta-
the type of mutation—was biased.
tion events are independent of each other, we now
How does this case distinguish chance from pre-
may address whether mutation is an independent or
dictability, uniformity, and so on? The sequence of
chance process relative to events or conditions other
numbers from the PRNG is deterministic, uniform,
than mutation.
and—if one knows the internal state—fully pre-
The use of a PRNG in an evolutionary simulation
dictable. The flawed PRNG produces a sequence of
illustrates how this kind of randomness (indepen-
outputs that have serial correlations (i.e., noninde-
dence) differs from other concepts (see Appendix
pendent), which means that, even without know-
A.3). I once used a flawed PRNG in a computer ing the internal state, it exhibits some strongly pre-
simulation of evolution that sequentially generated dictable behavior, because a very small number is
(1) a number to decide whether a mutation would followed reliably by another small number. How-
occur, and then (2) a second number to decide the ever, if one does not know the internal state, most
type of mutation. In the first step, the method of of the behavior of the PRNG is very unpredictable.
implementing the decision was to ask if m < μ, Importantly, the relation of the flawed PRNG
where μ is the mutation rate for a gene (a very to the simulation remains a matter of “chance”
small number) and m is a number between 0 and 1. (independence) even though it produces a highly
However, the particular flaw of this PRNG was that predictable effect based on the nonindependence
an extremely small number was followed, not by of one number from the next. The relationship still
a uniformly distributed number, but by a smallish meets Aristotle’s “independent causal sequence”
number. Because the first step in the mutation algo- condition because the computer code for the PRNG
rithm depended on testing whether m < μ, where is a separate function, walled off from the rest of the
μ is an extremely small number, the next number simulation program, operating independently—the
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
to produce marked symptoms of poisoning. In this direction a
number of experiments have been performed with arsenic,
particularly those of Cloetta[1], who found that the dose of arsenic for
dogs could be gradually raised, if given by the mouth, to many times
the ordinary fatal dose, but that if at this point a subminimal fatal
dose was injected beneath the skin acute symptoms of arsenic
poisoning followed.
We show in a later chapter that the excretion of lead in persons
tolerant of the metal takes place through the medium of the bowel,
and that probably those individuals who are engaged in what are
recognized as dangerous processes in lead industries, and yet show
no signs of illness, have established a kind of balance between the
intake of the poison and its excretion by the bowel. It is rarely
possible in such persons to find any lead excreted through the
kidney. Occasionally, however, such persons, after working a
considerable time in a dangerous lead process, become suddenly
poisoned, and inquiry frequently discloses the fact that some
disturbing factor, either intercurrent illness, alcoholic excess, etc.,
has occurred, or that the breathing of a big dose of dust has
precipitated the symptoms of general lead poisoning. On the other
hand, the experience of all persons engaged in the routine
examination of lead workers is that, although a worker may show
signs of lead absorption as distinguished from definite lead poisoning
during the earlier period of his employment, he later shows less and
less signs of the influence of the poisonous substance; even a mild
degree of definite poisoning in the early stages of work in a lead
process does not seriously militate against this gradually acquired
tolerance, whilst careful treatment during such a time as the man is
acquiring tolerance to the poison frequently tides him over the
period, and enables him to withstand the ordinary dangers attached
to his work.
The earliest symptom of lead absorption is anæmia. The anæmia
is not very profound, and the diminution in the red blood-cells rarely
reaches as low as 2,000,000 per c.c., the hæmoglobin remaining
somewhere between 75 and 80 per cent. Some loss of orbital fat, as
well as fat in the other parts of the body, occurs, but beyond this no
obvious clinical signs of poisoning exist. Should such persons
possess unhealthy gums, a blue line rapidly makes its appearance,
but where the gums are healthy it is unusual to see any sign of
deposit in this prodromal stage.
Persons who gradually acquire tolerance go through the stage of
anæmia without exhibiting any symptoms of colic or paresis, and
without any treatment the hæmoglobin and the number of red cells
gradually pass back to a more or less normal condition. During this
period—that is, whilst the blood shows signs of a diminution in its
corpuscular and colour content—basophile granules may always be
found if sought for, but disappear as a rule when the blood-count has
returned to about 4,000,000 per c.c. and an 80 per cent.
hæmoglobin. Such a man has now developed tolerance to the
poisonous influence of lead, a tolerance which may be described as
a partial immunity produced by recurrent subminimal toxic doses. On
the other hand, in a number of persons who show definite
susceptibility, the blood-changes are progressive, and do not show
signs of automatic regeneration. In such persons, even after so short
time as four to six weeks’ exposure to lead absorption, definite
symptoms of colic may make their appearance. The removal of such
an individual from the poisonous influence of lead generally clears
up the symptoms in a short time, but the symptoms may occasionally
continue for several months after removal from the influence of the
poison. An individual of this type is to be looked upon as showing
peculiar susceptibility, and should not be employed in any lead
process where there is risk.
Such statistics as are available on this point show that an
increased tolerance to the poisonous influence of lead is gradually
acquired during periods of work, in that the number of attacks of
poisoning diminish in frequency very considerably in relation to the
number of years worked. As will be seen on reference to the chapter
dealing with the statistics of lead poisoning (p. 46), the greatest
number of cases occur in persons who have only worked a short
time in lead. On the other hand, the sequelæ of lead poisoning only
make their appearance, as a rule, after long-continued exposure. It is
important to bear in mind that the various forms of paresis rarely
make their appearance unless the subject has been exposed to
long-continued absorption of lead, and, further, that the blood of such
persons will as a rule show, on careful examination, evidences of the
long-continued intoxication. If measures, therefore, were taken to
determine the presence of such continued intoxication, and to
diminish the amount of poison absorbed (subjecting the individual at
the same time to a proper course of treatment), a large number of
the cases of paralysis, encephalopathy, and death, incidental to the
handling and manufacture of lead, could be eliminated.
Susceptibility may at times be shown by several members of one
family. Oliver[2] says that he has known many members of one family
suffer from and die of lead poisoning. In our experience several
instances of this susceptibility have been noticed. In one case two
brothers, working in one shift of men, developed poisoning, although
no other persons in that shift showed any signs of it. A third brother,
who came into the works after the other two had left, and who was
placed under special supervision on account of the susceptibility
exhibited by his two brothers, although given work which exposed
him to the minimal degree of lead absorption, developed signs of
poisoning six weeks after his entrance into the factory. In another
factory, three sons, two daughters, and the father, all suffered from
lead poisoning within a period of four years: the father had three
attacks of colic, ultimately wrist-drop in both hands; one daughter
had one attack of colic, and the other three attacks; whilst the three
brothers all suffered from colic and anæmia, and one had early signs
of weakness of the wrist. There was no evidence at all to show that
these persons were more careless, or had been more exposed to
lead dust, than any other of the persons with whom they worked, or
that the work they were engaged upon was more likely to have
caused illness to them than to other workers. Persons with a fresh
complexion and red hair have been noted to be more susceptible to
lead poisoning than dark-haired persons.
In one factory with which we are familiar, a number of Italian
workmen are employed; these show considerably less susceptibility
to lead poisoning than do their English comrades as long as they
adhere to their own national diet. When, however, they give this up,
and particularly if they become addicted to alcohol, they rapidly show
diminished resistance; in fact, all the cases of plumbism occurring
among the Italians in this factory during the last ten years have been
complicated with alcohol. It is possible that the relatively large
quantity of vegetables in the diet of these Italians influences the
elimination of absorbed lead. There is some reason to suppose,
however, that there may be racial immunity to lead poisoning.
The following case in the same factory illustrates a point already
mentioned—namely, the gradually acquired tolerance to poisoning,
and the unstable equilibrium existing. The individual was a man of
twenty years of age. He commenced work on August 2, 1905. Six
weeks later he was under treatment for seven weeks, for lead
absorption, and had a peculiarly deep blue line round his gums, and
a diminished hæmoglobin of 75 per cent. The symptoms
disappeared with ordinary routine treatment, and his work was
shifted to a position in the factory where he was exposed to the
minimum amount of lead absorption, at which work he continued
during the rest of the time he remained in the factory. He continued
quite well until June, 1906, when he was again under treatment for
two weeks, with the same blue line and anæmia, and his blood
showed the presence of basophile granules. He was under treatment
again in January and February, 1909, for five weeks, had again a
deep blue line and basophile staining of his blood. On November 7,
1911, having had no anæmia and no blue line, he had a slight attack
of colic. During this period of work his blood had been examined on
eight occasions, and on each occasion it had shown basophile
granules. The attack of colic was an exceedingly mild one. There is
no reason to suppose that he had indulged in alcoholic excess, but
there was some reason to think that for about a month he had been
subjected to increased lung absorption. No other persons working in
the same shift at the same work developed poisoning during the
whole of this period. This case illustrates initial susceptibility, partial
tolerance, and ultimate breaking down of such partially established
tolerance.
During the experimental inquiry on lead poisoning by one of us [K.
W. G.[3]], the question of the subminimal toxic dose and the minimal
toxic dose was under consideration. Animals subjected to inhalation
of lead dust invariably succumbed to the effects of the poison when
the dose given represented from 0·0001 to 0·0003 gramme per litre
of air inhaled, the period of inhalation being half an hour three times
a week. On the other hand, when the lead content of the air was as
low as 0·00001 gramme per litre, the symptoms of poisoning were
long delayed, and in more than one instance, after an early
diminution in weight, recovery of the lost weight took place, and the
animals, whilst showing apparent symptoms of absorption, had no
definite symptoms of paresis. These observations tend to confirm
such clinically observed facts as are given in the case cited above,
but they, of course, do not form a criterion as to the amount of lead
dust which may be regarded as innocuous to man.
Lead is peculiarly a cumulative poison, and post-mortem analyses
of viscera show that it may be stored up in certain parts of the body,
more especially in the bone and red bone marrow and brain, and to
some extent in the liver, spleen, and kidneys. Any circumstance,
therefore, that temporarily interferes with the ordinary channels
through which lead is excreted may determine the presence of a
much larger quantity than usual of the metal in circulation in the
body; and if in addition an increased quantity of the poison be
inhaled, more or less acute symptoms follow. The localization of the
deposit of lead is therefore of some importance.
Meillère and Richer[4] give an analysis of various organs of the
body, but their results are not in accord with the majority of other
observers. They found that the hair particularly contains a large
quantity of lead. They do not seem to have examined the bones.
Next to the hair, the liver seems to have contained the largest
amount. Wynter Blyth[5] found 117·1 milligrammes of lead in the
brain of a person who died of encephalopathy. In another case he
found 0·6 gramme in the liver, 0·003 in the kidney, and 0·072 in the
brain. Hougounencq[6] examined the organs of a person who died
from lead poisoning, and found the largest amount of lead in the
large intestine.
Large intestine 0·2150 gramme.
Small intestine 0·0430 „
Liver 0·0050 „
Brain 0·0008 „

In the lung, stomach, kidney, and heart, only traces were found.
Dixon Mann[7] describes some experiments in which potassium
iodide was given in cases of chronic poisoning, and during the whole
of the experiments the fæces and urine were analyzed three times a
week. He found by this means that a considerable amount of lead
was being eliminated by the intestine. He therefore administered 2
grammes of lead acetate three times a day for five days to a patient,
and he found that the fæces contained 0·1762 gramme the first day,
0·17411 gramme the second day; the fourth day it had fallen to
0·0053 gramme, and on the sixth day to 0·0006 gramme. The
largest amount at any one time in a day obtained from the urine was
only just over 0·001 gramme; the average amount found in the case
of chronic poisoning was about 3 milligrammes, whereas the
greatest amount at any one time in the urine was only 0·9
milligramme.
The quantity of lead present in the brain necessary to determine
acute poisoning is not known, and it is probable that an extremely
minute quantity will produce very serious effects; and in support of
this may be quoted a number of observations in which search has
been made for the metal in persons who have died of diseases
affecting the brain associated with other symptoms of poisoning, and
yet post-mortem examination of the brain by chemical methods has
not revealed the presence of any lead whatever. In the case reported
by Mott (see p. 71), no lead at all was recognized in the brain.
There are no reasons, therefore, for supposing that the immunity
to lead poisoning depends on the fixation and storing up of the
poisonous metal in a non-poisonous form in some special situation in
the body, and, further, the particular situation in the body richest in
lead in any given case of poisoning will depend rather on (1) the type
of compound causing the poisoning, and (2) the portal through which
such poisoning occurs.
The question of the detection of lead in the body is referred to in
the chapter dealing with Chemical Examination. It is as well to point
out in this connection that chemical investigation of the amount of
lead present in the organs of persons dying from lead poisoning
should, if possible, always be made where there is any doubt as to
the diagnosis.
Certain observers—amongst them Gautier[8]—are of opinion that
traces of lead may be found in normal persons. Thus, in a rat (Mus
decumanus) Gautier found 2 milligrammes of lead in 60 grammes of
liver. He considers that in many persons at least 0·5 milligramme of
lead may be swallowed daily incorporated with the food, as a
number of foods are liable to contamination by lead. Tinned foods,
particularly those which are soldered up after the materials have
been placed in the tin, certain tinned fruits with acid juices, often
contain small masses of solder loose in the tins; in the case
particularly of fruits the natural acid may slowly dissolve the lead
from the solder. The amount of so-called “normal” lead, if it is to be
found at all, must be very small, and would certainly be much smaller
in the case of a normal person than in one who had been subject to
definite lead poisoning. Such experimental evidence as is
forthcoming supports the clinical observations that persons exposed
to small doses of lead eventually develop tolerance of the metal, so
that they may ultimately withstand many times the dose sufficient in
the first instance to produce poisoning.
Such circumstances are the natural factors in the prevention of
poisoning, and if due care be given to their significance, the surgeon
in charge of any lead works may by judicious treatment and
alternation of employment so assist and strengthen the natural
defensive forces that susceptibility may be diminished, and the
degree of tolerance increased to a very considerable extent. We do
not imply that efficiency in the exhaust ventilation can be in any way
relaxed; all we desire to emphasize is that certain natural defensive
forces of the body do undoubtedly exist by which susceptible
persons ultimately become less susceptible, and that by appropriate
means these defensive forces may be augmented.
Susceptibility and immunity to poisoning by lead may be
considered, according to the type of lead compound absorbed,
further in its relation to age and sex. All compounds of lead are not
poisonous in the same degree; the more easily soluble compounds
are more poisonous than the less soluble. On the other hand,
compounds which appear at first sight unlikely to produce poisoning
may do so; for instance, fritted lead or lead silicate, a substance
largely used in the potteries as a glaze, and manufactured by fusing
together litharge and a silicate, would appear at first sight to be quite
an innocuous substance. Owing to its method of preparation,
however, it is not a pure compound of lead and silica, but contains
lead oxide, metallic lead, etc., entangled in its meshes, and
experimentally one of us (K. W. G.) has demonstrated that such a
compound may be acted on by the tissues of the body, both when
injected subcutaneously and even when inhaled, and so gradually
produce definite symptoms of lead poisoning, but at a much slower
rate than the more poisonous lead compounds. The fineness of
division in which the compound of lead exists is another factor
affecting its poisonous nature; the more finely divided particles find
their way into the lung more easily than the coarser particles. Various
subsidiary matters may also determine the susceptibility in a given
individual, and of these a certain number require mention, as they
probably act as definite predisposing factors. Age and sex may be
regarded as predisposing factors to lead poisoning, and certain
diseases also.
Age.—Young persons are regarded as more liable to lead
poisoning than adults, although it is difficult to obtain definite figures
on the point, the duration of employment acting as a disturbing factor
in estimating the susceptibility of young persons. They may have
worked in a lead works for a year or more without showing any signs
of poisoning, but develop them later in adult life, although it is very
likely that absorption had taken place during the earlier period. In the
Report of the Departmental Committee on the Use of Lead in the
Potteries (Appendix XII.), the attack rate for the period 1899 to 1909
for young persons is 19·3 per 1,000, and for adults 18·8 for the same
period, but the figures upon which these attack rates are based are
too small to build any conclusion. The general clinical conclusions of
appointed surgeons and certifying surgeons in the various lead
factories would be, we believe, that the susceptibility of young
persons is at least twice that of adults, and there is some ground for
supposing that the tissues of an adult when growth has ceased more
readily adapt themselves to deal with the absorption and elimination
of poisonous doses of lead than do the tissues of a young person.
Sex.—Women are more susceptible to poisoning by lead than
men, and in lead poisoning from drinking water the proportion of
women (especially pregnant women) and children attacked is stated
to be higher than in men, and one such epidemic is quoted by Oliver
where the rise in the number of miscarriages and premature births
led to the discovery of the fact that the water-supply was
contaminated with lead. The close relationship of lead poisoning to
miscarriage has been repeatedly made out, especially by Oliver, in
the white lead industry as carried on twenty years ago. Oliver also
quotes the effect upon rabbits[9], Glibert upon guinea-pigs[10], and in
the experiments of one of us (K. W. G.), referred to on p. 99, all the
animals to which lead was given during pregnancy aborted; and,
further, with one exception out of eight animals, all died of lead
poisoning, not as the result of the abortion, but some time later,
although no further administration of lead was made. This confirms
the well-known abortifacient effect of diachylon, and there is no
doubt that the lead circulating in the maternal blood determines the
abortion. Further, observers who have examined the fœtus in such
cases have demonstrated the presence of lead in the fœtus itself.
Oliver[11] found that eggs painted with lead nitrate did not hatch out,
and on opening the eggs the embryos were found to have reached
only a limited stage of development, and to have then died, whereas
control eggs painted with lime produced live chicks. From what is
stated later with regard to the curious action of lead upon the blood,
the mechanism of abortion is easily understood; it is probable that
placental hæmorrhages are produced, as in other organs of the
body. But the effect of lead on the female is not only apparent during
pregnancy. A considerable number of women working in lead
processes suffer from amenorrhœa, and often from periods of
menorrhagia and dysmenorrhœa, which as a rule is the more striking
symptom. The effect of lead on the uterine functions, however, only
exists so long as the constant intake of the poison is taking place,
and many cases are recorded where women, after having had
successive abortions while working in lead factories, have ultimately
gone through a normal pregnancy and given birth to a living child.
This circumstance bears a strong analogy to the similar train of
events in syphilis.
In the Report of the Committee on the Use of Lead in the
Potteries, some inquiry was made with regard to the possible
association of lead absorption on the male side as a predisposing
cause of infant mortality and premature birth. The tables given are
not very conclusive, and from our own observations there seems to
be very little evidence for supposing that a male lead worker is less
likely to beget children, or that his children are more likely to be
unhealthy than those of men working in any other industrial process.
We are here speaking of the effect of lead under the conditions of its
general use in this country now. In the absence of any precautions
whatever as to daily absorption of dangerous dust, the effect on the
offspring, even in the case of male lead workers, may well be
evident, as has been shown by Chyzer[12] in the manufacture of
pottery as a home industry in Hungary. One greatly disturbing factor
in estimating the greater susceptibility of the female than the male in
many lead industries is that the more dangerous work is performed
by the women, such, for instance, in the Potteries, as the process of
colour-blowing and ware-cleaning.
Predisposing Causes of Lead Poisoning.—In lead poisoning,
as in many other diseases, a number of predisposing and
contributory causes may be cited which tend to lower the
susceptibility of the individual to the poisonous effect of the metal
and its compounds, or to so modify the functions of the body that a
smaller dose of poison may produce more profound changes than
would otherwise be the case.
Certain diseases may be regarded as predisposing causes by
lowering the general resistance of the body tissues to the influence
of lead, and a consideration of the chapter on Pathology will at once
demonstrate how seriously certain diseases may contribute in this
way.
The peculiar effect of lead is upon the blood and the walls of the
bloodvessels, and it will therefore follow that any disease which may
affect the intima of the bloodvessels may predispose to lead
poisoning; and, further, as the elimination of lead takes place to a
certain extent through the kidney, any disease which affects either
the renal epithelium or the general maintenance of the excretory
function of the kidney may predispose that organ to the irritative
effects of the lead circulating in the blood. In the same way, the
condition of lead absorption in which the balance of absorption and
elimination of lead remains in such a ratio that no definite symptoms
of lead poisoning appear may have that delicate balance easily
upset by the introduction of some secondary cause, which, when
operating in association with lead absorption, may precipitate
symptoms attributable to poisoning by that metal. Chronic alcoholism
especially, producing as it does definite changes in the kidney of
itself—changes which it is impossible to distinguish by the naked eye
from the effects of lead poisoning—must clearly act as a
predisposing, if not even an exciting, cause of lead kidney infection.
In experiments upon animals, it was found that the addition of
alcohol to the diet of an animal which was the subject of chronic lead
absorption precipitated the attack of definite poisoning; in other
words, the latent period of lead poisoning—that is to say, the
resistance exhibited by the tissues to the toxic influence of lead—
was considerably diminished by this addition of a second irritant,
alcohol. In several experiments, also, where the form of lead
experimented with was one of the least toxic of the lead compounds,
the animals subjected to such a compound alone did not become
poisoned, but succumbed if alcohol were added to their diet. This
experimental work is amply borne out by the clinical evidence of all
persons who have had experience of industrial lead poisoning, as
cases of colic and wrist-drop are frequently observed in lead workers
shortly after alcoholic excesses. Individuals, therefore, who are
suspected of the alcoholic habit should not be employed in any
process where they are likely to run risk of absorption of lead dust.
Such diseases as syphilis and gout, by causing a heightened
arterial tension or definite disease of the intima of the bloodvessels
themselves, tend to weaken the arteries in much the same manner
as does lead circulating in the blood, and must on that account act
as predisposing causes.
In persons employed in lead trades some species of tolerance is
generally developed, and if the functions of the body progress in the
normal way the balance of elimination and absorption are equal,
and, as will be seen later, the chief channel for the elimination of lead
from the body is through the bowel. It follows, therefore, that any
disease which tends to produce constipation or chronic inactivity of
the normal intestinal functions will also tend to lower the resistance
of the individual to lead poisoning.
Of the various types of intestinal disease of a chronic nature—
such, for instance, as chronic dysentery, colitis, and the like—little
need be said; but the predisposing effect of diseased conditions of
the upper portion of the alimentary canal must not be overlooked,
more particularly affections of the oral cavity itself. This special type
of infection, often included under the term of “oral sepsis,” besides
producing anæmia, is also a constant cause of intestinal
disturbance, and as such operates as a particular predisposing
cause of lead poisoning.
With regard to gout the evidence is not so clear. It was pointed out
by Garrod[13] that gout was common among house-painters, and it
has been generally stated that lead poisoning predisposes to this
complaint. In the opinion of a considerable number of observers,
however, gout is by no means common among persons working in
white lead factories or lead-smelting works, but there seems to be
some reason to suppose that it is somewhat common among those
persons employed in the painting trades, but not among those
employed in the manufacture of paints and colours. From the
experiments carried out by one of us [K. W. G.[13]]. it seems probable
that the occurrence of gout among painters may be associated with
the use of turpentine, largely employed in the ordinary processes of
painting, as this substance in particular is not one that is used by
workers in other lead trades, and, from experiments performed on
animals, the inhalation of turpentine vapour was found to produce
very definite changes both in the kidney and the general metabolism
of the body.
Malnutrition.—Malnutrition is recognized as a predisposing
cause of practically all forms of disease, and with a chronic
intoxication, such as lead poisoning, malnutrition and starvation, with
its attendant depression of all the vital forces of the body, is
essentially a predisposing cause of poisoning, so much so that even
the fact of commencing work without previously partaking of food
may operate directly as a cause of poisoning. It has been found,
moreover, experimentally by one of us [K. W. G.[14]] that an animal
fed with milk containing lead nitrate did not develop poisoning,
though the control animal developed well-marked symptoms of
poisoning with a much smaller dose given in water.
Anæmia.—Anæmia has already been referred to as occurring
with great frequency in persons who are absorbing lead, and it
usually forms one of the chief factors in the symptom-complex of
lead cachexia. As the action of lead is particularly upon the blood
and the hæmopoietic organs, diminishing the number of red cells
and the amount of hæmoglobin, and impairing the organs from which
fresh blood-cells are produced, a disease or state associated with
anæmia other than of lead origin acts as a definite predisposing
cause in the development of toxic symptoms in a worker in an
industrial lead process.
Among the anæmias, two particular types may be referred to as of
chief importance. In the first place, chlorosis, the anæmia occurring
particularly in young women, is often associated with intestinal
stasis. Lead anæmia occurring in a chlorotic person is always more
severe than simple lead anæmia. Young persons suffering from
chlorosis, therefore, should not be employed in a dangerous lead
process until the anæmia has been treated. The second type of
anæmia, which, from its frequency, may be also regarded as a
predisposing cause of lead poisoning, is chronic secondary septic
anæmia. Anæmias of this type, as was pointed out by William
Hunter[15], resemble in many points the original idiopathic or
Addisonian anæmia, often termed “pernicious anæmia,” and one of
us has had occasion to inquire into the curious type of secondary
anæmia associated with septic affections of the upper respiratory
tract, particularly those related to chronic suppurative affections of
the accessory sinuses of the nose, of the gums, of the mucous
membrane of the mouth and the throat. The commonest forms of this
secondary anæmia are those due to chronic post-nasal discharge,
and to chronic infections of the gums and alveolus of the jaws, the
latter often classed together under the term “pyorrhœa alveolaris.”
This term is an exceedingly clumsy one, indicating a discharge of
pus from the gum edges and sockets of the teeth, which are often
loose. The disease commences as an infective gingivitis along the
edges of the gum, and progresses to rarefying osteitis of the alveolar
process, and often of the body of the bone. The affection rarely gives
rise to pain, and as a rule the individual is entirely unaware that any
chronic suppuration is present, and little or no notice is therefore
taken of the disease. Progressive anæmia may thus be set up
without any knowledge of its cause, partly by absorption of the actual
bacteria and their products through the alveolar bloodvessels, and
partly by the fact of the constant swallowing of pus and bacterial
products, which set up various forms of chronic gastro-intestinal
incompetence. From the discharges of the mouth, and issuing from
the gum edges, numerous bacteria have been isolated, and in more
recent work one of us [K. W. G.[16]] has succeeded in isolating and
identifying certain bacteria as a direct cause of arthritis deformans, a
malady occasionally, but without sufficient grounds, ascribed to lead
poisoning. Arthritis of various types may occur in persons engaged in
lead trades, but in all such cases we have had the opportunity of
examining there has been some obvious source of septic infection,
and no evidence that the arthritis was due to the action of lead. It is
most important to draw the attention of those engaged in the
protection of lead workers from the dangers of their occupation to
these chronic septic conditions of the mouth, and it may be taken as
a general rule that, wherever the blue line makes its appearance
along the gums, such gums are in a state of chronic infection, and
the appearance of the blue line is merely a secondary effect. It is
exceedingly rare to find the blue line in persons with intact gums and
clean teeth; and although attention is frequently drawn to the fact
that a lead line exists in a person whose teeth are normal, little or no
notice is taken of the presence or absence of a suppurative condition
of the gum margins. Moreover, such a suppurative condition does
not always result in obvious inflammation of the gum edges, and
very considerable destruction of the alveolus and the interdental
bone may exist without any obvious signs of its presence, unless the
case be examined carefully with a fine probe. This particular point
has been the subject of experiment by one of us. Animals exposed
to the influence of air laden with lead dust never develop a blue line,
although all the usual symptoms of lead poisoning make their
appearance. When, however, some slight suppurative lesion of the
gums was produced by an inoculation into the gum tissue of
organisms isolated from a case of infective gingivitis in a human
being, the site of inoculation and any suppurative lesion that resulted
locally at once allowed the development of a blue line, and it was
only in animals so treated that it was possible to produce
experimentally the Burtonian line.
There is no doubt that any chronic septic infection may predispose
to lead poisoning through the production of a secondary anæmia,
and it is therefore inadvisable to pass for work in a lead process of a
dangerous nature any persons suffering from an infected condition of
the mouth. It follows also that the care of the mouth and gums
should be rigorously enforced upon all persons employed in lead
trades, as the mere mechanical facilities for the accumulation of
débris around the individual teeth tends to increase the quantity of
lead dust that may be retained in the mouth. This is gradually
rendered soluble and absorbed, through the action of the bacterial
acids which are always produced along the gum margins when any
entangled food is retained in the interdental spaces.
One further point of importance attaches to the infections of the
upper respiratory tract—namely, the constant ingestion of bacteria of
a fermentative type. By this means the contents of the stomach may
be maintained in a state of hyperacidity, and any small quantities of
lead which become swallowed are thereby at once rendered soluble
in the intermeal periods.
Of the other types of anæmia which may act as predisposing
causes of lead poisoning, little need be said, as they are either
associated with other grave symptoms or are rare in this country. But
as all forms of anæmia, particularly septic anæmia, malarial fever,
etc., are associated with destruction of the blood-cells, the presence
of basophile staining granules in the red corpuscles of such persons
is a constant feature, and must not be confounded with the basophile
staining owing its origin to the effect of lead.
In addition to the diseases mentioned which may be said to
predispose to lead poisoning, certain other diseases have been
stated to be predisposed to by the action of lead. It is no doubt a fact
that where chronic anæmia, wasting, loss of subcutaneous fat,
decreased muscular power, and general lowering of the metabolic
activity of the body, are produced, an individual so affected may be
supposed to be more susceptible to certain infectious diseases, and
among these stress has been laid on the alleged association of
phthisis with lead absorption. This point is discussed in the next
chapter.
In summing up the difficult question of predisposition to lead
poisoning, together with the correlated questions of susceptibility and
immunity, certain facts may at any rate be clearly stated:
1. Undoubted individual susceptibility and immunity exist with
regard to lead poisoning in exactly the same way as individual
susceptibility and immunity may be shown to exist towards poisoning
by many other metals and drugs. Therefore, given the same
opportunities for infection, a person showing early signs of lead
absorption may be regarded as susceptible.
2. Females are at least twice, and probably three times, as
susceptible to lead poisoning as are males. Much of this
susceptibility is determined by the extra stress thrown upon the
female generative organs.
3. Certain diseases predispose to lead poisoning mainly by nature
of the alterations in metabolism produced—chiefly anæmia.
4. Many persons engaged in lead industries become gradually
tolerant of the absorption of lead, and in time resist much larger
doses than would have been possible at the commencement of
exposure, but in such persons the balance between absorption and
excretion upon which that tolerance depends may become easily
disturbed by intercurrent disease or sudden increase in absorption.

REFERENCES.
[1] Cloetta: Dixon Mann’s Forensic Medicine and Toxicology, p. 463.
[2] Oliver, Sir T.: Diseases of Occupation, p. 142.
[3] Goadby, K. W.: Departmental Committee on Lead Poisoning, etc., in
China and Earthenware Manufacture, Appendix No. XXV.
[4] Meillère and Richer: Meillère’s Le Saturnisme. Paris, 1903.
[5] Blyth: Abstract of Proc. Chem. Soc., 1887-88.
[6] Hougounencq: Meillère’s Le Saturnisme, p. 73.
[7] Dixon Mann: British Medical Journal, 1893.
[8] Gautier: Société de Biologie, April, 1903.
[9] Oliver, Sir T.: British Medical Journal, May 13, 1911, p. 1096.
[10] Glibert, D. J.: Le Saturnisme Expérimental. Extrait des Rapports
Annuels de l’Inspection du Travail. Bruxelles, 1906.
[11] Oliver, Sir T.: Diseases of Occupation, p. 139.
[12] Chyzer, A.: Des Intoxications par le Plomb se présentant dans la
Céramique en Hongrie. Budapest, 1908.
[13] Garrod: The Lancet, 1870.
[14] Goadby, K. W.: Departmental Committee on Lead Poisoning, etc., in
China and Earthenware Manufacture, Appendix XXV.
[15] Hunter, William: Severest Anæmias.
[16] Goadby, K. W.: The Lancet, March 11, 1911.
CHAPTER IV
STATISTICS OF PLUMBISM[A]
[A] Based mainly on reports received from certifying factory surgeons during the ten years 1900-1909.

Classification of notified cases of lead poisoning was carried out on practically the same
lines between the years 1900 and 1909, and comparison of the data so collected has
interest, in view of their large number—nearly 7,000—in respect of (1) increase or decrease
in recorded amount in each one of eighteen classes of industries; (2) severity and number
of attack—i.e., whether first, second, third, or chronic; and (3) main symptoms.
Notification was first enjoined by Section 29 of the Factory and Workshop Act, 1895,
which subsequently, on consolidation of the Factory Acts, became Section 73 of the Act of
1901. This enactment requires every medical practitioner, attending on, or called in to visit,
a patient whom he believes to be suffering from lead poisoning contracted in a factory or
workshop, to notify the case forthwith to the Chief Inspector of Factories at the Home Office;
and a similar obligation is imposed on the occupier of a factory or workshop to send written
notice of every such case to the certifying surgeon and inspector of factories for the district.
In form there is close similarity between this section and that requiring notification under the
Infectious Diseases (Notification) Act; but whereas the symptoms of these diseases are,
within well-recognized limits, precise, in lead poisoning the differential diagnosis has not
infrequently to be made from a variety of common ailments—headache, anæmia,
rheumatism, abdominal pain; and there is no precise standard of what constitutes lead
poisoning.
The notification of the practitioner as a rule gives no information beyond the belief that the
case is one of lead poisoning. As a matter of routine the notification is followed up by an
inquiry by the certifying surgeon and inspector to see whether regulations already in force
have been infringed in the particular work-place or not, and as to how far there may have
been contributory negligence on the part of the sufferer. The data supplied on the surgeon’s
report form the basis of the tabulation[1]. Brief explanation is wanted of the method adopted
in classification. Cases represent all attacks reported within a year, and not previously
reported within the preceding twelve months, so as to make the number of persons and
cases in a year the same. Where the interval between two reports on the same person was
more than twelve months, the fresh attack was again included. The number of such second
reports on persons already included in a return numbered 284 (4·2 per cent.), and a portion
of these certainly, probably not more than 100, have been included twice or thrice in the
total 6,638 cases. Cases in which there was obvious error in diagnosis, or in which the
opinion of the certifying surgeon was very strongly against the diagnosis (especially when
the report had been made in the first instance by the occupier alone, and not by a medical
practitioner), were excluded from the return. These numbered 458 (6·8 per cent.). Others,
again, where there was a strong element of doubt, but not to be regarded as more than a
difference of opinion between two medical men, were marked doubtful and included. Of
these there were 424 (6·3 per cent.).
The classification of industries was designed to represent the way in which the poisoning
may be supposed to originate from (a) lead fumes (1 to 4), (b) handling metallic lead (5 and
6), (c) dust from lead compounds (7 to 14), and (d) lead paint (15 to 17). We attach now
only slight importance to this attempt to define causation, as it will appear from our survey
that we regard almost all cases as the result of inhalation either of fumes or dust.
The reports describe not only the particular attack, but also the general condition of the
patient at the time of the attack. Very frequently a combination of symptoms—colic,
anæmia, and varying degree of paralysis—are described as present, and when this is the
case each one of them has been entered under the appropriate heading. The total number
of symptoms, therefore, greatly exceeds the number of cases, but this does not affect the
correctness of the estimate of each one as a proportion on the total number reported. The
reports do not give detailed information such as can be gained from hospital records.
Especially is this the case with the symptoms of paralysis and encephalopathy.
Table III. shows the number of reported cases included in returns for each of the years
1900 to 1909. On the total figures there has been a reduction of 47·7 per cent. In the
several industries the salient feature is that the considerable diminution achieved is limited
to industries—notably white lead, earthenware and china, litho-transfers, and paints and
colours—in which, under regulations or special rules, locally applied exhaust ventilation for
the removal of dust, and periodical medical examination of the workers, have been required.
Where, owing to the nature of the processes carried on, it has been found impracticable, in
the present state of knowledge, to apply local exhaust ventilation, and where periodical
examination of the workers is lacking, as in smelting of metals[A] and industries using paint,
there has been tendency to increase in the number of cases. In coach-building the increase
is in part due to activity in the motor-car industry.
[A] This is now required by the regulations dated August 12, 1911.

TABLE III.—NOTIFICATION OF POISONING BY LEAD (under S. 73, 1901), 1900-1909.


Reported Cases.
Total
Industry. 1900-09. 1909. 1908. 1907. 1906. 1905. 1904. 1903. 1902. 1901. 1900.
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8) (9) (10) (11) (12)
Lead poisoning 6,762 275 553 646 578 632 592 597 614 629 863 1,05838
30 32 26 33 23 26 19 14 34

1. Smelting of
metals 41218 665 702 282 381 241 331 372 28 543 341
2. Brass works 754 5 6 91 11 51 101 15 5 61 3
3. Sheet lead and
lead piping 1093 92 14 6 7 9 7 11 12 17 171
4. Plumbing and
soldering 21712 28 27 202 164 242 213 26 231 23 9
5. Printing 20017 211 302 263 162 194 15 132 19 231 182
6. File-cutting 21119 8 92 10 15 12 204 242 271 467 403
7. Tinning and
enamelling 1382 21 10 25 181 141 10 14 11 10 5
8. White lead 1,29531 322 793 71 1087 901 1162 1092 1431 1897 3586
9. Red lead 108 10 12 7 6 10 11 6 13 14 19
10. China and
earthenware 1,06557 585 11712 1038 1074 843 1064 973 874 1065 2008
10a. Litho-transfers 48 1 2 10 5 5 3 3 2 7 10
11. Glass cutting
and polishing 489 42 31 4 41 3 — 4 82 113 7
12. Enamelling iron
plates 521 3 7 6 4 2 3 4 31 9 11
13. Electric 2856 272 251 21 26 271 33 28 161 491 33
accumulators
14. Paints and
colours 4227 392 25 351 37 571 321 391 46 56 561
15. Coach-building 69741 956 703 703 857 563 494 745 631 654 705
16. Ship-building 26910 271 15 221 261 322 48 241 151 281 322
17. Paint used in
other
industries 45218 42 471 492 373 492 273 461 441 61 505
18. Other
industries 65920 572 785 562 662 701 533 40 64 891 864

The principal figures are those of the cases, fatal and non-fatal; the small figures relate to fatal cases only.
For the sake of completeness the figures for the years 1910 and 1911 are given below. The grand totals are
comparable with those for each of the years 1900 to 1909, but not the total for all of the several groups of
industries. Thus, the name of heading No. 7 is altered to “Tinning of metals,” and No. 12 to “Vitreous
enamelling,” because of regulations widening their scope, and now including cases which previously figured in
No. 18, “Other industries.”

Industry. 1911. 1910.


Lead poisoning 66937 50538
Smelting of metals 483 345
Brass works 91 7
Sheet lead and lead piping 12 4
Plumbing and soldering 372 251
Printing 322 334
File-cutting 182 91
Tinning of metals 13 17
Vitreous enamelling 191 17
White lead 412 341
Red lead 131 10
China and earthenware 926 7711
Litho-transfers 1 1
Glass cutting and polishing 5 —
Electric accumulators 241 31
Paints and colours 21 171
Coach and car painting 1045 706
Ship-building 366 212
Use of paint in other industries 561 513
Other industries 884 473

TABLE IV.—ANALYSIS OF REPORTS ON LEAD POISONING BY CERTIFYING


SURGEONS FROM JANUARY 1, 1900, TO DECEMBER 31, 1909.

Severity of Symptoms. Number of Attack.


Third,
No. Occupation. Total. Severe. Moderate. Slight. First. Second. Chron
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8) (9)
M. F. M. F. M. F. M. F. M. F. M. F. M.
1 Smelting of
metals:
Cases 411 — 104 — 105 — 197 — 276 — 65 — 64 —
Per cent. 100 — 25·3 — 25·6 — 47·9 — 67·2 — 16·8 — 15·6 —
2 Brass works:

You might also like