You are on page 1of 17

Child Development, March/April 1999, Volume 70, Number 2, Pages 396–412

Development of Children’s Knowledge about Unconsciousness


John H. Flavell, Frances L. Green, Eleanor R. Flavell, and Nancy T. Lin

Children of ages 5, 6, 7, 8, and 10 years, and adults were asked whether people who are sound asleep and
not dreaming could or would: (1) see, hear, listen, notice, think, wish, pretend, and feel things (primary-
consciousness activities), (2) know that they are asleep, and know whether they are or are not engaged in
primary-consciousness activities such as perceiving and thinking (reflective-consciousness activities), (3) delib-
erately decide to or try to perform mental or physical actions (control activities). Results indicated that the rec-
ognition that people do not engage in conscious mental activities when unconscious is still developing during
the late middle-childhood years. We speculate that a developing understanding of consciousness may assist
the development of an understanding of unconsciousness and vice versa, and that sensitivity to the phenome-
nology as contrasted with the content of mental states may be a late acquisition in the theory-of-mind area.

INTRODUCTION bed), one is not aware of doing them and one cannot
decide to do or not do them.
Psychologists have learned a great deal about the de-
We have found only one empirical study of adults’
velopment of children’s knowledge about the mind
intuitions about consciousness (Kemp & Strongman,
during the past decade. Reviews of this extensive
1994), and that one yielded very limited information.
theory-of-mind research literature can be found in, for
In that study, adult participants were merely asked to
example, Astington (1993), Bartsch and Wellman (1995),
indicate whether they thought animals, very young
Flavell and Miller (1998), Lewis and Mitchell (1994),
children, and retarded people “are conscious or aware
Perner (1991), Taylor (1996), and Wellman and Gel-
in the way we are” (not further defined) and then to
man (1992). Despite all this work, however, we still
write a brief definition of what they understood con-
know virtually nothing about children’s understand-
sciousness to be. The authors found that most partic-
ing of certain aspects of the mental world. One of
ipants attributed at least limited consciousness to
these neglected topics is their knowledge about what
these other beings and cited awareness of environ-
mental life is like when one is conscious as opposed to
ment, other people, and/or the self in their defini-
unconscious. We believe that in our culture at least,
tions of consciousness.
most adults have intuitions about the conscious-
It is unclear what children of different ages would
unconscious distinction that run roughly as follows
be expected to know about this aspect of mental life.
(cf. Flavell, Green, & Flavell, 1998). When one is con-
We are aware of no previous developmental studies
scious one experiences a more or less continuous
in this area. One might suppose that children would
stream of consciousness (James, 1890) consisting of a
know quite a bit, at least by age 5 or so. There is first
succession of thoughts, percepts, feelings, and other
of all the abundant research evidence that they have
mental states and contents. One is at least intermit-
acquired some knowledge about thinking, perceiv-
tently aware of who one is and what one is currently
ing, feeling, and other mental states by this age (see
doing, oriented in time and place, and able to attend
the reviews just cited). Indeed, much of the research
consciously to both external and internal events. One
literature in this area contrasts the ability of 4- and 5-
is also able to decide to stop doing one thing and do
year-olds to solve false-belief, appearance–reality, and
another; that is, one can to some extent consciously
other theory-of-mind tasks with the frequent inability of
direct, redirect, and otherwise deliberately control
younger children to do so. Furthermore, like their elders,
one’s own physical and mental actions. In marked
they have had daily opportunities to contrast the vivid
contrast, none of these events occur when one is com-
experiences of self and world that they have when
pletely unconscious. In a deep and dreamless sleep
awake with their inability to recall having had any such
state, for example, one may be able to perceive and re-
experiences while deep asleep and not dreaming.
spond to some events at some low, nonconscious
However, there are also reasons to suspect that
level (e.g., stir in response to a sudden noise or some-
children of this age might at least be less aware of the
one’s touch), but one is not aware of having perceived
differences between consciousness and unconscious-
or responded to anything provided that one remains
sound asleep. Similarly, although one may be able to © 1999 by the Society for Research in Child Development, Inc.
do certain things while in this state (e.g., turn over in All rights reserved. 0009-3920/99/7002-0010
Flavell et al. 397

ness than their elders. For one thing, there is evidence preschool. The two older child groups were elemen-
that they underestimate the amount of mental content tary school children drawn from a community college
people experience during the waking state (Flavell, summer program: the (mostly) 7-year-old group con-
Green, & Flavell, 1993, 1995a). For example, they are sisted of 6 girls and 12 boys (M 5 7,4, range 5 6,9–8,9)
apt not to realize that there is a stream of conscious- who had completed first grade; the (mostly) 8-year-
ness that flows spontaneously even when a person is old group was composed of 8 boys and 10 girls (M 5
just sitting idly, not engaged in any task. In fact, they 8,1, range 5 7,6–8,8) who had completed second
sometimes even say that nothing is going on in the grade. The adults were 7 male and 11 female college
mind of a person who is obviously engaged in a cog- students. The participants were from primarily upper-
nitive task. In addition, children of this age show very middle-class families, and were mostly Caucasian and
limited introspective skills (Flavell, et al., 1995a; Fla- Asian. One experimenter tested the adults and a second
vell, Green, Flavell, & Grossman, 1997). That is, they experimenter tested the children.
often deny that they have just been thinking when
they clearly must have been (e.g., because they had
Procedure
just been presented with something that is very
thought-provoking), just as they often fail to infer that Main tasks. The experimenter showed the partici-
others are thinking when they, too, clearly must have pant the first of several pictures, a line drawing de-
been. If, as appears to be the case, they are less intro- picting a child sitting up in bed with a picture of a
spective than older people and less aware of the near- boat on the wall and a tape recorder on the bed. The
continuous flow of conscious mental experience in child, named Lee, was identified as a boy for male
the conscious state, they may also be less aware of its participants and as a girl for female participants. The
absence in the unconscious state, and, more generally, experimenter said: “Lee has been sick all day with a
less knowledgeable about levels of consciousness or tummy ache. She (or he) has been feeling sad because
attention. The purpose of the present studies was to she doesn’t feel well and because she is missing the
probe adult intentions about such matters and com- trip to the fire station with her class at school. She had
pare them with those of children of different ages. really wanted to see all those fire engines. She spent
the morning looking at the picture of the boat on the
wall; she saw the sun and all the waves; she even
STUDY 1 counted how many waves there were.” Picture 2,
with the child in a slightly different position, was then
In this study, 5-year-olds, 7-year-olds, 8-year-olds,
shown. The experimenter continued: “All morning
and adults were tested for their understanding of the
long she kept wanting something to drink. ‘I’m so
difference between the mental activities and experi-
thirsty today. I really want some ginger ale. Mom said
ences that occur when a person is conscious versus
I could have some with my lunch. I wish I had some
not conscious. Participants were read an illustrated
right now!’ While she was in bed, she listened to
story about various mental activities and experiences
some music on her tape recorder. She played her fa-
a child had while awake: feeling A, seeing B, listening
vorite songs. She also heard the birds singing in the
to C, thinking about D, and so forth. They were then
tree outside her window. She decided to pretend that
asked if the child continued to have these same men-
she was in a tree house instead of in her bed. But she
tal states later, when sound asleep and not dreaming.
knew she was awake in her own bed. Finally Lee fell
A similar method had been pilot-tested previously
asleep just before lunch time (Picture 3 shows her
with a group of 20 college students. The percentages
lying down). Here she is, sound asleep, under the
of these students who agreed with our intuitions that,
covers.” The experimenter then gave each participant
once asleep, the child would not continue to have
experience saying both “yes” and “no” to questions
these mental states ranged from 85% to 100%.
about Lee by asking, in counterbalanced order: “All
morning Lee has been in bed. Now she’s sound
Method asleep. Is she still in bed? That’s right/Actually, She is
still in bed.” and “All morning Lee has been sitting
Participants
up. Now she’s sound asleep. Is she still sitting up?
Three groups of children and one group of adults That’s right/Actually, she’s not still sitting up.” No
were tested, with 18 participants in each group. The corrective feedback was given during testing.
youngest group, 5-year-olds, consisted of nine boys The questioning continued with reference to cop-
and nine girls (mean age in years and months 5 5,4, ies of Picture 3, showing the child in a sleep state.
range 5 5,0–5,6) drawn from a university laboratory Each of the next eight questions were of the following
398 Child Development

form: “All morning Lee has been ____ (e.g., looking at “While you are asleep and not dreaming can you
the picture of the boat on the wall). Right now, she is know you are asleep, or not?” followed by “How can
sound asleep and not dreaming. Is she still ____ (e.g., you know that?” or “Why can’t you know that?”
seeing the picture)?” The eight states or activities que- The Awareness and Decision questions were pre-
ried in this way were: seeing the picture, wishing she sented in counterbalanced order across participants
had some ginger ale, pretending to be in a tree house, and the order of choices within these questions was
know she’s asleep (as contrasted with the previous: also counterbalanced. The Sleep questions were al-
knew she was awake), thinking about the fire station, ways given last.
listening to the music, hear the birds, and feeling sad.
The eight questions were presented in a different ran-
Results
dom order to each participant within each group,
with the same set of 18 random orders being used for Table 1 shows the percentages of participants in
all four groups. each age group who said that each of the listed mental
Additional tasks. The children in the two elemen- states would not continue to occur after a child story
tary school groups only were then asked the follow- character passed from a conscious waking state to an
ing three sets of questions: unconscious, dreamless-sleep state. As the numbers
Awareness of feeling states. The experimenter said: with asterisks indicate, as a group the 5-year-olds
“Let me explain what I mean by the word ‘aware’. showed a significant tendency to deny to the uncon-
When I am aware of something, I am paying attention scious child only the experience of seeing the picture—
to it. I know it is happening right now. Right now I am not a difficult inference given that the character was
aware that you are sitting across from me. I am paying portrayed with her eyes closed and facing away from
attention to you. I am also aware that the chair I am sit- the picture. In contrast, the two older child groups
ting in is uncomfortable. Well, I asked two children significantly denied auditory as well as visual experi-
about what it feels like to be deep asleep and not ences, with the 8-year-old group also significantly de-
dreaming. One child said: ‘While I am deep asleep nying pretending. Finally, the adult group signifi-
and not dreaming, I am aware that I feel peaceful, cantly denied the occurrence of all eight mental
quiet, calm. I am aware of these feelings while I am states, the more cognitive and affective ones as well as
sleeping.’ The experimenter paused briefly. “The other the more perceptual ones. Thus, the adults’ intuitions
child said: ‘While I am deep asleep and not dreaming. about conscious-unconscious differences tended to be
I am not aware of feeling anything. I am not aware of coincide with our own and with those of most of
any feelings while I am sleeping.’” The experimenter the 20 adult participants in the pilot study. Three of the
paused again. “Which child do you think is more states (wishing, knowing, hearing) showed signifi-
right?” After the participant had responded the ex- cant, p , .05, increases in denial with age by x2 or
perimenter confirmed the choice by repeating the Fisher exact test; another (thinking) showed a near-
critical portion of the chosen statement (“The one significant, p , .10, increase with age.
who said I am not aware of feeling anything?” or “The Summing across all eight questions, the mean per-
one who said I am aware that I feel peaceful, calm and
quiet?”) She then continued, “OK. Why do you think
that child was more right?” Table 1 Percentage of Correct Responses to Main Task Ques-
Ability to make decisions. The experimenter said: tions in Study 1
“When you make decisions about things you are mak- Percentage of Correct Responses
ing choices, aren’t you? Like you can decide what
program you’d like to see on TV or what books you Task Question 5-Year-Olds 7-Year-Olds 8-Year-Olds Adults
want to read. I asked two children about making de-
cisions while they were deep asleep and not dream- Seeing 89* 100* 94* 94*
Wishing 56 50 61 94*
ing. One child said: ‘While I am deep asleep and not Pretending 61 61 83* 89*
dreaming, I can make decisions about things.’ The Know asleep 39 61 72 89*
other child said: ‘While I am deep asleep and not Thinking 44 56 67 83*
dreaming, I can not make decisions about things.’” Listening 61 83* 83* 83*
The experimenter then asked: “Which child do you Hear 44 78* 94* 78*
Feeling sad 56 72 56 78*
think is more right?” After the participant’s choice
was confirmed as before, the experimenter asked why Note: Percentages significantly, p , .03, different from chance ex-
that child was more right. pectation of 50% according to the binomial table are marked with
Knowledge of sleep state. The experimenter said: an asterisk.
Flavell et al. 399

centages correct were, from youngest to oldest group, quate justifications of correct answers. To illustrate, a
56%, 70%, 76%, and 86%, with all but the 5-year-olds’ justification of a correct answer would be scored as
percentage being significantly, p , .05, above chance adequate if it appealed to the fact that a person’s senses
by t test. The numbers of participants in each group are shut down when the person is in a dreamless
responding correctly to at least 7 of the 8 questions sleep, or if it made vague or implicit references to the
were 4, 9, 8, and 12 from youngest to oldest group, a absence of consciousness or awareness (no child par-
near-significant age trend: x2(3, N 5 72) 5 7.33, p , ticipant actually described the person as not being
.10. A simple analysis of variance (ANOVA) per- “conscious” when in that state). The percentages of
formed upon participants’ total-number-of-ques- 7- and 8-year-olds who both answered correctly and
tions-correct scores, range 5 0–8, yielded a significant also adequately justified their correct answer accord-
age effect, F(3, 68) 5 4.31, p , .01. Subsequent pair- ing to our fairly generous criteria were, respectively,
wise group comparisons by Tukey test showed that 28% and 6% for the Awareness question, 39% and
the adults had significantly, p , .01, higher scores 50% for the Decision question, and 44% and 33% for
than the 5-year-olds, with all the other pairwise com- the Sleep question. Although these percentages and
parisons failing to show significant group differences. those in Table 2 are not very high, a few responses tes-
In the Awareness, Decision, and Sleep questions tified to a quite good understanding of what things
presented at the end of the testing session, the 7- and are like when one is deeply asleep. These are among
8-year-olds were asked whether a person who was the best examples: “It’s just like you are dead except
deep asleep and not dreaming would be aware of any you come back to life in the morning.” “When you are
feelings, could make decisions, and would know that [asleep but] not dreaming you don’t really have any-
he or she was asleep. Table 2 shows the percentages of thing in your brain so you can’t make a decision.”
children in each group who correctly answered these “You do not know you are in your bed or that your
questions in the negative, both as their initial re- eyes are closed because you are sleeping.”
sponse and as their final judgment after attempting to Finally, for each of these two groups the numbers
justify their initial response. As the table indicates, of participants’ correct answers in the main task were
only 1 of the 12 percentages was significantly higher correlated with those in the additional task (initial an-
than would be expected by chance—namely, the final swers only). The consistency proved to be quite high
judgments of the 8-year-olds about knowledge of for the 7-year-olds, r(17) 5 .69, but not for the 8-year-
being asleep. The numbers of 7- and 8-year-olds an- olds, r(17) 5 .21.
swering all three questions correctly (final judg-
ments) were six and five, respectively—thus, only
STUDY 2
about one third of the sample.
A category system was devised to score the 7- and Farthing (1992) makes the following interesting dis-
8-year-olds’ justifications for their correct and incor- tinction between primary consciousness and reflective
rect responses; this same category system was also consciousness:
used in Study 2. Two judges scored the three sets of Reflective consciousness consists of thoughts about one’s
justifications separately (interjudge agreement for the own conscious experiences per se. In primary conscious-
three sets ranged from 83% to 89%) and then resolved ness you are the subject who does the thinking, feeling,
any disagreements by discussion. The category of and acting in regard, mainly, to external objects and
principal interest was that of at least minimally ade- events. But in reflective consciousness your own con-
scious experiences—percepts, thoughts, feelings, and
actions—are the objects of your thoughts. Thus, in pri-
Table 2 Percentage of Correct Responses to Additional Task
Questions in Study 1 mary consciousness you might perceive an event . . . and
have thoughts about that event. But in reflective con-
Percentage of Correct Responses sciousness you might have thoughts not about the event
itself, but about your thoughts concerning that event (Far-
Task Question 7-Year-Olds 8-Year-Olds thing, 1992, p. 13).

Awareness of feeling states 56 (50) 56 (56) Variations on this distinction are often encountered in
Ability to make decisions 67 (67) 61 (61) philosophical discussions of consciousness (e.g.,
Knowledge of sleep state 61 (72) 50 (78*) Rosenthal, 1993). A few of the test items in Study 1 as-
sessed children’s knowledge about reflective con-
Note: Percentages significantly, p , .03, different from chance ex-
pectation of 50% according to the binomial table are marked with
sciousness, notably the know-asleep questions in the
an asterisk. Numbers in parentheses reflect children’s final an- main and additional tasks and the awareness-of-
swers following their attempts to justify their initial response. feelings question in the additional tasks. However,
400 Child Development

the majority tested their knowledge only about pri- children were of mean age 6, 8, and 10 years and were
mary consciousness, for example, about whether the drawn from the first, third, and fifth grades of a local
story character saw, heard, and thought about various elementary school. The 6-year-old group consisted of
external objects or events while asleep. 6 girls and 12 boys (mean age in years and months 5
Accordingly, one purpose of Study 2 was to obtain 6,5, range 5 5,11–6,10). The (mostly) 8-year-old group
more and better evidence concerning children’s knowl- consisted of 9 girls and 9 boys (mean age 5 8,6,
edge about consciousness of this more metacognitive range 5 7,10–9,4). The (mostly) 10-year-old group
reflective type. We tried to do this in several tasks by consisted of 11 girls and 7 boys (mean age 5 10,7,
first asking participants about the presence or ab- range 5 10,1–11,7). The adults were 15 female and 3
sence of a particular example of primary conscious- male college students. The participants were from
ness in a sleeping story character and then asking primarily upper middle class families and were mostly
them about the presence or absence of reflective con- Caucasian and Asian. The same female experimenter
sciousness concerning that same example. In one task (E1), assisted by a second female experimenter (E2),
(Hear), for example, participants first were asked tested all participants.
whether a deeply sleeping story character heard
the rain that was beating against his bedroom win-
Procedure
dow (primary consciousness). Then, depending upon
whether they answered this question in the affirma- Pretraining. Because the term know has several dif-
tive or in the negative, they either were asked if the ferent meanings, the first experimenter (E1) began the
character knows he is hearing it or if he knows he is testing session by trying to restrict participants’ inter-
not hearing it (reflective consciousness). We hoped pretation of the term to that of a person’s present
that this two-stage questioning procedure would awareness of ongoing mental and physical events.
make it clearer to the participants that the second, She did this by providing a variety of examples of
reflective-consciousness question concerned the char- things she presently “knew,” e.g., that she was feeling
acter’s awareness-nonawareness of his own psycho- happy (mental event) and that the participant was sit-
logical activity (or lack thereof) rather than the mere ting there (physical event). Then she asked the partic-
presence-absence of the activity itself. ipants a series of questions similar to those they
A second purpose of Study 2 was to assess children’s would be asked during subsequent testing and she
understanding that not only are nondreaming sleepers supplied the correct answer if they erred. For exam-
not consciously aware of the presence or absence of ob- ple, she asked the second experimenter (E2) to face
jects, events, and activities, they are also unable to con- away from her, held up three fingers and told E2 that
sciously and deliberately initiate or change activities or she was doing that, and then asked the participants
otherwise try to exert control over them. As noted in the whether E2 sees her fingers right now (correct an-
introduction, although a person may be able to do some swer: no) and then whether E2 knows she does not
things while in an unconscious state, the person is not see them (correct answer: yes). They were also asked
only unaware of doing them but also—and for that similar questions about situations in which (1) E2 sees
very reason—incapable of deliberately deciding to do something and knows she sees it, (2) knows that a cer-
them or refrain from doing them. Although one of the tain object she cannot see is behind her, and (3) does
additional task questions in Study 1 tested for this latter not know that a certain object is not behind her (she
understanding of control (the Decision question), it was knew it was there previously but does not know it is
assessed more thoroughly in Study 2. no longer there). Eight 6-year-olds, two 8-year-olds,
Finally, in addition to tests of knowledge concern- and two adults responded incorrectly to at least one
ing the possibility of reflective consciousness and of these four know questions and received corrective
control-of-activity when in a dreamless sleep, we also feedback. These participants were then questioned
included tasks designed to assess knowledge con- about another situation similar to (3). All of them an-
cerning primary consciousness plus a task question swered all of these additional questions correctly.
(Notice) that could be interpreted as referring either The testing then began with the following pre-
to primary or to reflective consciousness. amble: “I want to explain something about what hap-
pens when you are deep asleep at night. Part of the
Method time when you are deep asleep you dream about
things, and part of the time you don’t do any dream-
Participants
ing at all. I am going to ask you only about those
Three groups of children and one group of adults times when people are deep asleep and not dream-
were tested, with 18 participants in each group. The ing.” The first three tasks—Think, Hear, and Act—
Flavell et al. 401

were then presented in counterbalanced order. In negative. We recognized that some of the Think and
the Think and Hear tasks E1 first asked a primary- Hear questions ended up being rather odd (e.g.,
consciousness question about whether a person who “Does he know he is not hearing the rain?”), but could
was deep asleep and not dreaming could be thinking not think of a better way to make salient the differ-
about something (in the Think task) or would have ence between mental activities (primary conscious-
heard something (in the Hear task). In each of these ness) and awareness and conscious control of those
tasks she then asked a reflective-consciousness ques- mental activities (reflective consciousness and con-
tion followed by a control-of-activity question. In the trol-of-activity). Recall also that the Pretraining was
Act task she asked only a reflective-consciousness designed to familiarize the children with such ques-
question followed by a control-of-activity question. tion forms, at least a little.
Think. E1 displayed a line drawing of a sleeping Act. In this task E1 began by saying: “Here is a
girl and said: “Here is a little girl named Anna. She is child named Mark. He is deep asleep and not dream-
deep asleep and not dreaming. Here is the first ques- ing. Just a second ago, while he was sleeping, he
tion. She is still asleep and not dreaming. Could she moved his body. He was sleeping on his back but he
be thinking about something—like could she be rolled over and now he is sleeping on his side.” Then,
thinking about her toys?” E1 then repeated which- after the usual reminder that the child was still asleep
ever answer the participant gave in a matter-of-fact and not dreaming, the knowledge question was
tone: “She can (cannot) be thinking about that, okay.” “Does he know that he rolled over?” and the control-
If the participant had said she could be thinking of-activity question was “Can he think to himself
about the toys the next two questions were as follows: ‘Hmm. I am going to roll over again’?”
“You decided she could be thinking about something, The remaining tasks were then given in the order
like maybe her toys. Here is a question about what listed. E1 introduced them by saying: “Now I have
Anna knows right now. She is still asleep and not some questions to ask you, about when you are deep
dreaming. Does she know she is thinking about her asleep and not dreaming.”
toys?” After repeating the participant’s answer to this Asleep. “Suppose you are very tired. Almost as
knowledge question, E1 continued with the control- soon as you get in bed you fall asleep. You have been
of-activity question: “Here is one more question. She deep asleep and not dreaming for about an hour. While
is still asleep and not dreaming. Can she think to her- you are like that, do you know that you are asleep?”
self ‘Hmm. I am going to start thinking about my See. “While you are awake and your eyes are
friends instead of my toys now’?” If the participant closed, you see black or dark gray. Suppose you have
had initially said that Anna could not be thinking, the been deep asleep for about an hour. You are not
ensuing test procedure was identical to that above ex- dreaming and your eyes are closed. While you are
cept that the knowledge question became “Does she like that, do you see black or dark gray or do you not
know she is not thinking about anything?” and the see anything at all?” (The order of choices within the
subsequent control-of-activity question became “Can question was unsystematically varied.) E1 then
she think to herself ‘Hmm. I am going to start thinking asked: “While you are deep asleep and not dreaming,
about my toys now’?” do you know that you see black or dark gray (you
Hear. The procedure for this task was essentially don’t see anything)?”
the same as that for the Think task. Participants were Try. “While you are deep asleep and not dream-
shown a picture of a sleeping boy with rain streaks on ing, can you try to think about something, and do it,
his bedroom window. E1 said: “Here is a child named on purpose?”
Larry. He is deep asleep and not dreaming. Just a sec- Notice. “While you are awake, even with your eyes
ond ago, while he was asleep, a big storm started out- closed, you can notice and know about all sorts of
side. The wind is howling and blowing the rain things that are happening around you and inside you.
against his window. Pitter pat, pitter pat.” The first You can notice that you are feeling happy and you can
question was “Does he hear the rain?” The knowl- know that you are thinking about going out to play
edge question was then either “Does he know he is (seeing some friends). You can pay attention to smells
hearing the rain?” or “Does he know he is not hearing coming from the kitchen and figure out what you are
the rain?” The control-of-activity question then be- having for dinner—things like that. How about while
came either “Can he think to himself ‘Hmm. I am go- you are deep asleep and not dreaming? Can you no-
ing to start listening to the wind instead of the rain tice or pay attention to anything while you are that
now’?” if the answer to the hear question was affir- way?” If the response was “yes”, E1 asked “What
mative, or “Can he think to himself, ‘Hmm, I am going kinds of things can you notice or pay attention to?” If
to start listening to the rain now’?” if the answer was the response was “no”, E1 asked “Why not?”
402 Child Development

Asleep justification. E1 reminded the participants Table 3 Percentage of Correct Responses to Task Questions in
of their responses to the Asleep question by saying: Study 2
“You decided that when you have been deep asleep Percentage of Correct Responses
and not dreaming for about an hour, you know (do not
know) that you are asleep.” Next she asked either 6- 8- 10-
“How do you know that?” or “Why don’t you know Year- Year- Year-
Task Question Olds Olds Olds Adults
that?” As some participants responded to this ques-
tion, it became clear to E1 that they had misunder- Reflective consciousness
stood the Asleep question. For example, some partic- Think 61 56 67 78*
ipants described how they knew they were about to Hear 44 72 78* 83*
go to sleep or how they knew they had been asleep, Act 72 78* 100* 89*
rather than how they knew they were asleep. In such See 22* 83* 61 72
Asleep 39 78* 67 94*
instances, E2 repeated what they had just said, but Asleep: adequate
also repeated the test question in abbreviated form: justification 6 50 50 89*
“Well, how about when you are deep asleep and not Control-of-activity
dreaming for about an hour. While you are like that, Think 56 50 72 83*
do you know you are asleep?” Following such ques- Hear 72 72 89* 89*
tion clarification a number of participants changed Act 61 78* 89* 89*
Try 56 67 78* 83*
their responses. Additionally, some participants
changed their initial responses spontaneously, as they Primary consciousness
Think 39 50 56 61
thought about the question further. Accordingly, only Hear 50 72 72 44
a participant’s final, considered response to the See 22* 61 50 83*
Asleep question was used in subsequent data analy- Notice 67 89* 83* 72
ses; the same was true of the Notice question. Notice: adequate
The adequacy of participants’ justifications of their justification 33 72 56 72
answers to the Notice and Asleep questions was as-
Note: Percentages significantly, p , .03, different from chance ex-
sessed by two judges using the same scoring systems pectation of 50% according to the binomial table are marked with
employed in Study 1. As in that study, the few inter- an asterisk, with the exception of the two sets of adequate justifica-
judge disagreements that occurred were resolved tion percentages.
by discussion.

and not dreaming would be engaging in the mental


Results
activity in question.
The Think, Hear, Act, See, and Asleep tasks each Considering first the questions about reflective
contained a knowledge question designed to test par- consciousness, Table 3 shows that as a group the 6-
ticipants’ understanding about reflective conscious- year-olds evinced no significant tendency to deny
ness. (Although the knowledge question in the Act knowledge of the presence or absence of any of the
task concerned awareness of a physical rather than a five activities or states queried. In fact, they showed a
mental action—namely, rolling over in bed—it seemed significant tendency to assert such knowledge on the
to test much the same sort of knowledge as the other See task (78%) rather than deny it (22%). Thus, a good
four questions.) Likewise, the Think, Hear, Act, and number of them variously said that while sleeping a
Try tasks each contained a question about conscious person would know that he or she was (or was not)
control-of-activity. Finally, the Think, Hear, and See thinking, hearing, acting physically, seeing, and in a
tasks each began with a question about primary con- sleep state. In contrast, the 8-year-olds tended signif-
sciousness. Although it was possible to construe the icantly to deny such awareness in the case of acting,
Notice question as a reflective-consciousness one, as seeing, and asleep, the 10-year-olds did the same for
noted, almost all the participants seemed to construe hearing and acting, and the adults did so for thinking,
it as a primary-consciousness one concerning atten- hearing, acting, and asleep. Summing across all five
tion to external events. Consequently, we have grouped questions, the mean percentages correct were, from
it with the other three primary-consciousness ques- youngest to oldest group, 48%, 73%, 74%, and 83%,
tions for purposes of data analysis. Table 3 shows the with all but 6-year-olds’ percentage significantly (p ,
percentages of participants in each age group who an- .05) above chance by t test. The numbers of partici-
swered each of these 13 questions in the negative, pants in each group responding correctly to at least 4
thereby denying that a person who was sound asleep of the 5 reflective-consciousness questions were 5, 10,
Flavell et al. 403

10, and 15 from youngest to oldest group, a signifi- consciousness questions, the mean percentages cor-
cant age trend: x2(3, N 5 72) 5 11.25, p , .02. A simple rect were, from youngest to oldest group, 40%, 68%,
ANOVA performed upon participants’ total-questions- 65%, and 65%, with only the two middle groups’ per-
correct scores here (range 5 0–5) also yielded a signif- centages significantly, p , .05, above chance by t test
icant age effect, F(3, 68) 5 5.10, p , .01. Subsequent (the adults’ percentage approached significance—
pairwise group comparisons by Tukey tests showed namely, p , .10). The numbers of participants in
that each of the three older groups had significantly, each group responding negatively to at least three of
p , .01, higher scores than the 6-year-olds, with none the four primary-consciousness questions were 5, 8,
of the other pairwise comparisons yielding signifi- 10, and 11 in order of increasing age, a nonsignificant
cant group differences. trend. In contrast, a simple ANOVA performed on
The results for the four questions dealing with a total scores (range 5 0–4) did yield a significant age
conscious control of one’s activities when asleep were trend, F(3, 68) 5 3.60, p , .02. Tukey tests revealed
similar, but with weaker age trends. Again, the 6- that the 10-year-olds had significantly, p , .05, higher
year-olds were not significantly above chance on any scores than the 6-year-olds, with none of the other
of the four questions, whereas the 8-year-olds were pairwise group comparisons being significant.
on the Act question, the 10-year-olds were on the As to justifications of correct responses, Table 3
Hear, Act, and Try questions, and the adults were on shows a marked increase with age in adequate justi-
all four questions. Summing across all four questions, fications for negative response to the Asleep ques-
the mean percentages correct were, from youngest to tion: x2(3, N 5 72) 5 25.08, p , .001. There was also a
oldest group, 61%, 67%, 82%, and 86%, with only the near-significant increase with age in adequate No-
two oldest groups’ percentages significantly, p , .05, tice response justifications, comprised mainly of a
above chance by t test. The number of participants in difference between the 6-year-olds and the three
each group answering at least 3 of the 4 control-of- older groups: x2(3, N 5 72) 5 7.54, p , .10. We also
activity questions correctly were 10, 11, 15, and 16 scored these two sets of adequate justifications for ex-
from youngest to oldest group, a near-significant age plicit mention of the words conscious, aware, and their
trend: x2(3, N 5 72) 5 7.20, p , .10. A simple ANOVA derivatives (e.g., unaware). The percentages of partic-
performed on total scores (range 5 0–4) also yielded ipants using any of these terms at least once in the
only a near-significant age trend, F(3, 68) 5 2.12, p , .11. two sets of justifications were, from youngest to old-
The age trends were less consistent from question est group, 0%, 11%, 11%, and 67%, significant at p ,
to question in the case of the four primary-conscious- .001 by Fisher exact test. In general, the adults tended
ness questions. Once again, the youngest children to refer in their justifications to the absence of think-
were not significantly above chance on any of the ing or consciousness in a sleeping person rather than
questions; in fact, they were significantly below to the absence of perception of external events,
chance on the See question, tending to say that they whereas the children did not show this tendency.
see black or dark gray rather than nothing when One might expect that participants’ responses to
sound asleep. The 8- and 10-year-olds were above the control-of-activity questions would be similar
chance only on the Notice question and the adults to their responses to the reflective-consciousness
were above chance only on the See question. The questions because the control-of-activity questions
adults’ relatively low percentages of negative an- also referred to conscious reflection on one’s own fu-
swers to the Hear and Notice questions clearly under- ture activities (e.g., “Can she think to herself ‘Hmm.
estimated their knowledge, however. Four correctly I’m going to start thinking about my toys now’?”).
pointed out that a sleeper would hear a sound if it This proved to be the case for each group except, for
were loud enough. Another adult said that whether unknown reasons, the 10-year-olds. The correlations
the sleeper could be said to hear “sort of depends on between participants’ responses to the five reflective-
what hear means”; yet another said that “somehow consciousness questions and the four control-of-
the sound is entering the ear”. On the See question, activity questions were .52, .73, 2.22, and .87, from
where there was no potentially compelling external the youngest to the oldest group. The corresponding
stimulus, most of them said that a sleeper would see correlations for the Think, Hear, and Act reflective-
nothing rather than black or dark gray. Their rela- consciousness and control questions above were .47,
tively low percentage on the Think question is less .85, .19, and .81. There were also associations between
easily explained. The different wording of the ques- responses to the initial primary-consciousness response
tion (“Could she be thinking . . . ?” here versus “Is and to the ensuing reflective-consciousness questions
she still thinking . . . ?” in Study 1) may have been in the Think and See tasks. In the Think task partici-
partly responsible. Summing across all four primary- pants were more likely to say that the girl does not
404 Child Development

know she is not thinking, given a previous assertion as an overall developmental increase in understand-
that she could not be thinking (84%), than to say that ing. To illustrate, one adult participant responded in-
she does not know she is thinking, given a previous correctly to all 10 of these questions. In contrast, one
assertion that she could be thinking (46%). The com- 6-year-old got them all right (the only 6-year-old to do
parable percentages in the See task were 77% and so) and also gave an adequate justification for her
39%. No such association was observed in the Hear negative answer to the Asleep question: “Because
task, however: not know responses were about equally your eyes are closed and your brain is shut down, be-
likely to follow either hear or not hear responses. cause you’re asleep.” It was clear from their answers
Some of our primary-consciousness questions were and answer justifications that at least some of the 8-
arguably less valid than our reflective-consciousness and 10-year-olds really did understand that the men-
and control questions as measures of a person’s un- tal processes specified in these questions are not oper-
derstanding of what can and cannot happen in a state ative in a deeply sleeping individual. Here are some
of dreamless sleep. Perhaps there could be thinking of the justifications that seemed to reflect genuine un-
on some unconscious level while in this state. Perhaps derstanding: “When you go to sleep you just cut off
there could also be some hearing and even noticing of everything . . . everything is cut off.” “It’s kind of hard
a low-level, nonconscious kind. Some of the adult to explain but when you are sleeping it’s kind of like
participants seemed to take this view of things, and in there’s no you, and no one is there . . . you are in your
retrospect it seems a reasonable one. Thus, it seems own world of darkness.” “It’s sort of like you are
quite plausible to think that a participant who has a knocked out.” “I know when I’m going to fall asleep
perfectly adequate layperson understanding of con- but not when I’m asleep.” “It is sort of like I am sort of
sciousness and unconsciousness might respond af- gone for a while.” In contrast, some of the other 8- and
firmatively to the Think, Hear, and Notice primary- 10-year-olds, together with most of the 6-year-olds,
consciousness questions—construing them, in effect, failed to demonstrate such understanding. At the
as questions about nonconscious rather than primary same time, there was no clear evidence that the major-
consciousness processes (see Study 4). On the other ity of the younger participants had a strong, positive
hand, it is hard to make a similar argument for affir- theory that unconscious people could and would def-
mative answers to the five reflective-consciousness initely have these mental states. For example, just as
questions, the four control-of-activity questions, and only one 6-year-old got all 10 questions right, so also
the See question. It strains credibility to argue that did only one get them all wrong. Rather, the distribu-
people who are sound asleep and not dreaming can be tion of correct answers over participants in this
consciously aware of what they are and are not doing youngest group was essentially flat, suggesting that
(reflective-consciousness questions), can consciously most 6-year-olds had no fixed convictions one way or
decide or try to do something (control-of-activity the other.
questions), and are seeing black or dark rather than
not seeing anything at all (See question). Accordingly,
STUDY 3
it seemed reasonable to take the sum of each partici-
pant’s correct (i.e., negative) answers to these 10 ques- The 5-year-olds in Study 1 and the 6-year-olds in
tions as an overall index of that participant’s under- Study 2 gave no evidence of knowing that conscious
standing of consciousness and unconsciousness. The mental activities are necessarily absent in a sleeping
mean percentages of these questions correctly an- person who is not dreaming. Nevertheless, it is pos-
swered were, from youngest to oldest group, 50%, sible that children of this age possess a useful devel-
69%, 75%, and 84%, with only the last three percent- opmental precursor of that knowledge, namely, the
ages significantly, p , .05, above chance by t test. The belief that a conscious person is at least more likely
numbers of participants in each group who answered than an unconscious one to be engaging in such ac-
at least 8 of these 10 questions correctly were 5, 10, 8, tivities. The purpose of Study 3 was to test this pos-
and 15, from youngest to oldest group, a significant sibility. In this study, an experimenter showed 6-
age increase, x2(3, N 5 72) 5 11.81, p , .01. The corre- year-old participants pictures of a child who was
sponding numbers answering at least 9 of the 10 cor- wide awake and a child who was in a deep, dream-
rectly were 3, 7, 6, and 13, x2(3, N 5 72) 5 12.18, p , less sleep, stated that one of the two was engaged in
.01. A simple ANOVA performed on participants’ to- a certain mental activity, and asked the participants
tal-questions-correct here (range 5 0–10) also yielded which child was doing that. The mental activities
a significant age effect: F(3, 68) 5 5.30, p , .002. tested for consisted of primary-consciousness type
It should also be noted that there were individual perceptions and thoughts (listening, smelling, won-
differences in understanding at each age level as well dering) and reflective-consciousness type self-
Flavell et al. 405

reflections (consciously thinking to oneself that one about her current state and were worded as follows:
likes something or feels a certain way). At the end of “Right now, which one of the girls is thinking to
the session the participants were queried further herself—‘Hey, I like lying here in bed/Hey, I’m start-
about three of their correct answers. That is, they ing to feel a little warm’?” The questions were pre-
were asked whether the sleeping child could also be sented in a random order with the exception that the
doing a mental activity they had just correctly attrib- snoring question always came second, the not-listening
uted to the waking child. We predicted that the partici- question fifth, and the not-wondering question eighth.
pants would perform well on the main questions, Three follow-up questions were presented in fixed
which merely tested their knowledge that a conscious order to conclude the testing session. The first was
person would be likelier than an unconscious one to be about wondering, the second about listening, and the
perceiving, thinking, and self-reflecting, but poorly on third about self-reflection. To illustrate, the wonder-
these follow-up questions, which tested their knowl- ing follow-up question was: “Remember you said
edge that an unconscious person would be, not just less that ____ was wondering about his little dog in the
likely to do these things, but actually unable to do them. backyard? Do you think that ____ (the other child)
could also be wondering about something while he is
sleeping?” (The “while he is sleeping” phrase was of
Method course added only if the participant had correctly
Participants nominated the waking child initially as the one who
was wondering.)
The participants were 20 first-graders, 12 girls and
8 boys (mean age in years and months 5 6,8, range 5
6,1 to 7,0). They were from primarily upper-middle- Results
class families, and were mostly Caucasian and Asian. The results confirmed both predictions. Consistent
The same female experimenter tested all participants. with the first prediction, the children performed quite
well on the eight initial mental-activity questions.
Percentages of children responding correctly to each
Procedure
question ranged from 70% for the lying-in-bed reflec-
The experimenter began by establishing that the tive-consciousness question to 100% for the listening
participants knew that people sometimes snore when question, with all the percentages except the former
they sleep (all but one child did) and by explaining being significantly (p , .05, binomial) higher than
that sometimes people dream when they are asleep would be expected by chance. They as readily picked
and sometimes they do not. She then showed them the sleeping child as the one not listening (95%) and
pictures of two children lying face up in bed, one with not wondering (85%) as they picked the waking child
eyes closed and one with eyes wide open; they were as the one listening (100%) and wondering (80%);
both portrayed as girls for female participants and as identifying the former as the snorer was also easy
boys for male participants. The experimenter said (95%). Of the 20 participants, 16 were correct on at
that the first child was sound asleep and not dream- least 6 of the 8 questions and 9 were correct on all 8.
ing and that the second was wide awake, and then Consistent with the second prediction, the group
verified that the participants knew which was which. did not perform better than would be expected by
Then she asked a series of nine questions of the form: chance on the three follow-up questions. Of the 16
“Right now, one of these girls (boys) is ____. Can you children who had initially said correctly that the wak-
show me which one is ____? There were six primary- ing child would be the one who was wondering, only
consciousness questions, two reflective-conscious- 8 went on to say correctly that the sleeping child could
ness questions, and one question about snoring. The not also be wondering. The corresponding figures for
primary-consciousness questions asked which child the listening question were 20 and 11, and for the
was listening to A, smelling B, not listening to C, won- reflective-consciousness question they were 14 and 7.
dering about D, wondering about E, and not wonder-
ing about F. For example: “Right now, one of these
STUDY 4
girls is not wondering what is for dinner. Which girl is
not wondering about dinner?” The snoring question In the previous three studies children were often
and the two negatively worded questions were in- quite willing to attribute various forms of conscious
cluded so that the sleeping child would occasionally cognition to a deeply sleeping, nondreaming person.
be the correct choice. The reflective-consciousness However, the sleeping person was always portrayed
questions concerned the child’s conscious reflections in a static drawing rather than appearing live. One
406 Child Development

purpose of the present study was to find out whether when he went to bed. He’s deep asleep right now.
children would be equally willing to attribute con- He’s not even dreaming (starts the tape and freeze-
scious thought to a real (videotaped) person who ap- frames it with a close-up of the boy’s face). So is he
peared to be sound asleep and was described as being deep asleep right now? (All participants said he was.)
so by the experimenter. It seemed possible that actu- That’s right, he’s sound asleep and not dreaming. I’ll
ally seeing a video of a real person looking thor- tell you what’s going to happen. His sister decides to
oughly comatose would inhibit such attributions. play a trick on him. She’s going to tickle his nose with
A second purpose of this study was to assess un- a big feather. His nose is going to wiggle but he won’t
derstanding of levels of consciousness. More specifi- wake up (starts tape again and stops it 2–3 s after the
cally, we wanted to find out how sensitive partici- tickle). His nose wiggled but he did not wake up. Let’s
pants of different ages would be to the distinction look at that film again. I’ll stop it here (scene showing
between a low level, essentially nonconscious detec- the tickling). Remember, when Mike was tickled his
tion of a stimulus event and a fully conscious aware- nose wiggled, but he didn’t wake up. So, did he wake
ness of it, an awareness that would permit a present up? (All participants said he did not.) That’s right, he
conscious thought about it and a later recollection of didn’t.” Thus, each participant had the experience of
its occurrence. giving a positive answer to one question and a nega-
Recall that in Study 2 some of the adult partici- tive answer to a second before the test questions were
pants alluded to the possibility of nonconscious cog- asked. The experimenter then asked the three test ques-
nition in their justifications. The data on the reflective- tions, always in the following order:
consciousness Hear question in that study also hinted Feel. “While his sister is tickling him and his nose
at an increase with age in sensitivity to this distinc- is wiggling, does he sort of feel the tickling?”
tion. Similarly, Flavell, Green, and Flavell (1995b) found Think. “While his sister is tickling him and his
that older children were more aware than younger nose is wiggling, is he thinking to himself ‘Hey, I think
ones that a stimulus could be seen but not attended to someone is tickling my nose right now’?”
or thought about (see also Pillow & Lovett, 1998). Remember. “When he wakes up in the morning
To address these questions, 5-year-olds, 8-year- will he remember that his nose was tickled?”
olds, and adults were shown a videotape of a young Half the participants in each group received the
teenager lying on a bed, apparently sound asleep. His task just described first and another, very similar task
sister mischievously tickles his nose with a feather, second; in this other task, a sleeping girl stirs without
causing his nose to twitch, but he does not wake up. awakening when her father lightly brushes her hair
The participants were then asked three questions: (1) away from her eyes. The remaining participants expe-
if the sleeper “sort of felt” the tickling, (2) if, when it rienced the two tasks in the opposite order. At the end
happened, he had the thought that “someone is tick- of whichever task they were given second, partici-
ling my nose right now”, and (3) if, when he wakes pants’ answers to each of that task’s three key ques-
up, he will remember that his nose had been tickled. tions were repeated and participants were asked why
they answered as they did, e.g., “Why won’t he re-
Method member that?”
The session concluded with a third task similar to
Participants the two main ones, except that the sleeping individ-
The participants were kindergartners, third graders, ual showed no response at all when lightly tickled
and adults, 10 of each sex in each group. The children (and the experimenter called attention to his lack of
were drawn from local elementary schools. The mean response) and only the Feel question plus its follow-
age in years and months of the younger children was up “Why” question were asked.
5,9 (range 5,2–6,5). The mean age of the older children
was 8,9 (range 8,1–9,5). The adults were college stu- Results
dents. The participants were mainly from upper-mid-
dle-class families, and were mostly Caucasian and The top three rows of Table 4 show the percentages
Asian. One experimenter tested all the participants. of correct answers in each age group to the Feel (“yes”
answers), Think (“no” answers), and Remember (“no”
answers) questions of the first two tasks, in which the
Procedure
sleeping child in the videotape stirred slightly in re-
The experimenter began by saying: “I am going to sponse to a touch but did not wake up. The bottom
show you a videotape of a boy named Mike and then row shows the percentages of “no” answers to the
I’ll ask you a few questions. Mike was very, very tired Feel questions of the third task, in which the sleeper
Flavell et al. 407

Table 4 Percentage of Correct Responses to Task Questions in ever, they usually denied that the person would re-
Study 4 member having been touched or tickled the next
Percentage of Correct Responses morning, when he or she woke up: 17 denied this on
both tasks and 2 denied it on one. Finally, as Table 4
Task Question 5-Year-Olds 8-Year-Olds Adults shows, all of the adults denied the sleeper both the
present thought and the later memory on both tasks.
Feel 78* 85* 95*
If we take fully correct performance on these two
Think 45 48 100*
Remember 53 90* 100* tasks to consist of affirmative answers to both Feel
Feel—no movement 60 20* 40 questions and negative answers to both Think and
both Remember questions, then the numbers of 5-
Note: Percentages significantly, p , .02, different from chance ex- year-olds, 8-year-olds, and adults who were fully cor-
pectation of 50% by t test are marked with an asterisk. Percentages rect were 2, 5, and 19, respectively, x2(2, N 5 60) 5
of affirmative answers are entered in the bottom row, not because
they are regarded as correct but in order to facilitate comparison
33.53, p , .001. Five 5-year-olds and one 8-year-old
with the affirmative (correct) answers presented in the top row. said yes in response to all six questions, and three 5-
year-olds, one 8-year-old, and one adult answered no
to all of them; all of the other participants answered
yes to some questions and no to others.
showed no reaction at all to the touch; unlike the case A category system was devised to analyze partici-
with the previous three questions, no claim is made pants’ justifications of their answers to the Feel,
that a negative answer to this question is clearly right Think, Remember, and Feel—no movement ques-
and a positive one clearly wrong. An age (5-year-olds tions. Two judges scored each justification. Interjudge
versus 8-year-olds versus adults) 3 question (Feel agreement ranged from 85% for the Remember ques-
versus Think versus Remember) mixed ANOVA was tions to 97% for the Feel questions; disagreements
performed on the responses given in the first two were subsequently resolved by discussion. Consis-
tasks. Task and task order were not included in this tent with the data in the top and bottom rows of Table
analysis because it was evident from inspection that 4, the older participants, especially, were apt to justify
these variables had no significant effects on participants’ their answers to the questions about feeling by citing
responses. Significant main effects were found for age, the sleeper’s physical response (Feel questions) or
F(2, 57) 5 28.84, p , .001, and for question, F(2, 114) 5 lack of response (Feel—no movement).
6.22, p , .001; the interaction between age and ques- The category system also allowed us to code for
tion was also significant, F(4, 114) 5 3.64, p , .01. possible indications of some understanding of con-
These data show a clear pattern of developmental sciousness, unconsciousness, or levels of conscious-
changes. Participants in all three age groups tended to ness. We used both a liberal and a conservative crite-
say that the person on the videotape did “sort of feel” rion here. In the liberal scoring, a justification was
the touch when he or she stirred in response (Feel counted if it even hinted at some possible under-
questions). The older participants, particularly, were standing. An example is this 5-year-old’s justification
much less likely to draw this conclusion when, in the of a negative answer to the Think question: “No, she
third task, the person did not show any response to doesn’t know it.” To be counted in the more conserva-
the touch (Feel—no movement questions). This sug- tive scoring, a justification had to be more explicit or
gests that the movement was taken by many as a to make a generalization of some kind regarding con-
strong cue; participants’ justification of their answers sciousness or the lack thereof. For instance, this justi-
also confirmed this conclusion, as will be shown. In fication for a negative Think answer by an 8-year-old
contrast, the three groups responded differently to was counted in this subcategory: “No, because she’s
the Think and Remember questions. Only 7 of the 20 asleep and when you are asleep you don’t really think
5-year-olds correctly denied on both tasks that the anything because your mind sort of shuts off.” Six 5-
sleeping person was having the very conscious- year-olds, 11 8-year-olds, and 20 adults gave at least
sounding, verbalized thought that he or she was one justification that met the liberal criterion, x2(2, N 5
being tickled, and only four more denied it on one of 60) 5 21.30, p , .001. The corresponding figures for
the two tasks. Similarly, the corresponding figures in the conservative criterion were 0, 8, and 19, x2(2, N 5
this group for the Remember question were eight 60) 5 36.77, p , .001.
(two denials) and five (one denial). The 8-year-olds re- Of the 19 adults meeting this more conservative
sponded to the Think questions much as the 5-year- criterion, 17 gave clear evidence of drawing a distinc-
olds did: eight responded correctly on both tasks and tion between lower and higher levels of conscious-
three did so on one task. Unlike the 5-year-olds, how- ness or attention. Here are some examples: “She feels
408 Child Development

it and responds to it although she may not cognitively former insight at an earlier age than they would ac-
feel it—‘consciously’ is the word I was looking for.” quire the latter.
“He must feel it because he reacted . . . I don’t think
his brain is working to that level to where he can say
DISCUSSION
‘Oh, wow, I must be being tickled’ because if he was
he’d be aware that he’s being tickled and then he Four studies investigated the development of an un-
wouldn’t be asleep.” “Maybe at a subconscious level derstanding of what it is like, mentally, to be in a com-
but not at a conscious level.” “At some level he had monly occurring nonconscious state—namely, in a
to feel it.” “He senses something—maybe uncon- state of deep, dreamless sleep. In studies 1 and 2, chil-
sciously.” “Because I think she feels it on a subcon- dren of ages 5, 6, 7, 8, and 10, and adults were asked
scious level, but not on a conscious level because she questions about whether people in this state could or
is asleep.” “I don’t know if you mean feeling it and would, (1) see, hear, listen, notice, think, wish, pre-
being conscious of the fact that he’s feeling it.” In ad- tend, or feel things (primary consciousness), (2) know
dition, many of the adults used the words conscious, that they are asleep or know that they are or are not
unconscious, subconscious, and aware when explaining perceiving, thinking, feeling, or moving (reflective
their answers, whereas no child participant ever used consciousness), and (3) deliberately decide or try to
any of these terms. Recall that this same developmen- perform mental or physical actions (control-of activity).
tal trend was observed in studies 1 and 2. These studies showed an increase with age in the ten-
This study showed that many children are indeed dency to say that these instances of reflective con-
willing to attribute conscious-sounding thoughts to sciousness, control-of activity, and (less consistently)
an unconscious person even when the person is shown primary consciousness would not be present in a de-
“live” (via videotape) rather than in a drawing, clearly picted person who was sound asleep and not dream-
looks and acts asleep, and is repeatedly described by ing. Study 3 tested for a more elementary, perhaps
the experimenter as being in and remaining in that precursory understanding in 6-year-olds, namely,
state. This was true of the 8-year-olds as well as the 5- that a conscious person is at least more likely than an
year-olds. One could not argue, in their case, that they unconscious, nondreaming one to be engaging in
were just carelessly saying “yes” to any mental state mental activities. The 6-year-olds did show this un-
attribution question, because they usually said “no” derstanding. However, as in studies 1 and 2, they
to the memory questions. We suspect that the 8-year- were also often willing to say that the unconscious
olds, at least, might have been somewhat less inclined person, although less than likely than the conscious
to make the thought attribution if the person had not one to be engaging in these activities, could be doing
just stirred in response to the touch suggesting that he so. In Study 4, we assessed the willingness of 5-year-
or she had “sort of felt” it. It should be noted, how- olds, 8-year-olds, and adults to attribute verbalized,
ever, that the adults also thought that the person “sort conscious-sounding thoughts to a “live” (videotaped)
of felt” it, but never concluded from this that the per- sleeper rather than, as in studies 1–3, a still picture of
son was having a conscious thought about it. Recall one. More than half of the participants in each of the
also that the 8-year-old in studies 1 and 2 were like- two child groups made this attribution on at least one
wise more willing than the adults to make mental trial, whereas no adult participant ever did. The
state attributions to sleeping, nondreaming individu- adults in this study also showed a much better under-
als, although less so than the 5- and 6-year-olds. What standing of levels of consciousness than the children
many of the 5- and 8-year-olds in the present study did. That is, when they saw the sleeping individual in
seem to have failed to do was to distinguish between the videotape stir but not wake up in response to a
two markedly different levels of awareness or atten- light touch, they not only concluded that the individ-
tion: a low-level, subconscious sensing of a tactile ual did “sort of feel” the touch but would not think
stimulus and a fully conscious awareness of its pres- about it, they also often justified this conclusion by
ence and its identity. saying that the feeling was at a subconscious rather
Finally, the developmental lag found between de- than a conscious level.
nial of memory (8-year-olds) and denial of thought Although the developmental changes observed in
(adults) seems plausible to us: People have more fre- these studies appeared to be more or less gradual and
quent and more direct evidence that they cannot there was individual variation within each age group,
later recall events that happened while they were there were notable differences between the typical
asleep than that they had no conscious thoughts performance of the two youngest child groups (5- and
about them at the time they occurred. Consequently, 6-year-olds), the three older child groups ( 7-, 8-, and 10-
it makes sense that children would acquire the year-olds) and the adults. With the sole exception of
Flavell et al. 409

the See questions in Study 1 and the Feel question in many simpler and more straightforward questions
Study 4—both very easy questions—the 5- and 6- they were asked (e.g., “Is she still thinking about the
year-olds did not respond significantly more accu- fire station?”). As mentioned in the introduction, re-
rately than would be expected by chance to any of the cent studies have shown that young children tend to
primary-conscious, reflective-consciousness, or control- underestimate the amount of mental activity that does
of-activity questions in studies 1, 2, and 4 (see Tables go on in a conscious mind (Flavell et al., 1993, 1995a,
1, 3, and 4). In Study 1 the youngest participants (5- 1997); for example, they are largely unaware of the
year-olds) averaged only a nonsignificant 56% correct stream of consciousness, in themselves as well as in
to the 10 key questions asked in that study. In Study 3, others. In contrast, the present studies strongly sug-
only about half of the 6-year-olds responded to the gest that they also tend to overestimate the amount of
follow-up questions by denying that the sleeping (nondreaming) ideation that can go on in an uncon-
child could be experiencing various primary- and re- scious mind.
flective-consciousness mental states. In Study 4, like- It is of course possible that children of this age re-
wise, only a minority of the 5-year-olds consistently ally know more about consciousness and uncon-
said that the sleeper would not be aware of being sciousness than these studies have revealed, and that
touched and would not remember having been other, more sensitive testing methods would bring
touched later, after awakening. In each of the first two this knowledge to light. The finding in Study 3 that
studies only 39% of the youngest group said that a they are already more disposed to attribute mental
person who is sound asleep and not dreaming would states to a waking person than to a sleeping one when
not know that he or she is asleep. In Study 2 only 22% obliged to choose between the two is consistent with
of the 6-year-olds said that they would see nothing at these possibilities. On the other hand, it was striking
all while in a dreamless sleep; the rest said that they to see how little knowledge of consciousness and un-
would see black or dark gray, the alternative possibil- consciousness they displayed in all four studies, de-
ity offered to them. spite numerous opportunities to do so. Our belief,
In Study 1 an earlier waking state in which a char- then, is that although young children might know
acter was engaged in a number of mental activities more about these matters than we have shown, they
was contrasted with a subsequent sleeping state, as in probably do not know much more.
this example: “All morning Lee has been wishing she The 7-, 8-, and 10-year-old children clearly knew
had some ginger ale.” Right now she is asleep and not more about unconsciousness than the 5- and 6-year-
dreaming. Is she still wishing she had some ginger olds. Their overall averages of correct responses in
ale?” It would not have been surprising if most of the studies 1 and 2 ranged from 69% to 76%, with all of
young children had answered “no” to all such ques- these averages being significantly higher than chance
tions, assuming that a change from a positive to a expectation. Most comparisons showed that these
negative condition would imply a change from activ- older children performed significantly better than
ity to no activity. That is, they could have answered the younger ones and not significantly worse than the
correctly without understanding anything at all about adults. A glance at the asterisked entries in Tables 1–
consciousness or unconsciousness just by going with 3 shows that they answered about one-third of the in-
the apparent demand characteristics of the task. This dividual questions significantly more correctly than
clearly did not happen, however. Instead, they consis- would be expected by chance. A number of them also
tently denied the sleeping story character only the justified their correct answers in ways that left no
mental activity they could plainly see that he or she doubt as to their understanding, something that al-
was not engaging in—namely, seeing a picture (the most never happened in the two youngest groups. In
character was depicted with his or her eyes closed). In Study 4 also, almost all of the 8-year-olds realized that
Study 4, similarly, seeing a real person in the video- the sleeper would not remember the touching inci-
tape looking dead to the world might have led the 5- dent after awakening, whereas the 5-year-olds were
year-olds to assume that such a person must not be at chance on this question. At the same time, they did
having any thoughts, let alone verbalized, conscious- fail to perform better than would be expected by
sounding ones. But this clearly did not happen either. chance on a number of questions in Studies 1, 2, and 4,
It is true that some of the reflective-consciousness and also often failed to justify adequately the correct
questions in Study 2 could have been difficult for chil- answers they did give. Furthermore, in Studies 2 and
dren of this age to process simply because of their 4 the adults often made explicit mention of conscious-
complexity (e.g., “Does she know she is not thinking ness in their justifications, using words like conscious,
about anything?”). However, Tables 1, 3, and 4 show aware, and unconscious, whereas the older children
that they did not respond any more correctly to the rarely did (and the younger children never did). Also,
410 Child Development

as previously mentioned, the adults in Study 2 despite this fact, the only mental events they are ever
tended to focus on the absence of thinking or con- able to remember from recent periods of sleep are
sciousness more than on the absence of perception of dreams. From these two observations they might then
external stimuli, whereas the older children talked infer that the reason they do not also recall having
about both equally often. This suggests the hypoth- had perceptions and thoughts during these periods is
esis—only a hypothesis, given present evidence—that that conscious perceptions and thoughts simply do
children may begin by conceiving of unconsciousness not occur when one is asleep. The 8-year-olds in
mainly as a state in which conscious perception of Study 4 may have been almost, but not quite, ready to
current external happenings does not occur, and only draw this conclusion: Like the 5-year-olds, they did
later as a state in which nonperceptual or internal- not yet consistently deny thoughts about the touch-
perceptual activities like thinking, feeling, and reflec- ing incident, but unlike the younger children, they
tive consciousness are also absent. In sum, our data did consistently deny later recall of the incident.
suggest that there is considerable development in this It may not be surprising, then, that children still
area during middle childhood but that development seem to be acquiring intuitions in this area during the
also continues after this period. late elementary school years. On the one hand, this is
As to the adults, with the exception mainly of some the period in which they are becoming increasingly
participants in Study 2, we found that the college stu- aware of their own memory capacities and limitations
dents in the pilot study and in Studies 1, 2, and 4 (Schneider & Borkowski, 1998)—when they could
largely agreed with our own naive theory that a begin to sense what they should and should not be
nondreaming sleeper would retain the capacity for able to remember. On the other hand, it is also the pe-
nonconscious responding but would mostly or wholly riod in which introspective skills are improving and
lack primary consciousness, and would totally lack in which they are learning what waking mental life is
reflective consciousness and the ability to control like—for example, that it contains a stream of con-
mental and physical activities deliberately. There sciousness, that it involves self-awareness, etc. (Flavell
might have been even more agreement among adult et al., 1993, 1995a), and that stimuli can be perceived
participants if our questions had been about a person but not consciously attended to (Flavell et al., 1995b).
who is in a more extreme and unambiguous state of As they become more aware of the mental events that
consciousness, such as being knocked out or in a coma. go on in people’s minds when people are conscious,
(What young children would have made of such they become better able to infer that there exist non-
questions is uncertain, given their presumably lesser conscious periods in which these mental events do
familiarity with nonsleep states of consciousness.) At not go on. It may be logically possible to form some
the same time, we can imagine areas of disagreements concept of unconsciousness without much under-
even among adults concerning such subjective and standing of consciousness; for example, a person
hard-to-verify matters. A recent review (Lillard, 1998) could conceivably come to the view that nothing
has suggested that adult theories of mind may differ much happens inside an unconscious mind without
considerably from culture to culture. It would there- having any clear idea of what happens inside a con-
fore be of interest to know if there is significant inter- scious one. Nevertheless, it seems highly probable to
cultural (or even intracultural) variation in adults’ us that a developing concept of consciousness does
naive theories about consciousness, unconsciousness, help engender a concept of unconsciousness in chil-
and levels of consciousness and attention. dren. The opposite may also be true. That is, a grow-
How might children acquire the adult intuition (in ing appreciation of all that is absent in unconscious
our culture, at least) that little or no nondreaming states may also help children appreciate all that is
mentation goes on in a sleeping person? They might present in conscious ones. Thus, the developmental
learn something about it from parents, the media, or process here may be the familiar one of reciprocal me-
other outside sources, of course. For example, their diation or bi-directional facilitation, with a growing
parents may tell them that they did not know about understanding of consciousness mediating or facili-
some event that happened the night before because tating a growing understanding of unconsciousness
they were asleep at the time. Similarly, they can see and the reverse.
that other people are perceptually and intellectually There may be an additional, related reason why
unresponsive while they are sleeping. However, it the children in these studies were so much more will-
should also be possible for them to infer or consoli- ing to attribute conscious mental states to an uncon-
date this belief on their own, once they are cognitively scious person than the adults were. Consider what
mature enough to notice two things: First, their mem- goes on psychologically when a conscious mental
ory for most recent happenings is quite good; second, state occurs as, for example, when one thinks about
Flavell et al. 411

one’s dog or sees it bounding towards one. On the riences that help define what it is like to be them.
one hand, there is the content or referent of the mental Moreover, what it is like for me to have a given men-
states: one thinks about or sees the dog. At the same tal content may be different from what it is like for
time, there is also the thinking or seeing experience it- you to have even that very same content, and of
self: we think about or see the dog. A conscious mental course we are also likely to differ considerably in
event not only has content, it also comprises a men- what contents we have. This is part of the reason we
tal experience. As philosophers of mind are fond of tend to assume that each person is psychologically
describing it, there is “something it is like”, subjec- unique in some respects, possessing a personality and
tively, for a person to have a conscious thought or per- sense of self not wholly like that of any other individ-
cept. In contrast, there is presumably “nothing it is ual. Insights such as these, born of the various theory-
like,” experientially, for a computer to do a compu- of-mind acquisitions described in this article, help us
tation—or, for that matter, for a person to have a understand what it is to be a human being.
thought or percept that does not become conscious.
We speculate that children are less aware than
adults of the experiential, what-it-is-like-to-have-them ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
aspects of conscious mental states such as thoughts This research was supported by National Institute of
and percepts, and instead focus almost exclusively on Mental Health Grant 40687. We are grateful to the
their cognitive content. (This is probably less true in children, teachers and parents of Bing School of Stan-
the case of mental states whose subjective, experien- ford, Foothill Junior College, Los Altos Hills, Sum-
tial aspects are very salient, such as strong desires mer Program for Children, and Keys, Duveneck, El
and emotions.) Of course adults also usually “see Camelo, and Escondido Elementary Schools of Palo
through” the experience of having a mental event and Alto, California whose cooperation made this inves-
attend only or primarily to the event’s content or ref- tigation possible.
erent; this is the normal, adaptive thing for everyone
to do most of the time. The speculation here is only
that mental states are even more, and more often, ADDRESSES AND AFFILIATIONS
transparent in this respect for children than they are
for adults. If this speculation is correct, it might partly Corresponding author: John H. Flavell, Department
explain the developmental trends found in the of Psychology, Building 420, Stanford University,
present studies. When considering whether a person Stanford, California 94305-2130; e-mail: flavell@psych.
might be having a conscious mental state (primary or stanford.edu. Frances Green and Eleanor Flavell are
reflective) right now, children would be less likely also at Stanford University.
than adults to ask themselves whether that particular
individual could be having it—could, by virtue of be-
ing conscious at that moment and therefore capable REFERENCES
of experiencing it. If it were true that children tend to
Astington, J. W. (1993). The child’s discovery of the mind. Cam-
be ignorant of, or tend to ignore, the experiential as-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
pect of conscious mental states, then they would have Bartsch, K., & Wellman, H. M. (1995). Children talk about the
no more reason to deny them to an unconscious per- mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
son than to a conscious one.1 Farthing, G. W. (1992). The psychology of consciousness. Engle-
Becoming more aware of the conscious-uncon- wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
scious dimension of mental states may make possible Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L., & Flavell, E. R. (1993). Children’s
additional insights. Here are a few: People can have, understanding of the stream of consciousness. Child De-
and be influenced by, thoughts, perceptions, desires, velopment, 64, 387–398.
emotions, and other mental states that they are not Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L., & Flavell, E. R. (1995a). Young chil-
aware of having; that is, mental states can be noncon- dren’s knowledge about thinking. Monographs of the Soci-
ety for Research in Child Development, 60 (1, Serial No. 243).
scious or semiconscious as well as conscious, and
Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L., & Flavell, E. R. (1995b). The devel-
may affect our behavior even when they are not con-
opment of children’s knowledge about attentional focus.
scious. People are continually having conscious expe- Developmental Psychology, 31, 706–712.
1 The authors are grateful to David Rosenthal for suggesting Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L.,Flavell, E. R., & Grossman, J. B.
the line of thinking expressed in this and the preceding para- (1997). The development of children’s knowledge about
graph. He is of course not responsible for any shortcomings inner speech. Child Development, 68, 39–47.
our speculations may have as a developmental-psychological Flavell, J. H., Green, F. L., & Flavell, E. R. (1998). The mind
explanation. has a mind of its own: Developing knowledge about
412 Child Development

mental uncontrollability. Cognitive Development, 13, 127– dren’s use of cognitive explanations for another person’s
138. mistakes. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 44, 378–403.
Flavell, J. H., & Miller, P. H. (1998). Social cognition. In D. Rosenthal, D. M. (1993). State consciousness and transitive
Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), W. Damon (Series Ed.), consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 2, 355–363.
Handbook of child psychology:Vol. 2. Cognition, percep- Schneider, W., & Borkowski, D. F. (1998). Memory. In D.
tion, and language, 5th ed. (pp. 851 – 898). New York: Kuhn & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), W. Damon (Series Ed.),
Wiley. Handbook of child psychology Vol. 2. Cognition, perception,
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology (Vol. 1). New and language, 5th ed.: (pp. 467 – 521). New York: Wiley.
York: Henry Holt. Taylor, M. (1996). Social cognitive development from a
Kemp, S., & Strongman, K. T. (1994). Consciousness—a folk theory of mind perspective. In R. Gelman & T. Au
view. New Zealand Journal of Psychology, 23, 42–47. (Eds.), E. C. Carterette & M. P. Friedman (Series Eds.),
Lewis, C., & Mitchell, P. (Eds.). (1994). Children’s early under- Handbook of perception and cognition: Vol. 13. Perceptual
standing of mind: Origins and development. Hillsdale, NJ: and cognitive development (pp. 283 – 329). New York: Aca-
Erlbaum. demic Press.
Lillard, A. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in Wellman, H. M., & Gelman, S. A. (1992). Cognitive develop-
theories of mind. Psychological Bulletin, 123, 3–32. ment: Foundational theories of core domains. In M. R.
Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Rosenzweig & L. W. Porter (Eds.), Annual review of psy-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. chology (Vol. 43), pp. 337–375). Palo Alto, CA: Annual
Pillow, B. H., & Lovett, S. B. (1998). “He forgot”: Young chil- Reviews, Inc.

You might also like