You are on page 1of 42

A Concrete Introduction to Real

Analysis, Second Edition Robert


Carlson
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/a-concrete-introduction-to-real-analysis-second-editio
n-robert-carlson/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

An Introduction to Real Analysis First Edition Agarwal

https://textbookfull.com/product/an-introduction-to-real-
analysis-first-edition-agarwal/

Introduction to Real Analysis 1st Edition Christopher


Heil

https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-real-
analysis-1st-edition-christopher-heil/

Spaces An Introduction to Real Analysis Tom Lindstrøm

https://textbookfull.com/product/spaces-an-introduction-to-real-
analysis-tom-lindstrom/

Introduction to Politics Second Canadian Edition Robert


Garner

https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-politics-second-
canadian-edition-robert-garner/
An Introduction to Classical Real Analysis Karl R.
Stromberg

https://textbookfull.com/product/an-introduction-to-classical-
real-analysis-karl-r-stromberg/

Biota Grow 2C gather 2C cook Loucas

https://textbookfull.com/product/biota-grow-2c-gather-2c-cook-
loucas/

Biological Inorganic Chemistry Second Edition A New


Introduction to Molecular Structure and Function Robert
Crichton

https://textbookfull.com/product/biological-inorganic-chemistry-
second-edition-a-new-introduction-to-molecular-structure-and-
function-robert-crichton/

Reinforced Concrete Structures Analysis and Design (2nd


Edition) David A Fanella

https://textbookfull.com/product/reinforced-concrete-structures-
analysis-and-design-2nd-edition-david-a-fanella/

Introduction to Sustainability 1st Edition Robert


Brinkmann

https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-
sustainability-1st-edition-robert-brinkmann/
A Concrete Introduction
to Real Analysis
Second Edition
TEXTBOOKS in MATHEMATICS
Series Editors: Al Boggess and Ken Rosen

PUBLISHED TITLES
ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: A GENTLE INTRODUCTION
Gary L. Mullen and James A. Sellers
ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: AN INTERACTIVE APPROACH, SECOND EDITION
William Paulsen
ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: AN INQUIRY-BASED APPROACH
Jonathan K. Hodge, Steven Schlicker, and Ted Sundstrom
ADVANCED LINEAR ALGEBRA
Hugo Woerdeman
ADVANCED LINEAR ALGEBRA
Nicholas Loehr
ADVANCED LINEAR ALGEBRA, SECOND EDITION
Bruce Cooperstein
APPLIED ABSTRACT ALGEBRA WITH MAPLE™ AND MATLAB®, THIRD EDITION
Richard Klima, Neil Sigmon, and Ernest Stitzinger
APPLIED DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS: THE PRIMARY COURSE
Vladimir Dobrushkin
APPLIED DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS WITH BOUNDARY VALUE PROBLEMS
Vladimir Dobrushkin
APPLIED FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS, THIRD EDITION
J. Tinsley Oden and Leszek Demkowicz
A BRIDGE TO HIGHER MATHEMATICS
Valentin Deaconu and Donald C. Pfaff
COMPUTATIONAL MATHEMATICS: MODELS, METHODS, AND ANALYSIS WITH MATLAB® AND MPI,
SECOND EDITION
Robert E. White
A COURSE IN DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS WITH BOUNDARY VALUE PROBLEMS, SECOND EDITION
Stephen A. Wirkus, Randall J. Swift, and Ryan Szypowski
A COURSE IN ORDINARY DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS, SECOND EDITION
Stephen A. Wirkus and Randall J. Swift
DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS: THEORY, TECHNIQUE, AND PRACTICE, SECOND EDITION
Steven G. Krantz
PUBLISHED TITLES CONTINUED

DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS: THEORY, TECHNIQUE, AND PRACTICE WITH BOUNDARY VALUE PROBLEMS
Steven G. Krantz
DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS WITH APPLICATIONS AND HISTORICAL NOTES, THIRD EDITION
George F. Simmons
DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS WITH MATLAB®: EXPLORATION, APPLICATIONS, AND THEORY
Mark A. McKibben and Micah D. Webster
DISCOVERING GROUP THEORY: A TRANSITION TO ADVANCED MATHEMATICS
Tony Barnard and Hugh Neill
DISCRETE MATHEMATICS, SECOND EDITION
Kevin Ferland
ELEMENTARY DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS
Kenneth Kuttler
ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY
James S. Kraft and Lawrence C. Washington
THE ELEMENTS OF ADVANCED MATHEMATICS: FOURTH EDITION
Steven G. Krantz
ESSENTIALS OF MATHEMATICAL THINKING
Steven G. Krantz
EXPLORING CALCULUS: LABS AND PROJECTS WITH MATHEMATICA®
Crista Arangala and Karen A. Yokley
EXPLORING GEOMETRY, SECOND EDITION
Michael Hvidsten
EXPLORING LINEAR ALGEBRA: LABS AND PROJECTS WITH MATHEMATICA®
Crista Arangala
EXPLORING THE INFINITE: AN INTRODUCTION TO PROOF AND ANALYSIS
Jennifer Brooks
GRAPHS & DIGRAPHS, SIXTH EDITION
Gary Chartrand, Linda Lesniak, and Ping Zhang
INTRODUCTION TO ABSTRACT ALGEBRA, SECOND EDITION
Jonathan D. H. Smith
INTRODUCTION TO ANALYSIS
Corey M. Dunn
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL PROOFS: A TRANSITION TO ADVANCED MATHEMATICS, SECOND EDITION
Charles E. Roberts, Jr.
PUBLISHED TITLES CONTINUED

INTRODUCTION TO NUMBER THEORY, SECOND EDITION


Marty Erickson, Anthony Vazzana, and David Garth
INVITATION TO LINEAR ALGEBRA
David C. Mello
LINEAR ALGEBRA, GEOMETRY AND TRANSFORMATION
Bruce Solomon
MATHEMATICAL MODELLING WITH CASE STUDIES: USING MAPLE™ AND MATLAB®, THIRD EDITION
B. Barnes and G. R. Fulford
MATHEMATICS IN GAMES, SPORTS, AND GAMBLING–THE GAMES PEOPLE PLAY, SECOND EDITION
Ronald J. Gould
THE MATHEMATICS OF GAMES: AN INTRODUCTION TO PROBABILITY
David G. Taylor
A MATLAB® COMPANION TO COMPLEX VARIABLES
A. David Wunsch
MEASURE AND INTEGRAL: AN INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYSIS, SECOND EDITION
Richard L. Wheeden
MEASURE THEORY AND FINE PROPERTIES OF FUNCTIONS, REVISED EDITION
Lawrence C. Evans and Ronald F. Gariepy
NUMERICAL ANALYSIS FOR ENGINEERS: METHODS AND APPLICATIONS, SECOND EDITION
Bilal Ayyub and Richard H. McCuen
ORDINARY DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE FUNDAMENTALS
Kenneth B. Howell
PRINCIPLES OF FOURIER ANALYSIS, SECOND EDITION
Kenneth B. Howell
REAL ANALYSIS AND FOUNDATIONS, FOURTH EDITION
Steven G. Krantz
RISK ANALYSIS IN ENGINEERING AND ECONOMICS, SECOND EDITION
Bilal M. Ayyub
SPORTS MATH: AN INTRODUCTORY COURSE IN THE MATHEMATICS OF SPORTS SCIENCE AND
SPORTS ANALYTICS
Roland B. Minton
A TOUR THROUGH GRAPH THEORY
Karin R. Saoub
PUBLISHED TITLES CONTINUED

TRANSITION TO ANALYSIS WITH PROOF


Steven G. Krantz
TRANSFORMATIONAL PLANE GEOMETRY
Ronald N. Umble and Zhigang Han
TEXTBOOKS in MATHEMATICS

A Concrete Introduction
to Real Analysis
Second Edition

Robert Carlson
CRC Press
Taylor & Francis Group
6000 Broken Sound Parkway NW, Suite 300
Boca Raton, FL 33487-2742
© 2018 by Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
CRC Press is an imprint of Taylor & Francis Group, an Informa business

No claim to original U.S. Government works

Printed on acid-free paper


Version Date: 20171023

International Standard Book Number-13: 978-1-498-77813-8 (Hardback)

This book contains information obtained from authentic and highly regarded sources. Reasonable
efforts have been made to publish reliable data and information, but the author and publisher cannot
assume responsibility for the validity of all materials or the consequences of their use. The authors and
publishers have attempted to trace the copyright holders of all material reproduced in this publication
and apologize to copyright holders if permission to publish in this form has not been obtained. If any
copyright material has not been acknowledged please write and let us know so we may rectify in any
future reprint.

Except as permitted under U.S. Copyright Law, no part of this book may be reprinted, reproduced,
transmitted, or utilized in any form by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or
hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without written permission from the publishers.

For permission to photocopy or use material electronically from this work, please access
www.copyright.com (http://www.copyright.com/) or contact the Copyright Clearance Center, Inc.
(CCC), 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, 978-750-8400. CCC is a not-for-profit organization
that provides licenses and registration for a variety of users. For organizations that have been granted
a photocopy license by the CCC, a separate system of payment has been arranged.

Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and
are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.
Visit the Taylor & Francis Web site at
http://www.taylorandfrancis.com
and the CRC Press Web site at
http://www.crcpress.com
Contents

List of Figures xiii

Preface xv

1 Real numbers and mathematical proofs 1


1.1 Real number axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
1.1.1 Field axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
1.1.2 Order axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
1.2 Proofs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9
1.2.1 Proof by induction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10
1.2.2 Irrational real numbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14
1.2.3 Propositional logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
1.2.3.1 Truth tables . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16
1.2.3.2 Valid consequences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18
1.2.4 Rules of inference . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
1.2.5 Predicates and quantifiers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
1.3 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

2 Infinite sequences 29
2.1 Limits of infinite sequences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
2.1.1 Basic ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
2.1.2 Properties of limits . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34
2.2 Completeness axioms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
2.3 Subsequences and compact intervals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
2.4 Cauchy sequences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
2.5 Continued fractions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
2.6 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53

3 Infinite series 57
3.1 Basics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
3.2 Positive series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
3.3 General series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
3.3.1 Absolute convergence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63
3.3.2 Alternating series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64
3.4 Power series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66
3.5 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69

ix
x Contents

4 More sums 73
4.1 Grouping and rearrangement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73
4.2 A calculus of sums and differences . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
4.3 Computing the sums of powers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 85
4.4 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90

5 Functions 93
5.1 Basics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94
5.2 Limits and continuity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
5.2.1 Limits . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
5.2.1.1 Limit as x → ∞ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
5.2.1.2 Limit as x → x0 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97
5.2.1.3 Limit rules . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
5.2.2 Continuity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101
5.2.2.1 Rootfinding 1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104
5.2.3 Uniform continuity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105
5.3 Derivatives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108
5.3.1 Computation of derivatives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109
5.3.2 The Mean Value Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 114
5.3.3 Contractions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
5.3.3.1 Rootfinding 2: Newton’s Method . . . . . . . 119
5.3.4 Convexity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120
5.4 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124

6 Integrals 131
6.1 Areas under power function graphs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 134
6.2 Integrable functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139
6.3 Properties of integrals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147
6.4 Arc length and trigonometric functions . . . . . . . . . . . . 152
6.5 Improper integrals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154
6.5.1 Integration of positive functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . 156
6.5.2 Integrals and sums . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 160
6.5.3 Absolutely convergent integrals . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161
6.5.4 Conditionally convergent integrals . . . . . . . . . . . 162
6.6 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165

7 The Natural logarithm 171


7.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171
7.2 The natural exponential function . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175
7.3 Infinite products . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 178
7.4 Stirling’s formula . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 182
7.5 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 189
Contents xi

8 Taylor polynomials and series 193


8.1 Taylor polynomials . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195
8.2 Taylor’s Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200
8.3 The remainder . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 203
8.3.1 Calculating e . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 205
8.3.2 Calculating π . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 206
8.4 Additional results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207
8.4.1 Taylor series by algebraic manipulations . . . . . . . . 207
8.4.2 The binomial series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209
8.5 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213

9 Uniform convergence 217


9.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217
9.2 Uniform Convergence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 219
9.3 Convergence of power series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224
9.4 The Weierstrass Approximation Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . 226
9.5 Trigonometric approximation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
9.5.1 Solving a heat equation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
9.5.2 Approximation by trigonometric functions . . . . . . . 230
9.5.3 Fourier series . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 234
9.6 Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239

A Solutions to odd numbered problems 243


A.1 Chapter 1 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243
A.2 Chapter 2 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 250
A.3 Chapter 3 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 254
A.4 Chapter 4 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 259
A.5 Chapter 5 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 264
A.6 Chapter 6 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273
A.7 Chapter 7 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279
A.8 Chapter 8 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
A.9 Chapter 9 Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 286

Bibliography 293

Index 295
List of Figures

2.1 Graphical representation of a convergent sequence. . . . . . . 32


2.2 A bounded monotone sequence. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
2.3 Nested intervals. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
2.4 Constructing a convergent subsequence. . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
1
4.1 Graph of f (n) = n+1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
4.2 Graph of g(n) = sin(πn/10) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81
4.3 Adding F (j, k) for j = 0, . . . , 6, and k = 0, . . . , 4. . . . . . . . 89

5.1 The graph of 1/x2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96


5.2 A convex function. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121

6.1 Graph of 1 + x + sin(x) with lower Riemann sums. . . . . . . 132


6.2 Graph of 1 + x + sin(x) with upper Riemann sums. . . . . . . 133
6.3 Triangle area 1. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135
6.4 Triangle area 2. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 136
6.5 Parabolic area 1. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137
6.6 Parabolic area 2. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139
6.7 A common refinement of partitions. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141
6.8 Graph of tan−1 (x). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155

7.1 Area under f (x) = 1/x. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172


7.2 Two areas under f (x) = 1/x. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173
7.3 Graph of log(x). R. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177
x
7.4 Riemann sum for 1 log(t) dt. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184
Rx
7.5 Midpoint sum for 1 log(t) dt. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 185
Rx
7.6 Tangent Riemann sum for 1 log(t) dt. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186
Rx
7.7 Trapezoidal sum for 1 log(t) dt. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187

8.1 First order Taylor polynomial for ex . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198


8.2 Third order Taylor polynomial for ex . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 199
8.3 Taylor polynomial for cos(x) with center x0 = π/2. . . . . . . 200

9.1 An - tube around f . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220

xiii
Preface

This book is an introduction to real analysis, which might be briefly defined


as the part of mathematics dealing with the theory of calculus and its more
or less immediate extensions. Some of these extensions include infinite series,
differential equations, and numerical analysis. This brief description is accu-
rate, but somewhat misleading, since analysis is a huge subject which has
been developing for more than three hundred years, and has deep connections
with many subjects beyond mathematics, including physics, chemistry, biol-
ogy, engineering, computer science, and even business and some of the social
sciences.
The development of analytic (or coordinate) geometry and then calculus
in the seventeenth century launched a revolution in science and world view.
Within one or two lifetimes scientists developed successful mathematical de-
scriptions of motion, gravitation, and the reaction of objects to various forces.
The orbits of planets and comets could be predicted, tides explained, artillery
shell trajectories optimized. Subsequent developments built on this founda-
tion include the quantitative descriptions of fluid motion and heat flow. The
ability to give many new and interesting quantitatively accurate predictions
seems to have altered the way people conceived the world. What could be
predicted might well be controlled.
During this initial period of somewhat over one hundred years, the foun-
dations of calculus were understood on a largely intuitive basis. This seemed
adequate for handling the physical problems of the day, and the very suc-
cesses of the theory provided a substantial justification for the procedures.
The situation changed considerably in the beginning of the nineteenth cen-
tury. Two landmark events were the systematic use of infinite series of sines
and cosines by Fourier in his analysis of heat flow, and the use of complex
numbers and complex valued functions of a complex variable. Despite their
ability to make powerful and accurate predictions of physical phenomenon,
these tools were difficult to understand intuitively. Particularly in the area of
Fourier series, some nonsensical results resulted from reasonable operations.
The resolution of these problems took decades of effort, and involved a careful
reexamination of the foundations of calculus. The ancient Greek treatment of
geometry, with its explicit axioms, careful definitions, and emphasis on proof
as a reliable foundation for reasoning, was used successfully as a model for the
development of analysis.
A modern course in analysis usually presents the material in an efficient but
austere manner. The student is plunged into a new mathematical environment,

xv
xvi Preface

replete with definitions, axioms, powerful abstractions, and an overriding em-


phasis on formal proof. Those students able to find their way in these new
surroundings are rewarded with greatly increased sophistication, particularly
in their ability to reason effectively about mathematics and its applications to
such fields as physics, engineering and scientific computation. Unfortunately,
the standard approach often produces large numbers of casualties, students
with a solid aptitude for mathematics who are discouraged by the difficulties,
or who emerge with only a vague impression of a theoretical treatment whose
importance is accepted as a matter of faith.
This text is intended to remedy some of the drawbacks in the treatment of
analysis, while providing the necessary transition from a view of mathematics
focused on calculations to a view of mathematics where proofs have the central
position. Our goal is to provide students with a basic understanding of analysis
as they might need it to solve typical problems of science or engineering, or
to explain calculus to a high school class. The treatment is designed to be
rewarding for the many students who will never take another class in analysis,
while also providing a solid foundation for those students who will continue
in the ”standard” analysis sequence.
1
Real numbers and mathematical proofs

Simple facts of arithmetic or geometry are often tested by common experience.


If you throw six nuts into a basket, and then add ten more, you get the same
total as if ten went in first, followed by six. The commutativity of addition is
thus testable in a meaningful way.
The same cannot be said for many of the results of mathematics. What
direct experience suggests that there are infinitely many prime numbers, or
that the square root of two is not the quotient of two integers? Is the scarcity
of solutions to the equation

xn + y n = z n

convincing evidence that this equation has no positive integer solutions if n is


an integer bigger than 2?
Experience can also mislead. We can easily see 6 nuts, but finding −5 nuts
is more challenging; even professional mathematicians had trouble with neg-
ative numbers through the eighteenth century [5, p. 592-3]. Familiarity with
integers, rational numbers, and a geometric understanding of real numbers as
lengths makes it hard to believe that there is a number whose square is −1.
How then do we develop sound mathematical reasoning? Statements, ideas,
or algorithms need not be valid simply because they are phrased in a precise
way, have been tested in a few cases, or appeal to common intuition. In times
past experts believed that every length could be represented as the ratio of two
integers, and that squares of numbers are necessarily greater than or equal to
0. Brilliant minds believed, along with most calculus students, that except for
isolated exceptional points, all functions have derivatives of all orders at every
point. Even professional logicians seemed unwary of the traps in statements
such as “there is a barber in town who shaves someone if and only if they do
not shave themselves.”
The development of a sophisticated system of reliable mathematical think-
ing was one of the greatest achievements of the ancient Greeks. The accom-
plishment had several components. One part was the development of logic, so
that one has a way to construct valid arguments and to analyze arguments to
assess their validity. In addition the Greeks were able to apply these ideas in
the development of geometry, thereby creating a rich mathematical discipline
with numerous applications that could serve as a model for subsequent math-
ematics. Comments on the development of these mathematical ideas may be
found in [5, pp. 45, 50, 58–60, 171–172].

1
2 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

The modern view is that reliable mathematics is the result of a rigor-


ous process emphasizing proofs. A small number of foundational axioms are
accepted as true based on their effectiveness as building blocks, their simplic-
ity, and on extensive experience. The foundational axioms for mathematical
proofs may be judged by our experience and intuition, but in the end it must
be admitted that their truth is assumed. The same is true for the logical pro-
cedures which allow us to generate new results based on the axioms. Based
on the axioms and accepted rules of logic, proofs should consist of a careful
and complete sequence of arguments; each step should either be previously
established, or be a logical consequence of previously established results.
The modern concept of mathematical proof is quite mechanistic. In fact
the ideal is to create a system whereby the validity of any proof can be checked
by a computer, and in principle every proof can be generated by a computer.
This development has gone quite a way beyond the original conception of
the Greeks. It must also be admitted that in practice it is rare to see one of
these ideal mathematical proofs. They tend to be long and tedious, with an
astounding effort required to achieve results of mathematical significance. The
mechanistic view is taken as a guide, but in practice proofs are provided in a
more informal style.
Our treatment of analysis begins with a set of axioms for number systems,
including the real numbers. Elementary arguments give us a first taste of
the use of proofs to extend the axioms to a richer algebraic theory. To avoid
getting hopelessly bogged down in technical details, a considerable amount
of foundational material is assumed to be known in advance. Some of this
material includes properties of sets, functions, the equality predicate =, and
the elementary properties of the integers and rational numbers.
A more extensive discussion of proofs follows this introduction to the alge-
braic properties of the real numbers. The proof by induction method provides
several illustrations of the power of proof techniques. Propositional logic al-
lows us to assess the truth of complex statements based on the truth of simple
constituent parts. This introduction to proof techniques concludes with a dis-
cussion of quantifiers and predicates.
The formal treatment of mathematics, with its emphasis on careful proofs,
is a very cautious and sometimes difficult approach, but the resulting struc-
ture has a durability and reliability rarely matched in other subjects. The
choice of the real numbers as the focus for axiomatic characterization is effi-
cient, but it should be noted that there are alternative treatments which place
the emphasis on the integers and rational numbers. Alternatives which define
real numbers in terms of rational numbers are attractive because they mini-
mize the assumptions at the foundations of mathematics. Such an alternative
development may be found in [7, pp. 1–13] and in [9, pp. 35–45].
Real numbers and mathematical proofs 3

1.1 Real number axioms


1.1.1 Field axioms
The first axioms for the real numbers concern the arithmetic functions ad-
dition + and multiplication ·. These properties of + and · are shared with
the rational numbers and the complex numbers, along with other algebraic
structures. A set F such as the real numbers R, with arithmetic functions +
and ·, is called a field if for any a, b, c ∈ F the following axioms F.1–F.10 hold.

There is an addition function + taking pairs of numbers a, b ∈ F to the


number a + b ∈ F. Properties of addition are

a + b = b + a, (commutativity) (F.1)

(a + b) + c = a + (b + c). (associativity) (F. 2)


There is a number 0 such that

a + 0 = a. (existence of an additive identity) (F.3)

For every number a there is a number b, written (−a), such that

a + b = 0. (existence of an additive inverse) (F.4)

There is a multiplication function · taking pairs of numbers a, b ∈ F to the


number a · b ∈ F. Properties of multiplication are

a · b = b · a, (commutativity) (F.5)

(a · b) · c = a · (b · c). (associativity) (F.6)


There is a number 1 such that
1 6= 0, (F.7)
a · 1 = a. (existence of a multiplicative identity) (F.8)
−1
For every number a 6= 0 there is a number b, written a or 1/a, such that

a · b = 1. (existence of a multiplicative inverse) (F.9)

Finally, there is an axiom describing the interplay of multiplication and


addition.
a · (b + c) = a · b + a · c. (distributive law) (F.10)
Before turning to the order axioms, several consequences of the field ax-
ioms will be developed. These results will hold equally well for real numbers,
rational numbers, complex numbers, and certain other algebraic structures
(see Problem 1.4).
4 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

Proposition 1.1.1. For every a ∈ F,


a · 0 = 0.
Proof. Axioms F.3 and F.10 lead to
a · 0 = a · (0 + 0) = a · 0 + a · 0.
By F.3 and F.4, adding an additive inverse of (a · 0) to both sides gives
0 = a · 0.

The expression −a will be used to denote an additive inverse of a ∈ F.


A multiplicative inverse of a 6= 0 will be denoted a−1 . Both are unique, so
the notation is not misleading. As a first step in answering questions about
uniqueness, consider the uniqueness of the multiplicative identity.
Proposition 1.1.2. Suppose that a, b ∈ F, a 6= 0, and a · b = a. Then b = 1.
Proof. Multiply both sides of a · b = a by a−1 , which exists by F.9. Using the
associativity axiom F.6 for multiplication,
(a−1 · a) · b = 1 · b = b = a−1 · a = 1.

Here is the uniqueness result for multiplicative inverses.


Proposition 1.1.3. Suppose that a, b1 , b2 ∈ F, and a 6= 0. If a · b1 = a and
a · b2 = a, Then b1 = b2 .
Proof. Multiply both sides of a·b1 = a·b2 by b1 . Using the associativity axiom
F.6 for multiplication,
(b1 · a) · b1 = b1 · a · b2 .
Since b1 · a = 1, b1 = b2 .
Proposition 1.1.4. Suppose that a, b ∈ F and a 6= 0. Then there is exactly
one number x ∈ F such that a · x + b = 0.
Proof. For the equation
a·x+b=0
it is easy to find a formula for the solution. First add −b to both sides, ob-
taining
a · x = −b.
Then multiply both sides by a−1 to get
a−1 · a · x = (a−1 · a) · x = 1 · x = x = a−1 · (−b).
Thus there is at most one solution of the equation, and it is simple to check
that a−1 (−b) is a solution.
Real numbers and mathematical proofs 5

The uniqueness of the additive inverse follows from Proposition 1.1.4 by


taking a = 1. If instead b = 0, then Proposition 1.1.4 shows that if the product
x · y of two elements of a field is zero, then at least one factor must be zero.
Proposition 1.1.5. Suppose that x1 , b ∈ F, and x21 = b. If x ∈ F and x2 = b,
then either x = x1 or x = −x1 (or both if x1 = 0).
Proof. First notice that

x21 + x1 · (−x1 ) = x1 · (x1 + (−x1 )) = x1 · 0 = 0,

by the distributive law, so x1 ·(−x1 ) = −x21 . If x2 = b then another application


of the distributive law leads to

(x + x1 ) · (x + (−x1 )) = x2 + (−x21 ) = b − b = 0.

Either x + x1 = 0 or x + (−x1 ) = 0.
As is typical in arithmetic, write b/a for a−1 b, and ab for a · b. In any
field the positive integers can be defined recursively, 2 = 1 + 1, 3 = 2 + 1,
4 = 3 + 1, etc, but, unlike the rationals or reals (see Problem 1.4), some of
these “integers” may not be different from 0. With this caveat in mind, here
is the quadratic formula.
Proposition 1.1.6. (Quadratic formula): Suppose that b, c, x1 ∈ F, and
x1 satisfies the equation
x2 + bx + c = 0. (1.1)
Suppose in addition that 2 6= 0. Then there is a d ∈ F satisfying d2 = b2 − 4c
such that the numbers
−b + d −b − d
x1 = , x2 = ,
2 2
are solutions of (1.1), and every solution x ∈ F is one of these.
Proof. Since 2 6= 0, the number 2 has a multiplicative inverse and 2−1 ·b = b/2
is defined. For x ∈ F,

b b2 b2
(x + )2 = x2 + (2−1 + 2−1 )bx + = x2 + bx + ,
2 2·2 4
and (1.1) is equivalent to

b b2 − 4c
(x + )2 = . (1.2)
2 4
If
d = 2(x1 + b/2),
6 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

then d ∈ F,
b2 − 4c
(d/2)2 = ,
4
and x1 = (−b + d)/2 satisfies (1.2). Similarly, if x2 = (−b − d)/2, then

b
(x2 + )2 = (−d/2)2 = d2 /4 = (b2 − 4c)/4,
2
so x2 also satisfies (1.2).
Finally, if x is any solution of (1.1), then

b b2 − 4c
(x + )2 = = (d/2)2 .
2 4
By Proposition 1.1.5
b d
x+ =± ,
2 2
so x must have the form
b±d
x=− .
2

1.1.2 Order axioms


The existence of an ordering relation ≤ for the field of real numbers is one
of the ways to distinguish it from the field of complex numbers, as well as
many other fields. For instance, in establishing the quadratic formula we had
to worry about the possibility that 2 = 1 + 1 and 0 were the same number.
This will not be the case if F satisfies the order axioms. By definition a field
F is an ordered field if for any a, b, c ∈ F the following axioms O.1–O.6 hold.
There is a relation ≤ satisfying

a ≤ a, (O.1)

a≤b and b ≤ a implies a = b, (O.2)


a ≤ b and b ≤ c implies a ≤ c, (O.3)
either a≤b or b ≤ a, (O.4)
a≤b implies a + c ≤ b + c, (O.5)
0≤a and 0 ≤ b implies 0 ≤ a · b. (O.6)
As additional notation, write a < b if a ≤ b and a 6= b. Also write a ≥ b if
b ≤ a and a > b if b ≤ a and b 6= a.
Proposition 1.1.7. If F is an ordered field and a ≤ 0, then 0 ≤ −a.
Real numbers and mathematical proofs 7

Proof. Add −a and use O.5 to get

0 = a + (−a) ≤ 0 + (−a) = −a.

Proposition 1.1.8. If F is an ordered field, then 0 < 1.


Proof. By O.4 either 0 ≤ 1 or 1 ≤ 0. Let’s show that 0 < 1 in either case.
First suppose 0 ≤ 1. Axiom F.7 says 0 6= 1, so 0 < 1 in this case.
If instead 1 ≤ 0, then 0 ≤ −1 by Proposition 1.1.7. Now by Proposi-
tion 1.1.1
0 = (−1) · (1 + (−1)) = −1 + (−1) · (−1),
and so (−1) · (−1) = 1. By O.6 it then follows that 0 ≤ (−1) · (−1) = 1. Again,
0 6= 1 by F.7, so 0 < 1.

Proposition 1.1.9. Suppose F is an ordered field. If a, b, c ∈ F, a < b, and


b < c, then a < c.
Proof. Axiom O.3 gives a ≤ c, so the case a = c must be ruled out. If a = c,
then by O.5,
a − a = 0 < b − a = b − c.
This gives c − b ≤ 0, and the hypotheses give c − b ≥ 0, so O.2 leads to b = c,
contradicting our assumptions.
Proposition 1.1.10. If F is an ordered field then all positive integers n satisfy
n − 1 < n. In particular n 6= 0.
Proof. Start with 0 < 1, the conclusion of Proposition 1.1.8. Adding 1 to both
sides n − 1 times gives n − 1 < n. The combination of 0 < 1 < · · · < n − 1 < n
and Proposition 1.1.9 gives 0 < n.

It is helpful to establish some facts about multiplication in ordered fields


in addition to O.6.
Proposition 1.1.11. In an ordered field, suppose that 0 ≤ a ≤ b and 0 ≤ c ≤
d. Then 0 ≤ ac ≤ bd.
Proof. The inequality a ≤ b leads to 0 ≤ b − a. Since 0 ≤ c, it follows from
O.6 that
0 ≤ bc − ac,
or
ac ≤ bc.
By the same reasoning,
bc ≤ bd.
8 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

Axioms O.3 and O.6 then give

0 ≤ ac ≤ bd.

Proposition 1.1.12. In the ordered field F, suppose b ≤ 0 ≤ a. Then a·b ≤ 0.


Proof. By Proposition 1.1.7
0 ≤ −b,
so by O.6
0 ≤ a · (−b) = −(a · b).
and
a · b ≤ 0.

Proposition 1.1.13. In an ordered field F, if 0 < a ≤ b, then 0 < 1/b ≤ 1/a.


Proof. Proposition 1.1.12 implies that the product of a positive and negative
number is negative. Since a·a−1 = 1, a−1 > 0, and similarly for b−1 . Applying
O.6 gives
b − a ≥ 0,
a−1 b−1 (b − a) ≥ 0,
a−1 − b−1 ≥ 0
or
a−1 ≥ b−1 .

It is also convenient to be able to compare numbers with integers. For this


we need another order axiom, called the Archimedean Property.

For every a ∈ F there is an integer n such that a ≤ n. (O.7)

Proposition 1.1.14. Suppose F is an ordered field satisfying the Archimedean


property. If a > 0 and b > 0, then there is an integer k such that a ≤ k · b.
Proof. Since b 6= 0, it has a positive multiplicative inverse. For some integer
m then, 0 < b−1 ≤ m. Proposition 1.1.11 yields 1 ≤ b · m. Similarly, if a ≤ n
then
a · 1 ≤ n · m · b,
and we may take k = n · m.
Another consequence of O.7 is used quite often in analysis.
Lemma 1.1.15. In an ordered field satisfying the Archimedean property, sup-
pose a ≥ 0 and a < 1/n for every positive integer n. Then a = 0.
Real numbers and mathematical proofs 9

Proof. The only choices are a = 0 or a > 0. If a > 0 there is an integer n such
that 1/a ≤ n, or a ≥ 1/n. Since this possibility is ruled out by the hypotheses,
a = 0.
The axioms F.1–F.10 and O.1–O.7 discussed so far describe properties
expected for the real numbers. However, these axioms are also satisfied by the
rational numbers. Since our axioms do not distinguish between the rational
and real numbers, but these number systems are distinct, there must be some
properties of the real numbers that have not yet been identified.

1.2 Proofs
The idea of carefully reasoned mathematical proofs dates back to the ancient
Greeks. In rough outline the plan is to present a sequence of statements in
order to reach a correct conclusion. Each statement in the sequence should be
true, and its truth can be established in two ways. First, a statement may be
true because its truth was established before the current proof was started.
Second, a statement may be true because it follows from true statements by
a rule of inference.
Probably the simplest and most familiar examples of such arguments in-
volve algebraic manipulations. As an illustration, consider the proof that the
square of an odd integer is odd. If t is an odd integer, then

t = 2n + 1. s.1

Since both sides are equal, their squares are equal, so

t2 = (2n + 1)(2n + 1). s.2

The distributive law says that for all real numbers x, y, z,

(x + y)z = xz + yz. s.3

Apply this property with x = 2n, y = 1, and z = 2n + 1 to find

t2 = 2n(2n + 1) + (2n + 1) = 2[n(2n + 1) + n] + 1. s.4

If
m = n(2n + 1) + n, s.5
then m is an integer and
t2 = 2m + 1, s.6
which is odd.
10 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

1.2.1 Proof by induction


There is an amusing story from the childhood of the famous mathematical
scientist Carl Friedrich Gauss (1777–1855). His elementary school teacher,
wanting to keep the class busy, assigns the problem of adding the numbers
from 1 to 100. Gauss’s hand goes up more or less instantly, and the correct
answer
(100 × 101)/2 = 10100/2 = 5050
is produced. Actually Gauss is supposed to have solved the more general
problem of finding the sum
n
X n(n + 1)
k = 1 + 2 + 3 + ··· + n = .
2
k=1

This problem has the following elementary solution.

2 × (1 + 2 + 3 + · · · + n)

(1 + 2 + ... + (n − 1) + n)
=
+ (n + (n − 1) + . . . + 2 + 1)
= n(n + 1).
Each vertical sum is n + 1, and there are n such sums.
What about higher powers? For instance you could be planning to build
a pyramid of height n with cubes of stone. At the top you will use 1 cube of
stone. Moving downward, each layer is a square of stones, with the k-th layer
having k × k = k 2 stones. In order to make labor and transportation plans it
will be helpful to know the total number of stones if the height is n, which
amounts to
Xn
k2 .
k=1

There is a simple formula for this sum,


n
X n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
k2 = .
6
k=1

Along with many other problems, the verification of this formula for every
positive integer n can be handled by the technique known as proof by induc-
tion. After introducing proofs by induction, several important applications of
the method are given. The more general problem of finding formulas for the
sums of powers
Xn
km
k=1

is treated in a later chapter.


Real numbers and mathematical proofs 11

Proof by induction is one of the most fundamental methods of proof in


mathematics, and it is particularly common in problems related to discrete
mathematics and computer science. In many cases it is the method for es-
tablishing the validity of a formula, which may have been conjectured based
on a pattern appearing when several examples are worked out. The following
formulas provide a pair of classic illustrations:
n
X n(n + 1)
k = 1 + 2 + ··· + n = , (1.3)
2
k=1

n
X n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
k 2 = 1 + 2 2 + · · · + n2 = . (1.4)
6
k=1

The first formula (1.3) had an elementary noninductive proof, but the
second (1.4) is more of a challenge. Let’s test some cases. If n = 1 then the
sum is 1 and the righthand side is 1 · 2 · 3/6 = 1. If n = 2 then the sum is 5
and the right-hand side is 2 · 3 · 5/6 = 5. The first two cases are fine, but how
can the formula be checked for every positive integer n?
The brilliant induction idea establishes the truth of an infinite sequence of
statements by verifying two things:
(i) that the first statement is true, and
(ii) whenever the n-th statement is true, so is statement n + 1.
Sometimes it is convenient to modify this idea, showing that whenever the
first n statements are true, so is statement n + 1.
Let’s try this out with the list of statements
n
X n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
S(n) : k 2 = 12 + 22 + · · · + n2 = .
6
k=1

As is often the case, verification of the first statement is simple.


1
X 1(2)(3)
k 2 = 12 = 1 = .
6
k=1

Now suppose that n is one of the numbers for which the n-th statement
S(n) is true:
n
X n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
k 2 = 12 + 22 + · · · + n2 = .
6
k=1

The next case is a statement about the sum


n+1
X
k 2 = 12 + 22 + · · · + n2 + (n + 1)2 .
k=1
12 A Concrete Introduction to Analysis

Since the n-th statement is true, we may make use of it.


n+1
X
k 2 = 12 + 22 + · · · + n2 + (n + 1)2
k=1

n(n + 1)(2n + 1)
= [12 + 22 + · · · + n2 ] + (n + 1)2 = + (n + 1)2
6
n(2n + 1) 6(n + 1) (n + 1)(n + 2)(2n + 3)
= (n + 1)[ + ]= ,
6 6 6
since the identity n(2n + 1) + 6(n + 1) = (n + 2)(2n + 3) is easily checked.
This shows that if S(n) is true, then so is the statement
n+1
X (n + 1)(n + 2)(2n + 3)
S(n + 1) : k 2 = 12 + 22 + · · · + n2 + (n + 1)2 = .
6
k=1

If the formula (1.4) is true in case n, then it is true in case n + 1. But since
it is true in the case n = 1, it must be true for every positive integer n. Why
does this follow? Suppose some statement S(n) is not true. Then there must
be a smallest positive integer n0 such that the statement S(n0 ) is true, but
S(n0 + 1) is false. This is impossible, since it has been shown that whenever
S(n) is true, so is S(n + 1). The false statement S(n) can’t exist!
The proof by induction method commonly arises in questions about con-
crete mathematical formulas which are clearly either true or false. When trying
to establish the general procedure for proof by induction a bit of care is re-
quired. There are statements which do not have a well defined truth value (T
or F). One example is This statement is false. If the statement is true, then it
is false, and if it is false, then it is true! We shouldn’t run across any of these
self referential statements.
Here are some additional formulas that can be proved by induction.
n−1
X 1 − xn
xk = , x 6= 1.
1−x
k=0

Case n = 1 is
1 − x1
1= .
1−x
Assuming case n is true, it follows that
(n+1)−1 n−1
X X
xk = xk + xn
k=0 k=0

1 − xn 1 − xn + xn (1 − x) 1 − xn+1
= + xn = = , x 6= 1.
1−x 1−x 1−x
It is a bit more challenging to establish the next result, the Binomial
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright
law in the United States and you are located in the United
States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying,
distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works
based on the work as long as all references to Project
Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will
support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting free
access to electronic works by freely sharing Project
Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this
agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms
of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with
its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it
without charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside
the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to
the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying,
displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works
based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The
Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright
status of any work in any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project


Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project
Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed,
viewed, copied or distributed:

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United


States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it
away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg
License included with this eBook or online at
www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United
States, you will have to check the laws of the country where
you are located before using this eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to
anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges.
If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the
phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of
paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use
of the work and the Project Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth
in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and
distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder.
Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™
License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright
holder found at the beginning of this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files
containing a part of this work or any other work associated with
Project Gutenberg™.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute
this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the
Project Gutenberg™ License.

1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if
you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project
Gutenberg™ work in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or
other format used in the official version posted on the official
Project Gutenberg™ website (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at
no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a
means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project
Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™
works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or


providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project


Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different
terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain
permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™
trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3
below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on,
transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright
law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite
these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the
medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,”
such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt
data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other
medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES -


Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in
paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic
work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for
damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU
AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE,
STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH
OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH
1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER
THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR
ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE
OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF
THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If


you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of
receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you
paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you
received the work from. If you received the work on a physical
medium, you must return the medium with your written
explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the
defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu
of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or
entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.
If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund
in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set


forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’,
WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS
OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR
ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this
agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this
agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the
maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable
state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of
this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the


Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless
from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that
arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project
Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or
deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect
you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new
computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of
volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project
Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™
collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In
2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was
created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project
Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your
efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the
Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-
profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the
laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by
the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal
tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax
deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and
your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500


West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact
links and up to date contact information can be found at the
Foundation’s website and official page at
www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission
of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works
that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form
accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated
equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly
important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws


regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of
the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform
and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many
fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not
solicit donations in locations where we have not received written
confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or
determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states


where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know
of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from
donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot


make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations
received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp
our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current


donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a
number of other ways including checks, online payments and
credit card donations. To donate, please visit:
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could
be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose
network of volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several


printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by
copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus,
we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any
particular paper edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new
eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear
about new eBooks.

You might also like