You are on page 1of 42

Children as Tissue Donors Regulatory

Protection Medical Ethics and Practice


Shih-Ning Then
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/children-as-tissue-donors-regulatory-protection-medic
al-ethics-and-practice-shih-ning-then/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Chinese Dream and Practice in Zhejiang Politics Ning


Fang

https://textbookfull.com/product/chinese-dream-and-practice-in-
zhejiang-politics-ning-fang/

The child protection practice manual : training


practitioners how to safeguard children 1st Edition
Fertleman

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-child-protection-practice-
manual-training-practitioners-how-to-safeguard-children-1st-
edition-fertleman/

Utopia in Practice: Bishan Project and Rural


Reconstruction Ou Ning

https://textbookfull.com/product/utopia-in-practice-bishan-
project-and-rural-reconstruction-ou-ning/

Tissue optics light scattering methods and instruments


for medical diagnosis Third Edition Tuchin

https://textbookfull.com/product/tissue-optics-light-scattering-
methods-and-instruments-for-medical-diagnosis-third-edition-
tuchin/
Managing Medical Devices Within a Regulatory Framework
1st Edition Beth Ann Fiedler

https://textbookfull.com/product/managing-medical-devices-within-
a-regulatory-framework-1st-edition-beth-ann-fiedler/

Medical Law and Ethics 6th Edition Jonathan Herring

https://textbookfull.com/product/medical-law-and-ethics-6th-
edition-jonathan-herring/

Medical Ethics and the Elderly 3rd Edition Rai

https://textbookfull.com/product/medical-ethics-and-the-
elderly-3rd-edition-rai/

Security Supervision and Management Theory and Practice


of Asset Protection International Foundation For
Protection Officers (Ifpo)

https://textbookfull.com/product/security-supervision-and-
management-theory-and-practice-of-asset-protection-international-
foundation-for-protection-officers-ifpo/

Health protection principles and practice 1st Edition


Samuel Ghebrehewet

https://textbookfull.com/product/health-protection-principles-
and-practice-1st-edition-samuel-ghebrehewet/
Shih-Ning Then

Children
as Tissue
Donors
Regulatory Protection, Medical Ethics,
and Practice
Children as Tissue Donors
Shih-Ning Then

Children as Tissue Donors


Regulatory Protection, Medical Ethics,
and Practice

123
Shih-Ning Then
Queensland University of Technology
Brisbane, QLD, Australia

ISBN 978-981-13-3046-9 ISBN 978-981-13-3047-6 (eBook)


https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-3047-6

Library of Congress Control Number: 2018958938

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2018


This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part
of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations,
recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission
or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar
methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this
publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from
the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this
book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the
authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or
for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to
jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.
The registered company address is: 152 Beach Road, #21-01/04 Gateway East, Singapore 189721,
Singapore
For Mum and Dad.
Preface

This monograph is the result of research that began almost a decade ago. At that
time, I recall being surprised at how little had been written about children who act
as tissue donors. While the ethical concerns were relatively well articulated, little
consideration had been given to their situation in the legal or regulatory literature.
There was also very little known about how children who had acted as donors fared
in the short or long term. During the course of this research, it has been reassuring
to see more research, from the clinical domain, examining outcomes for donor
children and more professional bodies articulating guidelines or standards con-
cerned with donor children. While more work needs to be done, this demonstrates
an increasing concern for a cohort of children deserving of far more attention than
they have historically received.
This monograph seeks to add to this growing body of knowledge about donor
children. It does this by examining the existing ethical frameworks and providing
an original analysis of the legal and non-legal regulation of children’s participation
as donors across three Western countries. It combines these doctrinal and theo-
retical approaches with insights into clinical practice gained from the results of
qualitative research conducted with health professionals. It is hoped that clinicians,
families and donors, as well as hospital administrators, policy-makers and law
reformers will find this contribution to the literature to be useful in considering how
best to protect donor children’s interests and respect their rights.
There are many people who I wish to thank who have helped me during the life
of this research. To Emeritus Prof. Terry Carney, many thanks for being such a
great mentor. To Prof. Belinda Bennett, Prof. Judy Cashmore, Prof. Ben Mathews,
Assoc. Prof. Gabrielle Appleby and my colleagues at the Australian Centre for
Health Law Research at Queensland University of Technology, thank you for all
the feedback and support over the years.
Thank you to the participants who took part in my qualitative research. Their
perspectives are incredibly valuable in considering what more we can do for donor
children.

vii
viii Preface

Thank you to my parents-in-law, who have helped in so many ways to make this
possible. And to Leon, Theo and Harry, thank you for your ongoing support and
reminding me every day of the truly important things in life. I dedicate this book to
my parents, who have always fostered and supported my love of learning.
It is always challenging to keep up to date in an area where clinical practice is
developing and regulation is changing. However, I have endeavoured to state the
law as it stands as at 1 January 2018.

Brisbane, Australia Shih-Ning Then


Related Publications

This book incorporates material that the author published in the following journal
articles:
Then, Shih-Ning. 2009. The Legality of Tissue Transplants for the Benefit of
Family Members in the UK and Australia: Implications for Saviour Siblings.
Medical Law International 10:23–64.
Then, Shih-Ning, and Gabrielle Appleby. 2010. Tissue Transplantation from
Children: Difficulties in Navigating State and Federal Systems. University of New
South Wales Law Journal 33:305–336.
Then, Shih-Ning. 2011. Young Children as Regenerative Tissue Donors:
Considering the Need for Legal Reform In Light of Divergent Ethical Approaches.
Journal of Law and Medicine 19:172–195.
Then, Shih-Ning. 2015. Pressure placed on paediatric haematopoietic stem cell
donors: Views from health professionals. Journal of Paediatrics and Child Health
51 (12):1182–1187.
Then, Shih-Ning. 2017. Best Interests: The ‘Best’ Way For Courts to Decide if
Young Children Should Act As Bone Marrow Donors? Medical Law International
17 (1–2):3–42.
Then, Shih-Ning, Ian Kerridge, and Michael Marks. 2018. Children as
Allogeneic Haematopoietic Progenitor (Stem) Cell Donors: ethically challenging
and legally complex. Medical Journal of Australia 208 (8):334–337.

ix
Contents

1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 1
Clinical Context . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 2
The HSC Transplant Recipient . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 2
Children as HSC Donors: Interventions and Procedures . . . . . . . . . . 3
Risks and Outcomes for HSC Donors . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 5
Frameworks Informing This Monograph . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 7
The Relevance of Children’s Rights . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 8
Regulation and Its Forms . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 12
Qualitative Research . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 13
Roadmap of the Monograph . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 14
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .......... . . . . . . . . . 15
2 The Ethics of Children Donating Tissue to Another . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
Why the Ethical Unease? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
Vulnerability of the Donor Child . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
Influencing the Discussion: Major Ethical Theories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
The Ethics of Paternalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25
Interests Arising from Family and Intimate Relationships . . . . . . . . . 32
Utilitarian Perspectives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
Recognising the Emerging Autonomy of the Donor Child . . . . . . . . . 44
The Special Role of Medical Professionals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
The Moral Responsibility of Medical Professionals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
3 Ethical Frameworks and Their Influence on Practice . . . . . . . . . . . . 63
The Significance and ‘Status’ of a Child Acting as a Donor . . . . . . . . . 63
Clinical Narratives of Harm—Complexities and Uncertainties . . . . . . . . 66
The Potential for Physical Harm . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
The Potential for Psychological Harm . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68

xi
xii Contents

The Moral Responsibility of Clinicians—Varied Views


on Donor and Recipient Harms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77
The Absence of the Best Interests Standard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78
Reflections on Parental Decision-Making . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
Donor Children Outside the Spotlight of Attention . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80
The ‘Journey’ of Parents and Their Assessment of Risk . . . . . . . . . . 82
Parental Pressure on Child Donors and the ‘Expectation’
that Children Will Donate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 84
The Relevance of the Family Unit . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 86
The Family Unit and Familial Obligation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 86
The ‘Appropriateness’ of Pressure Being Placed on a Child Donor
Within the Family . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87
Managing the Emerging Autonomy of the Child Donor . . . . . . . . . . . . 89
An Expressed Wish to Donate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89
Dealing with a Child’s Objection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
4 Regulation of Child Tissue Donors in the United Kingdom . . . . . . . 99
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
The Role of the HTA . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100
A Note on Children as Organ Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101
Children as Tissue Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102
England and Wales . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102
Scotland . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106
The Role of the Courts and Best Interests . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109
The Relevant Test . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 110
Vulnerable Adult Donor Before the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 114
Child Participation and Best Interests in the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
Representation of Children . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120
Court Use of a Child’s Views . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123
5 Regulation of Child Tissue Donors in Australia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125
Ethical Guidelines . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126
Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 129
A Note on Children as Organ Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 129
Children as Blood Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 130
Donation of Regenerative Tissue . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131
Potential Liability of Medical Practitioners Under the Human
Tissue Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139
Summary of Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141
Contents xiii

Role of the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141


Issues of Jurisdiction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141
Applying the Best Interests Test . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 144
Cases Before the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146
Key Factors in Australia . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 151
Influence of International Law and Children’s Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . 152
Child Participation and Best Interests in the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 158
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 159
6 Regulation of Child Tissue Donors in the United States . . . . . . . . . . 163
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163
Professional Ethical Guidelines . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165
Policy on HSC Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165
Guidance on Living Solid-Organ Donors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 168
Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 170
Role of the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171
Court Applications Prior to Removal of Tissue . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173
Court Applications for Kidney Donation by Children . . . . . . . . . . . . 173
Court Applications for Regenerative Tissue Donation . . . . . . . . . . . . 179
Representation and Participation in the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 184
Taking into Account the Child’s View . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 187
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188
7 Medical Professionals’ Views on Legal and Non-legal
Forms of Regulation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191
Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191
Relationship Between Law and ‘Ethical Practice’ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 192
Law and Ethics as Essential Components or Separate Issues . . . . . . . 192
The Benefits of the Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193
Using Law to Resolve Disputes and Difficult Situations . . . . . . . . . . 194
Assisting Others to Focus on the Donor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195
Benefits Dependent on Knowledge . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 196
Negative Views About the Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197
Law Viewed as Inflexible, Unnecessary, or Out of Date . . . . . . . . . . 197
Wishing to Avoid Engaging with the Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198
Alternatives to Engaging with the Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 199
Clinicians’ Views Regarding Legal Reform . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200
Best Practice: International Guidelines, Policies and Standards . . . . . . . 200
World Medical Association (WMA) and
World Health Organization (WHO) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 201
World Marrow Donor Association (WMDA) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202
Worldwide Network for Blood and Marrow Transplantation
Association (WNBMT) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 203
xiv Contents

International Accreditation Standards—FACT-JACIE Standards . . . . 204


Overview of Guidelines, Policies and Standards . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207
Medical Professionals’ Views Regarding Key Recommendations
in Guidelines, Policies and Standards . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207
Interactions with the Donor Child . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207
Support for the Requirement for Independent
Medical Professionals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209
Support for and Recognition of the Value of a ‘Process’
Focusing on the Donor Child . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213
Medical Professionals’ Views of the Role of Guidelines,
Policies and Standards . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214
Accreditation Standards as Drivers in Practice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217
Influence of Accreditation Standards . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 217
Accreditation Standards Sufficient as Regulation? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 219
Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220
8 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223
Some Proposals to Refocus Attention on Donor Children . . . . . . . . . . . 223
Regulating Donation: Recognising the Value of Donor Focused
Processes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224
Separate Medical Professionals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226
Donor Child Supports . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227
Mechanisms to Ensure the Child’s Voice Is Heard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 228
What the Law Should Require in Relation to Child Donors . . . . . . . . . 229
Cognitively Disabled Children . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
Mature Children . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230
Immature Children . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231
Access to, and Issues in, the Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 232
Applying the Best Interests Test . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233
Concluding Comments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239
Appendix: Qualitative Study Methodology and Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243
Abbreviations

AAP American Academy of Pediatrics


GCSF Granulocyte colony-stimulating factor
HSC Haematopoietic stem cell
HTA Human Tissue Authority
NHMRC National Health and Medical Research Council
PBSC Peripheral blood stem cell
WHO World Health Organization
WMDA World Marrow Donor Association
WNBMT Worldwide Network for Blood and Marrow Transplantation
Association

xv
Chapter 1
Introduction

Every year, thousands of children around the world donate tissue to a family member
in an attempt to cure or treat that other person. Children proposed as donors will
almost always act as haematopoietic stem cell (HSC) donors—sourced from bone
marrow or peripheral blood—and in rare cases may donate an organ such as a kidney.
The great good that can come about through their participation is at the cost of
donor children undergoing physically invasive and unnecessary medical procedures.
The non-therapeutic element of their involvement brings about questions of what is
ethically acceptable and how should children’s involvement be regulated?
A book focusing on the topic of child donors, in particular HSC donors, also seems
timely. With the increase in potential uses and indications for HSC transplant, more
children are likely to be asked to act as donors.1 Recent years have brought about
the emergence of what seems to be more concern for child donors, demonstrated by
a growing body of medical and ethical literature examining effects on children who
donate, and repeated calls for research to improve the paediatric donor experience.2
Mirroring this to some extent has been the growth in professional ethical guidelines
available to clinicians who deal with child donors.3
In light of this increasing focus on the clinical experience and outcomes for
child donors, this book considers another dimension—the regulatory frameworks
at play—as well as addressing ethical issues and examining the perspectives of clin-
icians regarding the role of such regulation. In doing so this book draws upon ethi-
cal discourse, legal and non-legal forms of regulation and the results of qualitative
research to provide a window into the complexities of the situation where a child is
asked to act as a HSC donor for the benefit of another.

1 Grilley (2016), 1.
2 See, for example, Bauk et al. (2013), Pentz et al. (2014), Pelletier et al. (2015), Switzer et al.
(2016).
3 See, for example, Committee on Bioethics (2010), Bitan et al. (2016), van Walraven et al. (2010).

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2018 1


S.-N. Then, Children as Tissue Donors,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-13-3047-6_1
2 1 Introduction

Clinical Context

Before considering the relevant ethical and regulatory issues, it is necessary to briefly
outline the clinical context and current knowledge about paediatric HSC donors. It
should be noted that while there is some discussion of children acting as organ donors
in this book—and it is recognised that the risk profile for children acting as kidney
or liver lobe donors is considerably higher4 —the primary focus of this book is on
the more common situation of a child acting as a HSC donor.
In order for a child to be called upon to act as a tissue donor, their sick sibling
or (less commonly) another sick family member, may suffer from one of a range
of malignant or non-malignant diseases. These include lymphoblastic leukaemia,
myeloid leukaemias, myelodysplastic syndrome, multiple myeloma and severe aplas-
tic anaemia.5 Depending on the disease suffered, HSC transplant may be recom-
mended quickly following diagnosis, or only when other treatment has failed.
Healthy tissue-matched HSC is located in the bone marrow or peripheral blood
stem cells (PBSC) of the donor and provides the source of the potential cure for these
conditions. Healthy siblings are the most likely source of suitable tissue as they have
a 25% chance of immunologically compatibility—that is, being tissue-matched. It
is, however, possible to source matched tissue from elsewhere. Unrelated donations
of bone marrow or cord blood can be sourced from the international network of bone
marrow donor registries (which currently has over 31 million bone marrow donors
or cord blood units registered6 ), and haploidentical transplants are becoming more
prevalent.7 However, where a related donor is available, usually alternatives will not
be sought.8
How often will children be called upon to donate? More than one third of children
who receive a HSC transplant, will receive it from a sibling who is also a child.9
This equates to thousands of children acting as HSC donors globally on an annual
basis.10

The HSC Transplant Recipient

The recipient will usually be a sibling of the donor, and will often also be a child.
In rare cases, the proposed recipient may be a parent, cousin or aunt or uncle. The
process of donation and how the recipient reacts to the transplant are relevant to the
psycho-social impact of donation on a child donor and is briefly described here.

4 Van Asche et al. (2016), 59–60.


5 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 615.
6 World Marrow Donor Association (2017).
7 Moore et al. (2009), 123, Passweg et al. (2017), Chan and Tipoe (2013), 4.
8 Grupp et al. (2006), 415, Bitan et al. (2016), 97, Kisch et al. (2014), 437, Then et al. (2018).
9 Bitan et al. (2016), 97, Passweg et al. (2014), 748, Styczynski et al. (2012).
10 For numbers of child donors in Europe see Passweg et al. (2014), 748, Styczynski et al. (2012),

2935. For specific national numbers, refer to Chaps. 4–6.


Clinical Context 3

In the week prior to receiving a transplant, recipients will receive conditioning


treatment to kill off their existing bone marrow. Following conditioning, if a recipient
is not given a new source of cells relatively quickly via transplant, the consequences
are fatal.
Generally, the overall survival rates for recipients of bone marrow is quite high
(approximately 80%),11 but the chance of cure in individual cases will differ.12 Even
where a recipient lives following transplant, they can suffer significant complications
or experience chronic medical conditions for the rest of their lives.
In the immediate post-transplant phase, a recipient is kept in isolation for a period
of weeks and would not have physical contact with the donor. During this time the
risk of the recipient suffering severe graft versus host disease is the main concern.
As described by Bendorf and Kerridge, in its worst form, severe acute graft versus
host disease can result in a recipient, ‘losing her/his entire skin surface, experiencing
continuous abdominal pain and nausea and passing litres of diarrhea each day’.13
In the long-term, the majority of recipients will experience immunodeficiency and
renal dysfunction.14 The list of medical issues experienced by a minority of recipients
is extensive, including chronic graft versus host disease, cataracts, endocrine dysfunc-
tion, infertility, delayed sexual development, oral and dental problems, psycho-social
stress, secondary malignant neoplasms, cognitive disorders, avascular necrosis and
respiratory dysfunction.15
Despite the burden of these long-term effects, studies show that recipients tend to
experience a good quality of life—with some reporting comparable or better health-
related quality of life than population norms up to eight years following transplant.16

Children as HSC Donors: Interventions and Procedures

A child donor can undergo a number of procedures in order to donate HSC for trans-
plantation. Children will have to undergo tests to determine if they are tissue matched
and if they are suitable to act as a donor. If compatible, they may undergo a bone
marrow harvest (with or without the administration of a growth factor to stimulate
cell production) to obtain the necessary volume of cells. Alternatively, and generally
less likely, is that children may undergo a process known as aphaeresis. Following
both these procedures, the cells taken from the child are naturally regenerated in the
body.

11 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 615, Then et al. (2018), 334.


12 For example, Greenberg et al. (2014), at 246, state that in favorable circumstances the success
rate is 50–70%, whereas in less favourable circumstances the rate is 10–25%.
13 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 617. See also Mohty and Mohty (2011), Table 1.
14 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 616.
15 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 616. For a comprehensive review, see Baker et al. (2010).
16 See Baker et al. (2010), 334. Although the authors note that given the short-term nature of follow

up studies of transplant recipients in these studies, ‘more morbidity and mortality from late effects
may be seen in the near future’.
4 1 Introduction

Tissue-typing and suitability as a donor: In order to determine compatibility,


potential donors must provide blood to be tested. While this preceding step is seen
to be minimally invasive and, in practice, tends to be treated as separate to a tissue
donation, it is recognised that testing for tissue compatibility raises the same ethi-
cal issues as removal of tissue for donation, albeit with a much lower risk profile.
Like the removal of HSC tissue, this step is also considered to be a non-therapeutic
intervention for the benefit of another. However, both in practice, and implicitly in
most legal cases, this medical intervention has been accepted as occurring prior to
the decision regarding donation. There have, however, been calls for this process
to be re-examined, with it being recognised that the outcome of preliminary testing
has major implications for child donors.17 Where a child is tissue-matched, a pre-
donation evaluation is conducted to assess suitability to act as a donor. This includes
medical assessment for conditions which may preclude them acting as a donor and
answering (where the child is old enough) ‘sensitive and confidential questions’
related to sexual practices and drug use.18
Bone marrow harvest: Cells obtained by bone marrow harvest remains the most
common source of cells for transplant.19 A bone marrow harvest conducted on a
child donor usually takes place under general anaesthetic and involves the repeated
insertion of large bore needles into both sides of the hip bones (iliac crests) around
50–300 times.20 Where a donor child is significantly smaller than the recipient, the
child may be given granulocyte colony-stimulating factor (G-CSF) prior to harvest
to stimulate cell production.
Aphaeresis: The process of aphaeresis to obtain PBSC for transplantation has
historically been less common. Use of PBSC was found to be associated with poorer
outcomes and increased mortality for recipients and, as such, was not favoured for a
period of time.21 However, the evidence base is changing in this regard and it therefore
remains relevant, particularly in relation to older children. Generally, donors are
injected with cell stimulating G-CSF in the days leading up to the procedure.22 The
process of aphaeresis involves the donor having venous catheters put in place (usually
in their arms) and blood is taken from their body, passed through a machine—to
separate the relevant cells—and returned to the body via another catheter. In most
children under 12 years of age, a central line (i.e. central vascular access) will likely
be required, which is placed under general anaesthetic.23 In some circumstances,
children may also undergo aphaeresis to obtain lymphocytes for transplantation.
This same procedure is used but no G-CSF needs to be administered prior to the
procedure.

17 Then (2015), 1185–1186, Pentz et al. (2014), e1161–2.


18 Wiener et al. (2007), 47.
19 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2935.
20 Pulsipher et al. (2006), 423, Karakukcu and Unal (2015), 18.
21 Pulsipher et al. (2006), 422, Eapen et al. (2004), Bitan et al. (2016), 98.
22 Karakukcu and Unal (2015), 19.
23 Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394, Karakukcu and Unal (2015), 19.
Clinical Context 5

Risks and Outcomes for HSC Donors

Child donors as a group, have not historically always been subject to processes that
safeguard their physical or psychological interests. Research has shown harvested
volumes of tissue often exceeded current recommended amounts; donors were often
not assessed or treated by independent medical professionals; and physical and psy-
chological follow up for donors has been poor.24 In recent years, increasing concern
over the interests and risks to child donors has manifested in more published research
devoted to this traditionally overlooked group of children. The majority of this work
has been led by clinicians and associated health care professionals and, while this
section does not purport to provide an in depth review of our existing knowledge
about child donors, reference is made to some of these studies.
In terms of known physical risks, the major risk associated with donation comes
with the need for children to undergo general anaesthetic. Complications of anaes-
thesia involve vomiting, sore throat, decreased blood pressure and abnormal heart
rate.25 However, other serious complications including nerve, bone or tissue injury
can occur.26
Infection at the site of the harvest can result and other common short-term effects
include fatigue, low back pain, headaches, nausea, difficulty walking, problems sleep-
ing and bleeding problems.27 Pain at the harvest site is usually experienced for a day,
although can last for up to five days in some children.28 Rarely, long-term chronic
pain at the harvest site has been reported. Some children may become anaemic and
in some cases a blood transfusion may be needed.29 Sometimes iron supplements
may be given to donor children.30 Usually children donating bone marrow will stay
in hospital for one day.
Children who undergo aphaeresis are also in danger of suffering from a range of
adverse physical outcomes. Where a general anaesthetic is needed to place a central
line, the same risks associated with undergoing a general anaesthetic (described
above) apply to those children. Complications can arise from the central venous
catheter and pain is often experienced at the site of the line.31 Some donors experience
low calcium levels (hypocalcemia) during aphaeresis. The main risks associated with
aphaeresis relate to the need to use G-CSF to increase the level of cells in the donor’s
body prior to the procedure.
Cell stimulating G-CSF is usually administered prior to aphaeresis to collect
PBSC and is sometimes used prior to bone marrow harvests where the donor is
much smaller than the recipient. The use of this is, however, associated with certain

24 O’Donnell et al. (2010), van Walraven et al. (2013), 44.


25 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2938.
26 Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394.
27 Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394, Then et al. (2018), 334.
28 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2939.
29 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2937–8, Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394.
30 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2938.
31 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2939, Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394, Then et al. (2018), 334.
6 1 Introduction

adverse outcomes and some uncertainty exists as to long-term effects on healthy


children.
G-CSF is administered via injections daily in the four or five days preceding
aphaeresis. These injections can cause muscle or bone pain, headaches, abdominal
or back pain, fatigue, light-headedness, uveitis, sleeping problems and difficulty
walking.32 Severe adverse events such as splenic rupture have been reported in adults,
but not children.33
The main issue associated with use of G-CSF is the unknown long-term impact
it may have on children.34 As described by the American Academy of Pediatrics
(AAP):
Although most G-CSF effects are thought to be transient and self-limited, preliminary data
suggest that G-CSF affects not only myeloid cells but also chromosomal integrity and gene
expression. There is also the theoretic risk of potentially increasing the long-term risk of
leukemia, but to date, no clinical data support this concern.35
While the existing evidence suggests this may not be an issue of concern,36 unsur-
prisingly, there has been a call for more research on the long-term effects of G-CSF
in healthy donors.37
A further issue worthy of attention is that research shows that some risks materi-
alise more in younger, smaller donors than in other children. For example, the risks
of cardiovascular complications and anaemia from bone marrow harvest were found
to be highest in smaller children where the donor-recipient weight difference was
greatest.38 Smaller donors are also more likely to need to undergo blood transfusions
and be subject to multiple harvests.39 Data from Europe shows that over a four year
period ending in 2009, 453 children acted as regenerative tissue donors across 38
hospitals.40 Of those, 58 children were less than four years old with the youngest
being 0.7 years old. Literature is also available which shows that, at least in the
United States in 1996, the vast majority of transplant centres would be willing to
harvest from a child less than six months old.41
The evidence base regarding psychological outcomes for child donors is grow-
ing, but remains limited.42 Small scale studies have shown that former child donors
reported a wish to have more information, more emotional support and a greater

32 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2939, Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394, Then et al. (2018), 334.
33 Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394.
34 Bendorf and Kerridge (2011), 616.
35 Committee on Bioethics (2010), 394.
36 Karakukcu and Unal (2015), 20.
37 Pentz (2006), Styczynski et al. (2012), 2941.
38 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2938.
39 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2937, 2939. See also Pulsipher (2012), Pereira et al. (2017).
40 Styczynski et al. (2012), 2937.
41 Chan et al. (1996), 645–6.
42 See, for example, Wiener et al. (2007), Bauk et al. (2013). See also recent studies analyzing

different aspects of the child donor experience: van Walraven et al. (2013), D’Auria et al. (2015),
Hutt et al. (2015), Elfer (2017).
Clinical Context 7

role in decision-making.43 Such findings would be consistent with what adult donors
experience.44 Some child donors have reported feelings of being pressured or coerced
into acting without any choice,45 whereas other studies found donors considered there
was ‘no decision’ to be made, such was their immediate reaction to knowing they
could act as a donor.46
One larger study found that approximately 20% of paediatric donors scored poorly
on a health-related quality of life measurement, both before and up to one year fol-
lowing donation.47 That study found that younger children (between five and seven
years) were the most vulnerable. Studies have also shown parents overestimating
their donor child’s health-related quality of life and not appreciating the complex
emotional responses experienced by donors.48 Some have suggested that psycholog-
ical support for child donors both in the immediate and long term is required.49
Many of these studies have limitations, for example, limited sample size and
exclusion of donors where the recipient has passed away. While most of these studies
pose more questions than answers, some of these reported issues point the way to
improvements in processes for donor children that are discussed in this book.
Repeated calls have been made for further research in this area in an attempt to
advance the evidence base for designing more appropriate interventions for donors
and their families.50 This book adds to these calls by shedding light on clinical
perspectives and the role of regulation. It is suggested that consideration of more
appropriate regulation is another way to safeguard the interests of donor children.

Frameworks Informing This Monograph

A number of intersecting principles and perspectives guide the discussion in this


book. The concepts of ‘best interests’ and ‘rights to participation’ of children have
equivalents in the legal and ethical spheres and are key to the discussion that takes
place throughout this book. Underpinning the importance of these concepts is the
recognition that children are bearers of certain rights. The approach of this book
is to accept that children are both morally entitled and legally recognised (through
international law) as being rights holders. This perspective shapes the discussion of
how children who are proposed as or who act as donors should be treated.

43 Bauk et al. (2013), 241, D’Auria et al. (2015), 452.


44 Garcia et al. (2013).
45 See Garcia et al. (2013), 1048, Then (2015).
46 Pentz et al. (2014), e1159–60.
47 Switzer et al. (2016), 169.
48 Switzer et al. (2017), 2–3, Hutt et al. (2015), 1341.
49 Switzer et al. (2016), 170, Hutt et al. (2015), 1341, Pelletier et al. (2015), 738.
50 See, for example, Hutt et al. (2015), Bauk et al. (2013), Garcia et al. (2013), Pentz et al. (2014),

Pelletier et al. (2015), D’Auria et al. (2015), Weaver et al. (2015), Switzer et al. (2016), Switzer
et al. (2017), Derrington and Essner (2016).
8 1 Introduction

The Relevance of Children’s Rights

When looking at the child donor, the rights of such a child must be considered.
While philosophers have argued about the nature of rights and whether children can
be genuine rights holders, this book takes the view that children can, and do, possess
rights.51
The rights discussed in this book are a subset of human rights—i.e. human rights
attributable to children. In discussing these rights, it is recognised that while these
rights may be protected by law, this is not the only way that rights can be recognized
and respected.52 Sometimes non-legal means of regulation can be more effective at
respecting rights, and this is certainly arguably in the clinical ethical setting. This
accords with Sen’s view:
Human rights can be seen as primarily ethical demands. They are not principally ‘legal’…
commands. Even though human rights can, and often do, inspire legislation, this is a further
fact, rather than a constitutive characteristic of human rights.53

In terms of decision-making for children, the main theoretical divide has been
between a paternalistic welfarist perspective versus a children’s rights perspective.
However, as noted by Choudhry and Herring, ‘in many cases a welfare and rights
perspective will produce the same result’.54 Rather what distinguishes the approaches
is the view of who should be the primary decision-maker and the level of participation
of a child in the decision-making process.55 The welfarist is likely to accept that
parents and/or the court is always the proper decision-maker for a child. This view
is rejected by a children’s right advocate who will look to the child him or herself,
when competent, or the most appropriate surrogate decision-maker when they are
not, but recognizing that even non-competent children have a right to participate.
This book accepts that a children’s rights perspective should guide regulation and
action in this context.
At an international level the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child
(‘Convention’) provides an authoritative statement of what these rights include and
member States’ obligations towards children.56 Having achieved nearly universal
ratification by member states (with the notable exception of the United States), it
is arguable that some of the articulated rights are on their way to being accepted as
having the status of customary international law. The influence of the Convention at
national levels is discussed in later chapters.
In relation to children who are proposed as and who act as tissue donors there are
a range of potentially relevant rights that could be discussed in this context—e.g. the

51 Fordiscussion of children’s rights generally see, Eekelaar (1986, 1992), Freeman (1992), Fortin
(2009).
52 Choudhry and Herring (2010), 99.
53 Sen (2004), 319.
54 Choudhry and Herring (2010), 112.
55 Choudhry and Herring (2010), 112.
56 United Nations (1989).
Frameworks Informing This Monograph 9

right to protection from harm (art 19), and the right to privacy and noninterference
with family (art 16). While it is accepted that these rights may be relevant, the
focus of this book is on the two rights that correspond with articles 3 and 12 of
the Convention, namely, the right for a child to have his or her best interests taken
as a primary consideration (art 3) and the right of the child to be heard (art 12).
These rights constitute two of the four ‘general principles’ of the Convention that
establish rights in of themselves, but are also considered in the interpretation and
implementation of all other rights.57

Best Interests

Best interests is a concept with foundations in both ethical discourse and legal princi-
ple. The existence of a best interests standard to guide decision-making on behalf of
those considered vulnerable in our societies predates the existence of the Convention.
In the Convention itself, article 3(1) relevantly states:
In all actions concerning children, whether undertaken by public or private social welfare
institutions, courts of law, administrative authorities or legislative bodies, the best interests
of the child shall be a primary consideration.

The content that needs to be assessed in applying this standard, that by its very
nature is paternalistic, is likely to differ for each child and each decision that needs
to be made. As discussed in Chap. 2, while the standard can be viewed positively
as ‘flexible and adaptable’58 it equally suffers from criticisms of being vague and
unpredictable.59
Despite the criticisms, the best interests standard remains the mainstream ethi-
cal and legal justification for medical decision-making on behalf of children. It is
accepted that this standard remains relevant and is an appropriate legal standard for
courts within a children’s rights framework.60 How this plays out in practice, and how
the courts apply this standard in child donation cases is explored further in this book.
In Chap. 2 the ethical basis of best interests is discussed, Chaps. 4–6 discusses how
the best interests legal standard has been utilized in the United Kingdom, Australia
and the United States and Chap. 3 gives an insight into how health professionals
view it in the context of caring for donor children.

The Right of a Child to Participate

When we talk of a child’s right to participation as a donor we are, of course, referring


to more than just the act of them providing tissue for another. Participation in this

57 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2009), 3.


58 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2013), 9.
59 See Section “Criticism and Problems in the Context of Tissue Donation” in Chap. 2 The Ethics

of Children Donating Tissue to Another.


60 Then (2017).
10 1 Introduction

respect refers to not only a child’s right to be informed, voice views, and be listened
to, but also arguably extends—in some cases—to making the actual decision to act
as a donor. The way this is expressed in article 12 of the Convention is:
1. States Parties shall assure to the child who is capable of forming his or her own views the
right to express those views freely in all matters affecting the child, the views of the child
being given due weight in accordance with the age and maturity of the child.
2. For this purpose, the child shall in particular be provided the opportunity to be heard in
any judicial and administrative proceedings affecting the child, either directly, or through a
representative or an appropriate body, in a manner consistent with the procedural rules of
national law.61

Participation takes numerous forms depending on the age, understanding and


communication abilities of the child in question. It is clear that varying levels of
cognitive development amongst children as they grow from infants to young adults
mean that the extent to which they participate, and what participation means, will dif-
fer. For younger children, respect for their rights to participation in decision-making
may take the form of provision of age appropriate information and seeking their
views and providing appropriate ways for them to convey their views, and explain-
ing reasons for decisions. Fortin rightly suggests that, ‘[m]aking choices requires
very different skills and maturity from those required for taking part in a consul-
tation process’.62 As children mature, more and more attention should be given to
their views in the decision-making process—a point clearly made in article 12(1).63
Of course, at some point, when a child achieves sufficient maturity to be considered
competent, decision-making autonomy—with supports, if necessary (in the form of
appropriate information, the opportunity to have questions answered, time to con-
sider the options, the opportunity to speak to relevant people, etc.)—should be passed
to the child. This is consistent with interpretations of the Convention allowing mature
child to independently provide consent to medical interventions.64
For a proposed child donor, participation by that child is necessary at multiple
stages. In the medical arena, there are clinical appointments to attend and medical
decisions to be made. While good medical practice guidelines suggest that all chil-
dren should participate in medical decision-making processes to an age appropriate
level, in practice including in the donation context, this may not always occur.65
In some cases, judicial guidance is sought and children can become the subject of
court applications about whether they ought to donate.66 In this context, while laws
can direct that courts should take into account a child’s views in making a decision,
the extent that such directions are followed depends, in part, on whether a child

61 The Committee notes that the implementation of article 12 has been broadly conceptualised as

‘participation’, despite the absence of the term in article 12 itself: United Nations Committee on
the Rights of the Child (2009), 3.
62 Fortin (2009), 299.
63 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2009), 8–9.
64 Tobin (2012), 147.
65 Stegenga et al. (2018), Kilkelly and Donnelly (2011), Donnelly and Kilkelly (2011).
66 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2009), 9–10.
Frameworks Informing This Monograph 11

has effective ways of conveying their views to relevant parties. This can be particu-
larly problematic in the court setting.67 How children of varying ages and cognitive
capacities are given the opportunity to participate in these vastly different arenas of
medicine and law is discussed in more detail in Chaps. 4–6.

The Interrelationship Between Best Interests and Participation

While there has sometimes been a dichotomous approach to use of the welfarist best
interests approach as compared with a ‘rights-based approach’, these two perspec-
tives can, and do, exist under the Convention framework. Snelling’s suggestion that
‘rights-based reasoning should inform a best-interest analysis’68 is largely consistent
with how the Committee has interpreted the interaction of the right to express a view
and participate under article 12 and the operation of the best interest standard in
article 3.69
The Committee States:
There is no tension between articles 3 and 12, only a complementary role of the two general
principles: one establishes the objective of achieving the best interest of the child and the
other provides the methodology for reaching the goal of hearing… the child… In fact, there
can be no correct application of article 3 if the components of article 12 are not respected.
Likewise, article 3 reinforces the functionality of article 12, facilitating the essential role of
children in all decisions affecting their lives.70

In considering the work of these rights for children as tissue donors, Brennan’s
views—of a gradualist approach to viewing children’s rights—is adopted. She sug-
gests that: ‘children move gradually from having their rights primarily protect their
interests to having their rights primarily protect their choices … reflect[ing] the
transition of the child from being a creature whose interests are of moral concern,
and hence deserve the protection of rights, to being a creature who can choose for
herself’.71
This approach proposes that children’s rights initially function to ‘protect their
interests’ when they are very young, but as they mature and develop into autonomous
individuals, rights eventually act to ensure their choices are respected.72 Where chil-
dren are severely cognitively impaired with no change in cognitive capacity over time,
rights are still rightfully attributed to them—but they continue to work to primarily
protect their interests.

67 Fortin(2009), 291.
68 Snelling(2016), 51.
69 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2009), United Nations Committee on the

Rights of the Child (2013).


70 United Nations Committee on the Rights of the Child (2009), 15–16. See also United Nations

Committee on the Rights of the Child (2013), 11, 13.


71 Brennan (2002), 62.
72 Brennan (2002).
12 1 Introduction

Using a gradualist view of children’s rights in which the focus moves from protec-
tion to respect for a child depending on their development and maturity is consistent
with the approach in this book.

Regulation and Its Forms

This work adopts a de-centred view of law as one of a variety of forms of potentially
effective regulation. While the law has traditionally been considered as the tool of
regulation set by the State, it is not the only instrument that can influence or guide
an area of practice.73 Indeed, as recognised by Heimer:
Although law is a very special kind of normative system, it nevertheless must co-exist
with other normative systems. These overlapping normative systems sometimes support or
reinforce each other but at other times are in fierce competition.74

Implicit in adopting this approach is an acceptance that the traditional ‘command-


control’ or ‘deterrent’ model of regulation—that uses sanctions to deter people from
unwanted conduct—is unlikely to be sufficient.75 Legal measures such as these set
minimum standards rather than aspirational best practice standards, which may be
provided by other means (i.e. standards, policies or professional guidelines).76 Par-
ticularly, in the medical context, other studies have shown that use of the ‘command-
control’ model does not necessarily bring about the desired results.77 It is recognised
that ‘legal rules, may fail to shape social practices’.78
This book generally differentiates between ‘legal’ and ‘non-legal’ forms of regu-
lation. These terms fit broadly with the categorisations of ‘rules’ as compared with
‘standards’, as Black explains:
Rules are usually seen as relatively precise formulations: ‘a legal precept attaching a definite
legal consequences to a definite detailed state of fact’. Standards are seen as less precise,
requiring some judgement in their application.79

This explanation fits well with how the law and non-legal standards—in the form
of professional guidelines, policies and standards—are generally viewed.
In this area, regulation of children acting as donors is composed of domestic and
international law, international standards and domestic professional guidelines.
One of the concerns of this book is whether donor children are treated appro-
priately—in being given appropriate protections and respect through regulatory
schemes—and whether a new regulatory response is needed to ensure this.

73 Black (2002).
74 Heimer (2010), 179.
75 Parker and Braithwaite (2003), 130–131.
76 See generally Parker and Braithwaite (2003), 123.
77 See, for example, Magnusson (2002).
78 See generally Parker and Braithwaite (2003), 127.
79 Black (1997), 20.
Qualitative Research 13

Qualitative Research

Chapters 3 and 7 incorporate the results of a qualitative study that was conducted with
health care professionals in Australia. For an overview of the research methodology
adopted, see Appendix A. The rationale for including these results is that it allows
the theory of law and medical ethics to be compared against the ‘reality’ of medical
practice as described by those clinicians.
The approach to this research can be characterised as being from the perspective
of a ‘critical realist’—as the term is described by Maxwell.80 The main features of
such a stance are that:
• ontologically, it is accepted that ‘there is a real world that exists independently of
our perceptions, theories, and constructions’;
• epistemologically, it is recognised that ‘our understanding of the world is
inevitably a construction from our own perspectives and standpoint’; and
• there is ‘no possibility of attaining a single, “correct” understanding of the world’.81
This research will only be able to access and investigate a small part of the ‘real-
ity’ of child donation. Indeed in doing so, a researcher’s own history and values
inevitably shape the outputs of such research. The nature of social research is that
many influences are present and not all are able to be identified through any method
of research. In attempting to access and present knowledge about the topic of child
donors, qualitative methods have been used to provide a ‘thick description’82 of the
views of health professionals on the topics of ethics, regulation and medical practice
relating to child donors. Qualitative interviewing as the main tool of data collection
was used as it is accepted that people’s ‘knowledge, views, understandings, interpre-
tations, experiences and interactions are meaningful properties of the social reality’
worth investigating.83
The qualitative work focuses on ‘how social phenomena and processes operate
or are constituted’.84 While this work attempts to elucidate and explain, to a lim-
ited extent, how and why certain things happen in the context of child donors, these
explanations are not based on the idea that certain variables have a cause-effect rela-
tionship to outcomes.85 This research does not purport to provide definitive answers,
solutions or theories to ‘explain’ the views of health care professionals. Instead it
offers an insight into their perspectives and seeks to offer some limited explanation

80 Maxwell (2012), 3–5. See also generally the description of postpositivist in Lincoln et al. (2011),

98–115.
81 Maxwell (2012), 5.
82 See Ponterotto (2006), 543: ‘Thick description describes observed social actions and assigns
purpose and intentionality to these actions, by way of the researcher’s understanding and clear
description of the context under which the social actions took place. Thick description captures
the thoughts and feelings of participants as well as the often complex web of relationships among
them.’
83 Mason (2002), 63. See also Patton (2002), 21, Kvale (2007), 10–12.
84 Mason (2002), 175.
85 Mason (2002), 175.
14 1 Introduction

as to why certain things tend to occur, or not occur, in medical practice.86 The aim is
to ‘understand the processes, meanings, and local contextual influences involved’ in
relation to child donation.87 The findings presented here must, therefore, be viewed
against this understanding.
Socio-legal research such as this adds much to a mere doctrinal critique, helping to
elucidate the real, lived complexity of the issue and the significance (or lack thereof)
of the regulatory frameworks to those who are pivotal in clinical practice.

Roadmap of the Monograph

In Chap. 2, the ethical theories and principles that underpin the arguments for and
against children acting as tissue donors are discussed. This provides the ethical
foundation for the remainder of the book.
Chapter 3 uses the results of qualitative research to assess whether the ethical
frameworks discussed in Chap. 2 have influenced clinical practice. As discussed
there, the ethical literature often fails to account for the rich complexity and variety
of viewpoints present at the clinical level.
In Chaps. 4–6 the regulation of children acting as tissue donors through legal
and non-legal domestic regulation is examined. The differing regulatory positions in
the United Kingdom (Chap. 4), Australia (Chap. 5) and the United States (Chap. 6)
are discussed. Regulation in these countries is complicated with there often being
an interplay between legal regulation—in the form of legislated schemes and court
cases—and professional ethical guidance. International law also plays a role, with
countries adopting different positions regarding children’s rights to participation in
medical and judicial decision-making. What we see from these chapters is that often
the law governing when a child can act as a donor is complex and unsatisfactory.
Chapter 7 examines the views of clinicians in relation to the role of law and other
form of non-legal regulation. It also discusses a number of international standards
and guidelines that exist separate from the national professional guidelines discussed
in Chaps. 4–6.
Chapter 8 provides a recapitulation of the main findings and considers what can
be done to improve current regulation for the benefit of child donors.
Ultimately, it is argued that the interests of child donors have been forgotten for
too long. Donor children are deserving of attention and, in treating them with respect,
their voices ought to be heard before, during and after the act of donation occurs.

86 In this respect, some ‘causal processes’ (as that term is used by in Maxwell (2012), 35–8) will be

identified in this book from analysis of the fieldwork data. See also Mason (2002), 175.
87 Maxwell (2012), 94.
References 15

References

Baker, K. Scott, Dorine Bresters, and Jane E. Sande. 2010. The Burden of Cure: Long-term Side
Effects Following Hematopoietic Stem Cell Transplantation in Children. Pediatric Clinics of
North America 57: 323–342.
Bauk, Kathryn, Jennifer P. D’Auria, Amber Andrews, and Cammie M. Presler. 2013. The Pediatric
Sibling Donor Experience in Hematopoietic Stem Cell Transplant: An Integrative Review of the
Literature. Journal of Pediatric Nursing 28: 235–242.
Bendorf, Aric, and Ian Kerridge. 2011. Ethical Issues in Bone Marrow Transplantation in Children.
Journal of Paediatrics and Child Health 47: 614–619.
Bitan, M., S.M. Van Walraven, N. Worel, L.M. Ball, J. Styczynski, M. Torrabadella, V. Witt, et al.
2016. Determination of Eligibility in Related Pediatric Hematopoietic Cell Donors: Ethical and
Clinical Considerations. Recommendations from a Working Group of the Worldwide Network for
Blood and Marrow Transplantation Association. Biology of Blood and Marrow Transplantation
22: 96–103.
Black, Julia. 1997. Rules and Regulators. New York: Oxford University Press.
Black, Julia. 2002. Critical Reflections on Regulation. Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 27:
1–46.
Brennan, Samantha. 2002. Children’s Choices or Children’s Interests: Which Do Their Rights
Protect? In The Moral and Political Status of Children, ed. David Archard, and Colin M. Macleod,
23. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chan, Tak Kwong, and George Lim Tipoe. 2013. The Policy Statement of the American Academy
of Pediatrics—Children as Hematopoietic Stem Cell Donors—A Proposal of Modifications for
Application in the UK. BMC Medical Ethics 14: 43.
Chan, Ka Wah, James L. Gajewski, Daniel Supkis Jr., Rebecca D Pentz, Richard E. Champlin, and W
Archie Bleyer. 1996. Use of Minors as Bone Marrow Donors: Current Attitude and Management.
Journal of Pediatrics 128 (5):644–648.
Choudhry, Shazia, and Jonathan Herring. 2010. European Human Rights and Family Law. Oxford:
Hart.
Committee on Bioethics. 2010. Policy Statement—Children as Hematopoietic Stem Cell Donors.
Pediatrics 125: 392–404.
D’Auria, Jennifer P., Tania M. Fitzgerald, Cammie M. Presler, and Kimberley A. Kasow. 2015.
Through the Eyes of Young Sibling Donors: The Hematopoietic Stem Cell Donation Experience.
Journal of Pediatric Nursing 30: 447–453.
Derrington, Sabrina F., and Bonnie S. Essner. 2016. The Complex needs of Pediatric Hematopoietic
Stem Cell Donors and Their Families: Challenges and Opportunities. The Journal of Pediatrics
178: 14–15.
Donnelly, Mary, and Ursula Kilkelly. 2011. Child-Friendly Healthcare: Delivering on the Right to
be Heard. Medical Law Review 19 (1): 27–54.
Eapen, Mary, Mary M. Harowitz, John P. Klein, Richard E. Champlin, Fausto R. Loberiza Jr.,
Olle Ringden, and John E. Wagner. 2004. Higher Mortality after Allogeneic Peripheral-Blood
Transplantation. Journal of Clinical Oncology 22 (24): 7.
Eekelaar, John. 1986. The Emergence of Children’s Rights. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 6:
161–182.
Eekelaar, John. 1992. The Importance of Thinking That Children Have Rights. In Children, Rights
and the Law, ed. Philip Alston, Stephen Parker, and John Seymour, 221–235. Clarendon Press.
Elfer, Jane. 2017. To Investigate the Emotional Impact of Sibling Bone Marrow Donation
(Thesis). http://repository.tavistockandportman.ac.uk/1688/1/Elfer%20-%20Bone%20marrow.
pdf. Accessed 3 Sept 2018.
Fortin, Jane. 2009. Children’s Rights and the Developing Law, 3rd ed. Law in Context Series.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freeman, Michael D.A. 1992. Taking Children’s Rights More Seriously. In Children, Rights and
the Law, ed. Philip Alston, Stephen Parker, and John Seymour, 52–71. Clarendon Press.
16 1 Introduction

Garcia, Maria C., Jeremy R. Chapman, Peter J. Shaw, David J. Gottlieb, Angelique Ralph, Jonathan
C. Craig, and Allison Tong. 2013. Motivations, Experiences, and Perspectives of Bone Marrow
and Peripheral Blood Stem Cell Donors: Thematic Synthesis of Qualitative Studies. Biology of
Blood and Marrow Transplantation 19: 1046–1058.
Greenberg, Rebecca, Michael Campbell, and Linda Wright. 2014. Legal and Ethical Issues in
Child-and Family-Centred Care: Transplantation. In Paediatric Patient and Family-Centred Care:
Ethical and Legal Issues, ed. R. Zlotnik Shaul, 245–267. International Library of Ethics, Law
and New Medicine: Springer.
Grilley, Bambi J. 2016. Ethical Considerations in Pediatric Stem Cell Donation. Biology of Blood
and Marrow Transplantation 22: 1–3.
Grupp, Stephan A., Haydar Frangoul, Donna Wall, Michael A. Pulsipher, John E. Levine, and Kirk
R. Schultz. 2006. Use of G-CSF in Matched Sibling Donor Pediatric Allogeneic Transplantation:
A Consensus Statement from the Children’s Oncology Group (COG) Transplant Discipline Com-
mittee and Pediatric Blood and Marrow Transplant Consortium (PBMTC) Executive Committee.
Pediatric Blood & Cancer 46: 414–421.
Heimer, Carol A. 2010. The Unstable Alliance of Law and Morality. In Handbook of the Sociology
of Morality, ed. Steven Hitlin and Stephen Vaisey, 179–202. New York: Springer.
Hutt, D., M. Nehari, D. Munitz-Shenkar, Y. Alkalay, A. Toren, and B. Bielorai. 2015. Hematopoietic
Stem Cell Donation: Psychological Perspectives of Pediatric Sibling Donors and Their Parents.
Bone Marrow Transplantation 50: 1337–1342.
Karakukcu, Musa, and Ekrem Unal. 2015. Stem Cell Mobilization and Collection from Pediatric
Patients and Healthy Children. Transfusion and Apheresis Science 53: 17–22.
Kilkelly, Ursula, and Mary Donnelly. 2011. Participation in Healthcare: The Views and Experiences
of Children and Young People. International Journal of Children’s Rights 19: 107–125.
Kisch, Annika, Ingrid Bolmsjo, Stig Lenhoff, and Mariette Bengtsson. 2014. Having a Sibling as
Donor: Patient’s Experiences Immediately before Allogeneic Hematopoietic Stem Cell Trans-
plantation. European Journal of Oncology Nursing 18: 436–442.
Kvale, Steinar. 2007. Doing Interviews. London: Sage Publications.
Lincoln, Yvonna S., Susan A. Lynham, and Egon G. Guba. 2011. Paradigmatic Controversies, Con-
tradictions, and Emerging Confluences, Revisted. In The Sage Handbook of Qualitative Research,
ed. Norman K. Denzin, and Yvonna S. Lincoln, 97–128. Thousand Oaks: Sage.
Magnusson, Roger S. 2002. Angels of Death: Exploring the Euthanasia Underground. Melbourne
University Press.
Mason, Jennifer. 2002. Qualitative Researching, 2nd ed. London: Sage.
Maxwell, Joseph A. 2012. A Realist Approach for Qualitative Research. Los Angeles: Sage.
Mohty, B., and M. Mohty. 2011. Long-term Complications and Side Effects after Allogeneic
Hematopoietic Stem Cell Transplantation: An Update. Blood Cancer Journal 1 (4): e16.
Moore, Andrew S., Peter J. Shaw, Andrew R. Hallahan, Tina L. Carter, Tatjana Kilo, Ian Nivison-
Smith, Tracey O. O’Brien, et al. 2009. Haemopoietic Stem Cell Transplantation for Children in
Australia and New Zealand, 1998–2006: A Report on Behalf of the Australasian Bone Marrow
Transplant Recipient Registry and the Australian and New Zealand Children’s Haematology
Oncology Group. Medical Journal of Australia 190: 121–125.
O’Donnell, Paul V., Tanya L. Pedersen, Dennis L. Confer, J. Douglas Rizzo, Michael A. Pulsipher,
David Stroncek, Susan Leitman, and Paolo Anderlini. 2010. Practice Patterns For Evaluation,
Consent, and Care of Related Donors and Recipients at Hematopoietic Cell Transplantation
Centers in the United States. Blood 115 (24): 5097–5101.
Parker, Christine, and John Braithwaite. 2003. Regulation. In The Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies,
ed. Peter Cane and Mark Tushnet, 119–145. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Passweg, J.R., H. Baldomero, C. Peters, H.B. Gaspar, S. Cesaro, P. Dreger, R.F. Duarte, et al. 2014.
Hematopoietic SCT in Europe: Data and Trends in 2012 with Special Consideration of Pediatric
Transplantation. Bone Marrow Transplantation 49: 744–750.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright
law in the United States and you are located in the United
States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying,
distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works
based on the work as long as all references to Project
Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will
support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting free
access to electronic works by freely sharing Project
Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this
agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms
of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with
its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it
without charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside
the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to
the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying,
displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works
based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The
Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright
status of any work in any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project


Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project
Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed,
viewed, copied or distributed:

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United


States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it
away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg
License included with this eBook or online at
www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United
States, you will have to check the laws of the country where
you are located before using this eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to
anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges.
If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the
phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of
paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use
of the work and the Project Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth
in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is


posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and
distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder.
Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™
License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright
holder found at the beginning of this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files
containing a part of this work or any other work associated with
Project Gutenberg™.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute
this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the
Project Gutenberg™ License.

1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if
you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project
Gutenberg™ work in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or
other format used in the official version posted on the official
Project Gutenberg™ website (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at
no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a
means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project
Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™
works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or


providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project


Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different
terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain
permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™
trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3
below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on,
transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright
law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite
these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the
medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,”
such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt
data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other
medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES -


Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in
paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic
work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for
damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU
AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE,
STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH
OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH
1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER
THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR
ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE
OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF
THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If


you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of
receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you
paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you
received the work from. If you received the work on a physical
medium, you must return the medium with your written
explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the
defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu
of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or
entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.
If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund
in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set


forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’,
WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS
OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR
ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this
agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this
agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the
maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable
state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of
this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the


Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless
from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that
arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project
Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or
deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect
you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new
computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of
volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project
Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™
collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In
2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was
created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project
Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your
efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the
Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-
profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the
laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by
the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal
tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax
deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and
your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500


West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact
links and up to date contact information can be found at the
Foundation’s website and official page at
www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission
of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works
that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form
accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated
equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly
important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws


regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of
the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform
and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many
fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not
solicit donations in locations where we have not received written
confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or
determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states


where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know
of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from
donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot


make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations
received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp
our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current


donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a
number of other ways including checks, online payments and
credit card donations. To donate, please visit:
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could
be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose
network of volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several


printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by
copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus,
we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any
particular paper edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new
eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear
about new eBooks.

You might also like